Cover

Introduction: The Dark Tower

 The Dark Tower

 

Burningly it came on me all at once.

This was the place!

Robert Browning, “Childe Roland to the Dark Tower Came ”

Abandon a faith that abhors science. But if your newfound science won’t abide faith you’ve left

one narrow minded path to follow another. It’s possible to delight in both, but it isn’t easy.

Shelves sag with exciting books written for laymen like me, about how the universe began and

functions–cosmology and physics, but most are written by scientist who won’t tolerate faith and

thrill to say so. It’s a heavy obligation to show that in their contra-religious mentality these

scientists are narrowminded. Heavier still for a layman like me--I was a roughneck most of my

life, sweating and freezing night and day, summer, winter on an oil drilling rig, making some

oilman rich. We Starks were an uneducated lot, vagabond oilfield laborers who arrived in

California from Oklahoma in nineteen-fort-one. Only I, of four brothers and three sisters, ever

finished high school. I stayed only because of sports. Even then, I’m less an athlete than most in

my family. Less financially successful than most of them, too. So if I’m dwarfed by my seven

self-educated siblings, I’m a fool to take on scientists of Stephen Hawking’s ilk.

Why pick on Hawking?

Please. I can’t pick on Hawking. I agree with most of what he says that I have sense enough to

understand. Much of it I don’t understand and have no reason to object to. Only in those few

areas where Hawking attacks needlessly (and after at least twenty years, fruitlessly) humanity’s

hopes for meaning do I feel compelled to risk my considerable self esteem. His books are

enormously popular and his ideas influential. So if I’m going to make a fool of myself trying to

defeat the message that ours is an accidental universe, devoid of meaning beyond what physics

describes in theory and mathematics, why not at the expense of someone who is most influential

there, someone whose rich intellect can best afford it?

And a fool I am. Fool enough to hope that some young person reads my story and goes early

where, late, I wish I had gone. Or that my story will allay the fears of someone who yearns to

know how the universe began and functions but is afraid his faith won’t survive the

investigation. Oh, that mine had been one long journey of faith and science that began with

deliberation and, as with a Robert Frost poem, “assume(d) direction with the first line laid

down.” That I could reflect on a body of work like that of Arthur Koestler or Graham Greene,

then top it off with something of an autobiography describing the road I had traveled. Had I

talent enough and time...but I’m short of both. I do have a perspective on life denied Koestler or

Greene–I view reality through the lens of an undistinguished education. Should I have

contemplated suicide, as Graham Greene did, it could never have been on the Oxford campus

that I put the pistol to my head. Only by the good grace and long suffering of York College did I

ever set foot on a college campus, and then, nineteen-fifty-six, only because the new school

needed students lest it be a campus with teachers and no students. They scoured the continent

and came up with some surprisingly brilliant students, and me. I went because they allowed me

to and because I detested going back on that oily drilling rig. And while I would never have had

the courage to put a pistol to my own head, I’m sure there were several of my teachers who

would like to have.

Why do I rake up all this oilfield trash? To emphasize that if physics and cosmology excite a

man like me because they illustrate design in the universe, they can excite you, and should. If

you follow the logic of those many science books that sag the shelves, and not their illogical

prejudices against design, you’ll enjoy the splendor of science and remain as convinced as I am

that the evidence for design in the universe is, if not unassailable, compelling.

Nothing rewards like love. It’s its own reason to exist. The same goes for wonder. Love and

wonder are what humans are made for. But when one is confronted with evidence that makes

him suspect that all he has had faith in is fantasy, then wonder turns to despair. That happened to

me when first I peered through a microscope at fossils washed to surface from the bottom of a

ten-thousand foot oil well. There was no more hiding of the facts from what little faith remained

after a lifetime of sheltering it. No chance of holding Galileo in house arrest. I knew that the

earth was no longer the center of the universe, that fossils existed older than Noah’s flood, that

fifteen-billion years ago the universe deployed in what we call the big bang. No Grand Inquisitor

in my lifetime could stifle that knowledge. One follows for years a weak faith that allows only a

biblical interpretation of the physical universe until one day he suspects that he is arguing more

with God’s evidence than with the scientists who interpret it. Better, engage the evidence early.

Ah, there’s the rub; the rules for engaging God through his physical evidence are the same as

those for engaging him in meditation–ask honest questions, accept honest answers and prepare to

have your perspective changed forever.

There was no point at the end of my wandering where faith suddenly stepped forward like the

priests bearing the ark of the covenant, their feet striking the flowing waters of the Jordan and

halting it and Joshua leading the children of Israel into the promised land. Mine was a journey

like “Child Roland To The Dark Tower Came.” I was not sure I was even on a quest, I had

wandered aimlessly so long. “Burningly it came on me all at once. This was the place,” and I

was dauntless before the dark tower. But I was a battered old man at the end of a quest I began as

a boy. I had not conquered fear; somewhere on the long journey fear became disinterested in me,

shrugged his shoulders and walked away. Go early into science, it will alter your faith, but if this

book is successful it won’t destroy it.

What this book won’t do: It won’t change–does not attempt to change–people whose tragic

experiences in life have robbed them of faith–“If there were a God, how could He have let such

an evil thing happen?” I have nothing but compassion for such people. Not pity, compassion.

God’s existence is not contingent upon our belief in him, nor is he good or evil because we think

he is or is not. If God is good and someone rejects him because their experience in his creation

has been tragic and they can’t believe that a good God would allow such bad things to happen,

then their reasons for rejecting God as evil are good reasons. If God exists and is good, he thrives

in such doubts. But it is the good that drives these doubts. It is not scientific observation and

mathematical calculations. This book is zeroed in on scientific and mathematical calculations

aimed to dissuade people from believing in design in the universe. Physical things are neither

good nor evil, and physical existence is the study of physics. Scientists who argue that it is

impossible that a good god could have created a world riddled with evil should frame their logic

in theological or ethical proofs, not scientific ones.

But this book is not about religion poking holes in science, it is about logic poking holes in the

non-scientific claim against design in the universe. I’m convinced that the universe was

designed. Why it was designed as it is, and why there is evil in it, I do not know. The tsunami in

south Asia, the day after Christmas, two-thousand-four, left me shaking my fist at the heavens

one moment and perplexed the next at why a lotus eater like me, who flees catastrophe, is

privileged to share the same planet with others who rush to it risking their lives to bring relief;

and others who voluntarily leave the wealth and comfort I avidly pursue, to live in squalor so as

to make life less miserable for those who can’t escape it. When in this book I reason from first

cause, which has traditionally been called God, it is not because I aim to sell anyone on religion,

I am not associated with organized religion and have nothing to sell. I am grateful that mine is a

rich niche in time and place, a paradisaical time warp in man’s usual fare of famine, disease, war

and death. I cannot show you how a path back to the beginning will put you at the feet of a

beneficent First Cause of creation. But as I follow logic back to the big bang it leads inevitably to

the yawning question of First Cause and before I know it I have fallen in and can no more escape

than if it were a black hole.

Burningly it came on me all at once.

This was the place!

Robert Browning, “Childe Roland to the Dark Tower Came ”

Abandon a faith that abhors science. But if your newfound science won’t abide faith you’ve left

one narrow minded path to follow another. It’s possible to delight in both, but it isn’t easy.

Shelves sag with exciting books written for laymen like me, about how the universe began and

functions–cosmology and physics, but most are written by scientist who won’t tolerate faith and

thrill to say so. It’s a heavy obligation to show that in their contra-religious mentality these

scientists are narrowminded. Heavier still for a layman like me--I was a roughneck most of my

life, sweating and freezing night and day, summer, winter on an oil drilling rig, making some

oilman rich. We Starks were an uneducated lot, vagabond oilfield laborers who arrived in

California from Oklahoma in nineteen-fort-one. Only I, of four brothers and three sisters, ever

finished high school. I stayed only because of sports. Even then, I’m less an athlete than most in

my family. Less financially successful than most of them, too. So if I’m dwarfed by my seven

self-educated siblings, I’m a fool to take on scientists of Stephen Hawking’s ilk.

Why pick on Hawking?

Please. I can’t pick on Hawking. I agree with most of what he says that I have sense enough to

understand. Much of it I don’t understand and have no reason to object to. Only in those few

areas where Hawking attacks needlessly (and after at least twenty years, fruitlessly) humanity’s

hopes for meaning do I feel compelled to risk my considerable self esteem. His books are

enormously popular and his ideas influential. So if I’m going to make a fool of myself trying to

defeat the message that ours is an accidental universe, devoid of meaning beyond what physics

describes in theory and mathematics, why not at the expense of someone who is most influential

there, someone whose rich intellect can best afford it?

And a fool I am. Fool enough to hope that some young person reads my story and goes early

where, late, I wish I had gone. Or that my story will allay the fears of someone who yearns to

know how the universe began and functions but is afraid his faith won’t survive the

investigation. Oh, that mine had been one long journey of faith and science that began with

deliberation and, as with a Robert Frost poem, “assume(d) direction with the first line laid

down.” That I could reflect on a body of work like that of Arthur Koestler or Graham Greene,

then top it off with something of an autobiography describing the road I had traveled. Had I

talent enough and time...but I’m short of both. I do have a perspective on life denied Koestler or

Greene–I view reality through the lens of an undistinguished education. Should I have

contemplated suicide, as Graham Greene did, it could never have been on the Oxford campus

that I put the pistol to my head. Only by the good grace and long suffering of York College did I

ever set foot on a college campus, and then, nineteen-fifty-six, only because the new school

needed students lest it be a campus with teachers and no students. They scoured the continent

and came up with some surprisingly brilliant students, and me. I went because they allowed me

to and because I detested going back on that oily drilling rig. And while I would never have had

the courage to put a pistol to my own head, I’m sure there were several of my teachers who

would like to have.

Why do I rake up all this oilfield trash? To emphasize that if physics and cosmology excite a

man like me because they illustrate design in the universe, they can excite you, and should. If

you follow the logic of those many science books that sag the shelves, and not their illogical

prejudices against design, you’ll enjoy the splendor of science and remain as convinced as I am

that the evidence for design in the universe is, if not unassailable, compelling.

Nothing rewards like love. It’s its own reason to exist. The same goes for wonder. Love and

wonder are what humans are made for. But when one is confronted with evidence that makes

him suspect that all he has had faith in is fantasy, then wonder turns to despair. That happened to

me when first I peered through a microscope at fossils washed to surface from the bottom of a

ten-thousand foot oil well. There was no more hiding of the facts from what little faith remained

after a lifetime of sheltering it. No chance of holding Galileo in house arrest. I knew that the

earth was no longer the center of the universe, that fossils existed older than Noah’s flood, that

fifteen-billion years ago the universe deployed in what we call the big bang. No Grand Inquisitor

in my lifetime could stifle that knowledge. One follows for years a weak faith that allows only a

biblical interpretation of the physical universe until one day he suspects that he is arguing more

with God’s evidence than with the scientists who interpret it. Better, engage the evidence early.

Ah, there’s the rub; the rules for engaging God through his physical evidence are the same as

those for engaging him in meditation–ask honest questions, accept honest answers and prepare to

have your perspective changed forever.

There was no point at the end of my wandering where faith suddenly stepped forward like the

priests bearing the ark of the covenant, their feet striking the flowing waters of the Jordan and

halting it and Joshua leading the children of Israel into the promised land. Mine was a journey

like “Child Roland To The Dark Tower Came.” I was not sure I was even on a quest, I had

wandered aimlessly so long. “Burningly it came on me all at once. This was the place,” and I

was dauntless before the dark tower. But I was a battered old man at the end of a quest I began as

a boy. I had not conquered fear; somewhere on the long journey fear became disinterested in me,

shrugged his shoulders and walked away. Go early into science, it will alter your faith, but if this

book is successful it won’t destroy it.

What this book won’t do: It won’t change–does not attempt to change–people whose tragic

experiences in life have robbed them of faith–“If there were a God, how could He have let such

an evil thing happen?” I have nothing but compassion for such people. Not pity, compassion.

God’s existence is not contingent upon our belief in him, nor is he good or evil because we think

he is or is not. If God is good and someone rejects him because their experience in his creation

has been tragic and they can’t believe that a good God would allow such bad things to happen,

then their reasons for rejecting God as evil are good reasons. If God exists and is good, he thrives

in such doubts. But it is the good that drives these doubts. It is not scientific observation and

mathematical calculations. This book is zeroed in on scientific and mathematical calculations

aimed to dissuade people from believing in design in the universe. Physical things are neither

good nor evil, and physical existence is the study of physics. Scientists who argue that it is

impossible that a good god could have created a world riddled with evil should frame their logic

in theological or ethical proofs, not scientific ones.

But this book is not about religion poking holes in science, it is about logic poking holes in the

non-scientific claim against design in the universe. I’m convinced that the universe was

designed. Why it was designed as it is, and why there is evil in it, I do not know. The tsunami in

south Asia, the day after Christmas, two-thousand-four, left me shaking my fist at the heavens

one moment and perplexed the next at why a lotus eater like me, who flees catastrophe, is

privileged to share the same planet with others who rush to it risking their lives to bring relief;

and others who voluntarily leave the wealth and comfort I avidly pursue, to live in squalor so as

to make life less miserable for those who can’t escape it. When in this book I reason from first

cause, which has traditionally been called God, it is not because I aim to sell anyone on religion,

I am not associated with organized religion and have nothing to sell. I am grateful that mine is a

rich niche in time and place, a paradisaical time warp in man’s usual fare of famine, disease, war

and death. I cannot show you how a path back to the beginning will put you at the feet of a

beneficent First Cause of creation. But as I follow logic back to the big bang it leads inevitably to

the yawning question of First Cause and before I know it I have fallen in and can no more escape

than if it were a black hole.

Chapter One : “Infinite Fear, Infinite Regress,”

Infinite Fear, Infinite Regress

...the end of things and their beginning are hopelessly hidden from (man) in an impenetrable

secret: he is equally incapable of seeing the Nothing from which he was made, and the Infinite in

which he is swallowed up.

Blaise Pascal, Thoughts

Standing aquiver beside my desk, I was a biblical fundamentalist of the strictest order

confronting a teacher who was describing how life began and evolved to what we see today.

“Where did the water that the amoeba formed in come from?” I asked.

“The earth’s gravity drew oxygen and hydrogen to it and these mixed and became water.”

“Where did the earth that drew the oxygen and hydrogen come from?”

“It began as a gaseous cloud that got closer and closer together until it began to form into a

“Where did the gaseous cloud come from?” And so on, an infinite regress.

“Sit down, Donald, I am your teacher, you are not mine.”

She was, and would have been the following year had my family not followed the old drilling rig

from the gas fields of Rio Vista, California to an oil well two-hundred miles south at Greenfield

and spared me the embarrassment of having to repeat her class. But there was more afoot in the

world of science in nineteen-fifty than a seventh grade teacher trying to sort out how a failing

student had got her in an infinite regress--Einstein was in search of a unified theory, a theory that

would explain everything. I had no knowledge of Einstein’s search in those days, little of

Einstein. I could not have understood the first thing about a unified theory if it were explained to

me. Nor had I the slightest formal concept of such a thing as an infinite regress. But I knew what

infinite fear was. I was silently terrified that one day science would arrive at an explanation for

everything and it wouldn’t be God. That fear dogged me for forty years.

The impulse that moved my argument in the seventh grade, that there must be a first cause for

there to be any following affects, was a natural knee-jerk kind of impulse, had to be. Any

concept demanding brain power was hopeless with me--I was and am a slow learner. But knee-
jerk impulses have served me well over the years. Drilling rig roughnecks keep their fingers and

toes by going with first impulse--if things feel unsafe, they probably are. In my whole oilfield

career I’ve only mangled one finger.

Slow learner that I am, should I come into an apparently empty pool hall and see balls knocking

around on a pool table, I wouldn’t scratch my head and say, now if those balls are moving, either

they moved themselves or something moved them. I’d impulsively look around for a pool

shooter. If there really is no one in the pool hall, a pool hall in California, I’d run into the street

Something set those balls to moving. The logic to ask what is basic--cause and affect. The

process of following cause to affect, cause to affect, until one arrives at a first cause is regressive.

If the trail leads forever back, one cause to another, infinitely, it is an infinite regress.

Plato denied that there was an infinite regress--one must come to a stopping place, he said. His

stopping place was at a first cause -- the soul that moves all things but is moved by no other. This

first cause, a prime moving soul, he called the self moved mover and referred to it as God.

Aristotle went a step beyond his teacher, Plato, and reasoned that a first cause would move only

if he desired or needed something. Since he is complete in himself, desires or needs nothing, he

himself does not move. All things that exist have coexisted with him forever, but only because he

moves them to exist. They need him to exist, he does not need them. He needs nothing, he exists

by necessity, the existence of all other things is contingent upon him. Aristotle called this

Twenty-three-hundred years after Plato and Aristotle, Stephen Hawking, in his book, A Brief

History of Time and subsequent books, sidesteps the term, first cause. He says instead, there was

a time, called the big bang, “when the universe was infinitesimally small and infinitely

dense.”What this infinitely small dense object was that banged time, space and matter into

existence, Hawking never says. Nor does he say what it existed in if not in time and space.

It’s unwise for a person who is no historian to disagree with a history book, but unless one is a

cosmologist with expertise in quantum theory, he’d be a fool to disagree with Stephen

Hawking’s A Brief History of Time. I’ve never claimed to be a historian or a cosmologist with

expertise in quantum theory, and I’ve admitted being a fool. So, with my backside covered by

the assurance that fools have little to lose, I take issue with Stephen Hawking’s book.

Chapter Two : The Smallest Ball

 The Smallest Ball

 

To have squeezed the universe into a ball

To roll it toward some overwhelming question

T. S. Eliot, “The Love Song of J. Alfred Prufrock”

Stephen Hawing’s A Brief History of Time recounts that in 1929, Edwin Hubble made the

observation that wherever you look, galaxies are moving rapidly away from us, just as the

Russian physicist, Alexander Friedmann had predicted they were. Friedman took Einstein’s then

recent theory of relativity more at face value, it seems, than even Einstein did, and accurately

described our universe as expanding evenly in every direction.

Hawking notes that, “Hubble’s observation suggests that there was a time, called the big bang,

when the universe was infinitesimally small and infinitely dense.”1

backward from a universe that is expanding in every direction, one arrives at a starting place

where it was all together before it began to expand. Conceptualize it like this: reverse an air

pump and suck the air out of a basketball and see the basketball collapse. Think of the big bang

in the same way, the universe is sucked in upon itself until gravity makes it, in Hawking’s words,

“infinitesimally small, infinitely dense.” If one comes upon a pool table with balls exploding

from the middle of it, he doesn’t have to be familiar with pool, which I am not, to know that the

balls were originally all together in the middle and something burst them apart.

We may assume the same thing about our expanding universe–probably it originally was tiny

and dense. Good that it began to expand, otherwise time and space would not exist and we would

not exist. But how that original spot came into existence before time and space; what it was

before time and space; and why it deployed into time and space is out of reach for anything but

speculation. Hawking says of the big bang:

At that time...the density of the universe and the curvature of space-time would have been

infinite. Because mathematics cannot really handle infinite numbers, this means that the

general theory of relativity predicts that there is a point in the universe where the theory

itself breaks down. In fact, all our theories of science are formulated on the assumption

that space-time is smooth and nearly flat, so they break down at the big bang singularity2

This singularity, this maybe-something-maybe-nothing, as a foothold, is a quandary for

cosmologists struggling to construct a ladder to the heavens–a unified theory of everything that

tells us what the universe is and perhaps what it was before time and space and why it became

the universe in time and space. Hawking says that in order to predict how the universe should

have started off, one needs laws that hold at the beginning of time. He and Roger Penrose proved

that if the classic theory of relativity is used as the model for how the universe started off, one

arrives at a point of infinite density and infinite curvature of space-time where all the known

laws of science break down–a singularity. But, by the use of quantum mechanics, Hawking says

that one may arrive at a model of how the universe started off and avoid the singularity. His own

personal model of how the universe started out has remained unproven since the nineteen-
eighties, but were it worked out, it is doubtful that it would tell us how the universe started off.

And no theory can tell us why.

Quantum mechanics, hard at work in the minutia all these years, is short sighted. It has a good

vision of the tiny, but can’t see into the distance far enough to make out where the pieces go

when they explode. The general theory of relativity, however, is far sighted. It describes the big

picture but can’t make out the nitty-gritty. The theories need to work together if they are to solve

the “small” that began at the big bang and became the “large” that is the present universe. As of

now they are involved in a family quarrel and are not compatible. Hawking believes that he can

devise a theory that will resolve their disagreement, but such a theory must meet his criteria for

what a good theory is:

In order to talk about the nature of the universe and to discuss questions as to whether it

has a beginning or an end, you have to be clear about what a scientific theory is. I shall

take the simple minded view that a theory is just a model of the universe, or a restricted

part of it, and a set of rules that relate quantities in the model to observation that we

make. It exists only in our minds and does not have any other reality (whatever that might

mean (his parenthesis)). A theory is a good theory if it satisfies two requirements: it must

accurately describe a large class of observations on the basis of a model that contains

only a few arbitrary elements and it must make definite predictions about the results of

future observations3

I lack the expertise to understand the theory of relativity or quantum mechanics. Given a lifetime

to study, I would lack the intellect to understand them. I must rely on scientists to tell me if and

when they resolve the differences between the general theory of relativity and quantum

mechanics. If these difficulties are resolved, Stephen Hawking probably will resolve them. If

someone else does, he has the intellect to understand how they did it. If Stephen Hawking says

the problems are resolved, I trust him to believe that they are. He knows all the theories out

there. Thus far Stephen has said nary a word about a resolution of the difficulties between

quantum mechanics and the general theory of relativity.

He does say, “We don’t yet have a complete and consistent unified theory that combines

quantum mechanics and gravity. But we are fairly certain of some features that such a unified

theory should have.” For clarity and brevity, we will avoid an explanation and description of

these features and just mention that they are Feynman’s sum over histories and Einstein’s idea

that the gravitational field is represented by curved space-time. All attempts to combine the

general theory of relativity with quantum mechanics have, to this day, failed. Should they have

succeeded, here is what Hawking assumes will follow:

When we apply Feynman’s sum over histories to Einstein’s view of gravity, the analogue

of the history of a particle is now a complete curved space-time that represents the history

of the whole universe.4

He concludes on the following page:

There would be no singularities at which the laws of science break down and no edge of

space-time at which one would have to appeal to God or some new law to set the

boundary conditions for space-time. One could say: ‘The boundary conditions of the

universe is that it has no boundary.’ The universe would be completely self-contained and

not affected by anything outside itself. It would neither be created nor destroyed. It would

just BE.5

BE what? Remember, this small dense particle is posited as existing before the big bang,

therefore before the existence of time and space and matter. Absent time, space and matter, there

are no particles to BE, and therefore no “large class of observations” upon which Hawking can

construct a model that makes “definite predictions about the results of future observations.”

Without those observations from which future observations can be made, Hawking’s theory fails

as a good scientific theory.

Hawking posits this infinitesimally small, infinitely dense particle from whence all other

particles – an infinite number of them perhaps – derived, as an analogue of the universe, an

analogy. But nowhere does his tiny ball stop being a tiny ball and become an analogy. He even

gives physical properties to this tiny ball:

Using the no boundary condition, we find that the universe must in fact have started off

with just the minimum possible nonuniformity allowed by the uncertainty principle...

This would lead to the formation of galaxies, stars , and eventually even insignificant

creatures like ourselves.6

Later in this book we shall see how fine tuned this minimum nonuniformity had to be in the first

billionth of a second into the big bang for there ever to be a universe like the one we experience,

but that is not the point of this chapter. Nor is “Insignificant creatures like ourselves.” We’ll

disregard the snub for now, noting only that intelligence is the most marvelous thing in creation,

and Hawking’s theory can’t be a theory that explains everything if it dismisses intelligence as

insignificant.

The point here is that Hawking is describing an analogy as if it were not an analogy at all, but a

thing the analogy was supposed to be like. Given such detailed characteristics of the ball, this is

no analogy, this is what Hawking thinks that infinitely tiny ball really was.

Granting that the non-uniformity necessarily existed in the infinitely small, infinitely dense

analogue of a universe and the analogue was ready to explode into the big bang, what was this

analogue? Stephen Hawking describes it as “finite in size but (does) not have any boundary or

edge.” Of course it is a contradiction to describe something as “infinitesimally small” and

“finite” in size. It can’t be both infinitely small and finitely small at the same time. This is not to

quibble, it is only to ask what Hawking means.

Disregarding this seeming contradiction, we blow up this small particle to see what it looks like:

It’s a sphere, a basketball. That is, an immortal ant could walk forever around a basketball and

come to no boundary or singularity--he would not fall off. This is the example that Hawking

gives of his infinitely small, infinitely dense ball, but instead of a basketball, he describes it as

being like the earth, which he says he traveled round without ever having run into a singularity or

an edge. One cannot conclude from such an analogy that the earth is infinite. I know personally

that basketballs are not, and they fit the same analogy.

Moreover, until this “infinitesimally small, infinitely dense” ball explodes, it does not exist, the

universe does not exist, space and time or space-time does not exist (a note here: “explode” is

inaccurate if one is made to think of bombs and firecrackers. Even though the big bang’s first

three second enlargement makes a detonation of TNT look as if it were in slow motion, its

deployment was near perfect in symmetry). Obviously the ball has not become the universe at

this point, has not deployed in the big bang. The universe that we know exists only in time and

space–it is time and space! But time and space did not come to exist until after the big bang, and

so the universe did not come to exist until after the big bang. Until the big bang, nothing exists.

To talk about any configuration that fits Hawking’s description of “finite in extent...(with no)

boundary or edge,” as if it existed before time and space, is to talk about it as if it existed before

existence, which makes as much sense as to say that because an immortal bug could crawl

around a basketball for eternity, basketballs are infinite.

It is unimportant what precisely the configuration was that Hawking uses the shape of the world

as an analogy of, but it is of utmost importance that it had a configuration. Things have

configuration, non-things don’t. When Hawking talks about that infinitely small, dense particle,

he is talking about something rather than nothing. It makes no sense for an analogue to be

analogous of nothing; no sense for a theory to be a theory about nothing. Keep in mind the

criteria Stephen Hawking says a good theory must conform to: It must describe a few arbitrary

elements, and from those observations, make predictions. “Infinitesimally small, infinitely

dense” describes something that exists. There was a time, he says, when all the galaxies were

together at the same place. What place did they exist in before space; what time before time?

We laymen are not limited by the limits that Hawking places on himself. His science can’t

describe something beyond time and space, and time and space did not exist beyond fourteen

billion years ago. His mathematics meets with a paradox, and mathematics does not deal well

with paradoxes.

But we laymen know how to handle paradoxes without resorting to mathematics. We simply

point to what we see must have happened in reality, and draw logical conclusions. Mathematics

is an indispensable tool, but it can’t explain how something came from nothing or describe how

something can exist forever. Hawking can’t describe this infinitely small dense ball as existing

forever, because forever began fourteen billion years ago for Hawking’s science.

If we are not careful, Hawking will roll that particle into an infinitesimally small, infinitely dense

ball and sneak it by us without our seeing it and asking the bothersome metaphysical question,

“Where’d that come from?”

Of course there was no literal “small” or “dense” before the particle exploded at the big bang--

there was no space before the big bang for “small” to describe, nor matter for “dense” to

describe. Hawking’s usage of “infinitesimal” and “infinite” to describe conditions at or before

the big bang, explodes into a giant complication. If something is infinitely small, it follows that

there is an infinite number of divisions that are smaller than it, and an infinite number of

divisions larger. If it is infinitely dense there are an infinite number of divisions that are denser

than it and an infinite number of divisions less dense. That’s what infinite means.

No one illustrates better the breakdown of mathematics when it meets with the infinite than the

fifth century B.C. E. Greek philosopher, Zeno of Elea. Here is one of his paradoxes: Two runners

are racing around a track; the second runner is gaining on the first. He halves the distance

between himself and the lead runner, then halves the distance again, then halves that distance and

so forth. It is mathematically impossible for the second runner to overtake the lead runner

because however many times the second runner halves the distance between himself and the lead

runner, there will forever be another mathematical number to halve--divide two and you get one;

divide one and you get one-half; divide one-half and you get one-fourth. You can divide forever

and never arrive at a last division between the two runners.

Zeno used that paradox to show some illustrious Pythagorean mathematicians of his day that

their theories and formulas can lead them into absurdities. It’s a lesson that has escaped Stephen

Hawking and modern day scientists. Laymen need have no such problem. We may simply point

out to the Pythagoreans of Zeno’s scorn that the second runner did indeed overtake the first. The

problem lies with the primacy the Pythagoreans attribute to mathematics. For centuries, math

was a religion to the Pythagoreans. They are something of an historical allegory of a tendency in

humanity to put too much faith in scientific systems, the blessings of science not withstanding.

But Zeno’s paradoxical infinite number of mathematical divisions between two points is less a

problem than Hawking’s paradox. The failure of mathematics to describe one runner overtaking

the other is not a denial that in reality the second runner often overtakes the first runner, but a

demonstration of a our inability to describe the infinity of mathematical divisions between the

two. Zeno’s “infinite” is not a difficulty in reality but in math. Stephen Hawking’s difficulty is

not in mathematics but in reality–how describe something as existing either before time and

space, or describe something as coming from nothing? In this case the whole universe as existing

before existence or as coming from nothing.

The only apt description of the universe at or before the big bang is that there is no description,

squeeze it into as small a ball as one wishes. Reduced smaller and smaller it either vanishes into

nothing, and therefore we cannot describe it nor can we attribute to it any power to become

materially existent, or it exists small but materially and in time and space. The universe did not

exist before the big bang, because time and space and matter did not exist before the big bang. It

was nothing and there are no words that can describe nothing, no theories to explain it, no apt

analogy for it. Hawking himself says we cannot talk about events in the universe without the

notions of space and time. Although he does not suggest that space and time existed before the

big bang, he does insists that his little ball did. Until he proves that it did, we are left with all

scientific evidence that says that only after the initial bang was there any tiny particle to balloon

into the universe we know. There was nothing before the big bang, no particles to speed, no

space for a particle to speed in and no time with which to measure a particle’s speed travel.

There was nothing! The kind of nothing that you and I understand as well as any scientist.

Hawking knows a great deal about science and mathematics, but he can’t know more about

nothing than I do; I’m a specialist in nothing.

Were it possible, I would like to trace back one of those billions of particles speeding away from

the big bang, blossoming into the universe; trace them back to that tiny speck in which all of

them a fraction of a second previously were fused and from which they all exploded; then trace

that speck back as gravity shrinks it ever smaller and denser until it arrives at a point that

Stephen Hawking in the Twentieth Century would describe as “infinitesimally” small,

“infinitely” dense. Having gotten that far, I would insist on going further back--back, back, back,

because there are an infinite number of smallers and densers to trace back, and because time also

came into being with the big bang and is a property of it, I have an infinite stretch of duration,

prior to the advent of time, in which to do my tracing. Eventually my pursuit tires me and I

finally ask the question that’s bugging me, “Does this speck get so small that it finally

disappears? finally ceases to exists?”

If it doesn’t arrive at a point where it is small but existent one second, and a second beyond, non-
existent, then it must have existed always. The other alternatives are that it materialized out of

nothing (absurd), or it was created by something that already existed.

For Hawking to describe a configuration of something infinitely small and dense is to describe

something that can only exist as matter in space and time: “small” is contingent on space;

“dense” is contingent on matter, and both are contingent on duration in time. But before the big

bang, nothing existed in space or time because space and time did not exist. Is that small dense

configuration, that Hawking talks about, something or nothing? If time does not exist before the

big bang, which Stephen says it did not, and illustrates how even God could not have created the

universe before time, then in what land before time did this eternal BE just be?

It is necessary, according to Hawking, to know what a good scientific theory is before one can

talk about what the universe is and how it got started. A good theory, he says, “is just a model of

the universe, with rules that relate quantities in the model to observations that we make.” But

does he mean by “model,” or theory, what I mean, or you mean? If we know this, then we can

compare what he expects from a scientific theory and see if it is what we expect from a scientific

theory. I would hope a scientific theory would give me some idea if some power, call it God or

nature, that caused the universe to exist. If the universe did not exist before the big bang, what

was the big bang that caused it to exist? If the universe existed infinitely into the past, I want to

know that. If it exists now, in infinite space, or if it has finite dimensions as my house does, I

want to know. Those are some of the questions I would hope that a scientific model, or theory,

could tell me. My questions have to do with physical existence, they are what a philosopher

would call ontological questions.

Roger Penrose sometimes uses the terms, “good physical”answers in reference to descriptions of

things that mathematics is used to describe. Always, when evaluating a mathematical formula

that represents something other than itself, one must make sure he is not swept away by the

beauty of the formula rather than how well it represents what it is supposed to represent. Penrose

cautions with a question: “What is the physical justification in allowing oneself to be carried

along by the elegance of some mathematical description and then trying to regard that

description as describing a ‘reality?”7What he means by “good physical” I take to mean real in

the sense that physical things are real in a way that mathematics is not real. For instance, 2 + 2

only represents itself as a mathematical formula. Use the formula with apples and you have a

mathematical formula that descries a physical phenomena: 2 apples + 2 apples equals four

apples. Here mathematics is used to describe reality. Penrose is a co-publisher with Hawking of

several books, and he quotes Hawking in regards to scientific descriptions:

I don’t demand that a theory correspond to reality because I don’t know what it is.

Reality is not a quality you can test with a litmus paper. All I’m concerned with is that

the theory should predict the results of measurements.8

On the same page Penrose says that Hawking is one of those “‘positivists’ who have no truck

with ‘wishy-washy’ issues of ontology in any case, claiming to believe that they have no concern

with what is ‘real’ and what is ‘not real.”

The difficulty with Hawking’s procedure is that he may create a theory that is true in

mathematics but false in defining what the physical world is and how the world started off. In

other words, his mathematical formula may give a mathematical description of how the world

started off that is accurate as a mathematical formula, and is real in the sense that mathematics is

real, but which describes nothing that ever happened in material reality. It would not be a lie, it

would just be a mathematical formula that does not relate to space, time and matter. There are

mathematical formulas whose truth is so objectively apparent that no objection can be logically

leveled against them. Hawking’s no boundary theory is not one of them, that is why it remains

unproven after these many years. Objective language (with its limitations as a conveyor of ideas

that are themselves not physical entities) may explain time, space and matter with greater

accuracy than a less objective mathematical formula can explain it. A mathematical formula,

however elegant, does not accurately describe the universe that physically exists. Hawking closes

his book with precisely this point: “Even if there is one possible unified theory, it is just a set of

rules and equations. What is it that breathes fire into the equations and makes a universe for them

to describe?9

Unfortunately, the humility demonstrated in this closing statement is absent in most of A Brief

History. He opens his book by requiring that a theory of cosmology conform to close rules of

science. He closes the book with a confession that mathematics does not answer the crucial

question of reality. And between the opening and closing he makes unwarranted claims for what

his mathematical model, the no boundary little ball, does. Mainly, he claims that it displaces any

need for a creator. That is a pretty hefty ambition for “...just a set of rules and equations.” If his

theory displaces a need for a creator, one would at least expect it to know what creation is; what

reality is. This, however, he says he does not know.

We must not conclude that a mathematical formula whose figures hold throughout, represents

reality or tells us anything about how the universe started out. After all, there are numerous other

mathematical formulas – indeed, as many as there are cosmologists – whose formulas hold, and

yet which differ with Hawking’s. They can’t all be right. That a theory hold in its mathematical

integrity is not a criteria for being a true representation of what is real. It may be objectively true

as mathematics, but false in what it claims it represents in the physical world. To reiterate, in

some instances mathematics may be less adequate to tell what physical reality is and how the

world started off, than language is.

Give Hawking his due, but not more. It is of utmost importance to remember that this no

boundary theory, for all its ambition to displace a creator, remains with those that Brian Greene

characterizes as valiant but non-conclusive.It is unproven.10

Chapter Three : Land before time

Coming Soon!!!

Impressum

Texte: N.Pant
Bildmaterialien: N.Pant
Lektorat: N.Pant
Übersetzung: N.Pant
Tag der Veröffentlichung: 17.08.2015

Alle Rechte vorbehalten

Widmung:
Stephen Hawking

Nächste Seite
Seite 1 /