Inhalt

Cover

Note Pg 1

This Volume,  It Is Presumed By The Author,  Gives What Will

Generally Be Considered Satisfactory Evidence,   Though Not All The

Evidence,   Of What The Common Law Trial By Jury Really Is. In A

Future Volume,  If It Should Be Called For,  It Is Designed To

Corroborate The Grounds Taken In This; Give A Concise View Of The

English Constitution; Show The Unconstitutional Character Of The

Existing Government In England,  And The Unconstitutional Means

By Which The Trial By Jury Has Been Broken Down In Practice; Prove

That,  Neither In England Nor The United States,  Have Legislatures

Ever Been Invested By The People With Any Authority To Impair The

Powers,  Change The Oaths,  Or (With Few Exceptions) Abridge The

Jurisdiction,  Of Juries,  Or Select Jurors On Any Other Than Common

Law Principles; And,  Consequently,  That,  In Both Countries,

Legislation Is Still Constitutionally Subordinate To The Discretion And

Consciences Of Common Law Juries,  In All Cases,  Both Civil And

Criminal,  In Which Juries Sit. The Same Volume Will Probably Also

Discuss Several Political And Legal Questions,  Which Will Naturally

Assume Importance If The Trial By Jury Should Be Reestablished.

 

 

 

 

 

Chapter 1 (The Right Of Juries To Judge Of The Justice Of Laws) Section 1 Pg 2

For More Than Six Hundred Years   That Is,  Since Magna Carta,  In

1215 There Has Been No Clearer Principle Of English Or American

Constitutional Law,  Than That,  In Criminal Cases,  It Is Not Only The

Right And Duty Of Juries To Judge What Are The Facts,  What Is The Law,

And What Was The Moral Intent Of The Accused; But That It Is Also

Their Right,  And Their Primary And Paramount Duty,  To Judge Of The

Justice Of The Law,  And To Hold All Laws Invalid,  That Are,  In Their

Opinion,  Unjust Or Oppressive,  And All Persons Guiltless In Violating,

Or Resisting The Execution Of,  Such Laws.

 

Unless Such Be The Right And Duty Of Jurors,  It Is Plain That,  Instead

Of Juries Being A "Palladium Of Liberty" A Barrier Against The Tyranny

And Oppression Of The Government They Are Really Mere Tools In Its

Hands,  For Carrying Into Execution Any Injustice And Oppression It

May Desire To Have Executed.

 

But For Their Right To Judge Of The Law,  And The Justice Of The Law,

Juries Would Be No Protection To An Accused Person,  Even As To

Matters Of Fact; For,  If The Government Can Dictate To A Jury Any Law

Whatever,  In A Criminal Case,  It Can Certainly Dictate To Them The

Laws Of Evidence. That Is,  It Can Dictate What Evidence Is

Admissible,  And What Inadmissible,  And Also What Force Or Weight

Is To Be Given To The Evidence Admitted. And If The Government Can

Thus Dictate To A Jury The Laws Of Evidence,  It Can Not Only Make It

Necessary For Them To Convict On A Partial Exhibition Of The

Evidence Rightfully Pertaining To The Case,  But It Can Even Require

Them To Convict On Any Evidence Whatever That It Pleases To Offer

Them.

 

That The Rights And Duties Of Jurors Must Necessarily Be Such As Are

Here Claimed For Them,  Will Be Evident When It Is Considered What

The Trial By Jury Is,  And What Is Its Object.

 

"The Trial By Jury," Then,  Is A "Trial By The Country" That Is,  By The

People As Distinguished From A Trial By The Government.

 

It Was Anciently Called "Trial Per Pais"   That Is,  "Trial By The

Country." And Now,  In Every Criminal Trial,  The Jury Are Told That The

Accused "Has,  For Trial,  Put Himself Upon The Country; Which

Country You (The Jury) Are." 

 

The Object Of This Trial "By The Country," Or By The People,  In

Preference To A Trial By The Government,  Is To Guard Against Every

Species Of Oppression By The Government. In Order To Effect This

End,  It Is Indispensable That The People,  Or "The Country," Judge Of

And Determine Their Own Liberties Against The Government; Instead

Of The Government's Judging Of And Determining Its Own Powers

Over The People. How Is It Possible That Juries Can Do Anything To

Protect The Liberties Of The People Against The Government,  If They

Are Not Allowed To Determine What Those Liberties Are?

 

Any Government,  That Is Its Own Judge Of,  And Determines

Authoritatively For The People,  What Are Its Own Powers Over The

People,  Is An Absolute Government Of Course. It Has All The Powers

Chapter 1 (The Right Of Juries To Judge Of The Justice Of Laws) Section 1 Pg 3

That It Chooses To Exercise. There Is No Other Or At Least No More

Accurate Definition Of A Despotism Than This.

 

On The Other Hand,  Any People,  That Judge Of,  And Determine

Authoritatively For The Government,  What Are Their Own Liberties

Against The Government,  Of Course Retain All The Liberties They Wish

To Enjoy. And This Is Freedom. At Least,  It Is Freedom To Them;

Because,  Although It May Be Theoretically Imperfect,  It,

Nevertheless,  Corresponds To Their Highest Notions Of Freedom.

 

To Secure This Right Of The People To Judge Of Their Own Liberties

Against The Government,  The Jurors Are Taken,  (Or Must Be,  To Make

Them Lawful Jurors,} From The Body Of The People,  By Lot,  Or By

Some Process That Precludes Any Previos Knowledge,  Choice,  Or

Selection Of Them,  On The Part Of The Government.

 

This Is Done To Prevent The Government's Constituting A Jury Of Its

Own Partisans Or Friends; In Other Words,  To Prevent The

Government's Packing A Jury,  With A View To Maintain Its Own Laws,

And Accomplish Its Own Purposes.

 

It Is Supposed That,  If Twelve Men Be Taken,  By Lot,  From The Mass Of

The People,  Without The Possibility Of Any Previous Knowledge,

Choice,  Or Selection Of Them,  On The Part Of The Government,  The

Jury Will Be A Fair Epitome Of "The Country" At Large,  And Not Merely

Of The Party Or Faction That Sustain The Measures Of The Government;

That Substantially All Classes Of Opinions,  Prevailing Among The

People,  Will Be Represented In The Jury; And Especially That The

Opponents Of The Government,  (If The Government Have Any

Opponents,) Will Be Represented There,  As Well As Its Friends; That

The Classes,  Who Are Oppressed By The Laws Of The Government,  (If

Any Are Thus Oppressed,) Will Have Their Representatives In The Jury,

As Well As Those Classes,  Who Take Sides With The Oppressor   That Is,

With The Government.

 

It Is Fairly Presumable That Such A Tribunal Will Agree To No

Conviction Except Such As Substantially The Whole Country Would

Agree To,  If They Were Present,  Taking Part In The Trial. A Trial By

Such A Tribunal Is,  Therefore,  In Effect,  "A Trial By The Country." In Its

Results It Probably Comes As Near To A Trial By The Whole Country,  As

Any Trial That It Is Practicable To Have,  Without Too Great

Inconvenience And Expense. And. As Unanimity Is Required For A

Conviction,  It Follows That No One Can Be Convicted,  Except For The

Violation Of Such Laws As Substantially The Whole Country Wish To

Have Maintained. The Government Can Enforce None Of Its Laws,

(By Punishing Offenders,  Through The Verdicts Of Juries,) Except

Such As Substantially The Whole People Wish To Have Enforced. The

Government,  Therefore,  Consistently With The Trial By Jury,  Can

Exercise No Powers Over The People,  (Or,  What Is The Same Thing,

Over The Accused Person,  Who Represents The Rights Of The People,)

Except Such A Substantially The Whole People Of The Country

Consent That It May Exercise. In Such A Trial,  Therefore,  "The

Country," Or The People,  Judge Of And Dtermine Their Own Liberties

Chapter 1 (The Right Of Juries To Judge Of The Justice Of Laws) Section 1 Pg 4

Against The Government,  Instead Of Thegovernment's Judging Of And

Determining Its Own Powers Over The People.

 

But All This "Trial By The Country" Would Be No Trial At All "By The

Country," But Only A Trial By The Government,  If The Government

'Could Either Declare Who May,  And Who May Not,  Be Jurors,  Or

Could Dictate To The Jury Anything Whatever,  Either Of Law Or

Evidence,  That Is Of The Essence Of The Trial.

 

If The Government May Decide Who May,  And Who May Not,  Be

Jurors,  It Will Of Course Select Only Its Partisans,  And Those Friendly

To Its Measures. It May Not Only Prescribe Who May,  And Who May

Not,  Be Eligible To Be Drawn As Jurors; But It May Also Question Each

Person Drawn As A Juror,  As To His Sentiments In Regard To The

Particular Law Involved In Each Trial,  Before Suffering Him To Be

Sworn On The Panel; And Exclude Him If He Be Found Unfavorable To

The Maintenance Of Such A Law. [1]

 

So,  Also,  If The Government May Dictate To The Jury What Laws They

Are To Enforce,  It Is No Longer A " Trial By The Country," But A Trial By

The Government; Because The Jury Then Try The Accused,  Not By Any

Standard Of Their Own   Not By Their Own Judgments Of Their Rightful

Liberties   But By A Standard. Dictated To Them By The Government.

And The Standard,  Thus Dictated By The Government,  Becomes The

Measure Of The People's Liberties. If The Government Dictate The

Standard Of Trial,  It Of Course Dictates The Results Of The Trial. And

Such A Trial Is No Trial By The Country,  But Only A Trial By The

Government; And In It The Government Determines What Are Its Own

Powers Over The People,  Instead Of The People's Determining What

Are Their Own Liberties Against The Government. In Short,  If The Jury

Have No Right To Judge Of The Justice Of A Law Of The Government,

They Plainly Can Do Nothing To Protect The People Against The

Oppressions Of The Government; For There Are No Oppressions Which

The Government May Not Authorize By Law.

 

The Jury Are Also To Judge Whether The Laws Are Rightly Expounded

To Them By The Court. Unless They Judge On This Point,  They Do

Nothing To Protect Their Liberties Against The Oppressions That Are

Capable Of Being Practiced Under Cover Of A Corrupt Exposition Of

The Laws. If The Judiciary Can Authoritatively Dictate To A Jury Any

Exposition Of The Law,  They Can Dictate To Them The Law Itself,  And

Such Laws As They Please; Because Laws Are,  In Practice,  One Thing

Or Another,  According As They Are Expounded.

 

The Jury Must Also Judge Whether There Really Be Any Such Law,  (Be

It Good Or Bad,) As The Accused Is Charged With Having Transgressed.

Unless They Judge On This Point,  The People Are Liable To Have Their

Liberties Taken From Them By Brute Force,  Without Any Law At All.

 

The Jury Must Also Judge Of The Laws Of Evidence. If The

Government Can Dictate To A Jury The Laws Of Evidence,  It Can Not

Only Shut Out Any Evidence It Pleases,  Tending To Vindicate The

Accused,  But It Can Require That Any Evidence Whatever,  That It

Chapter 1 (The Right Of Juries To Judge Of The Justice Of Laws) Section 1 Pg 5

Pleases To Offer,  Be Held As Conclusive Proof Of Any Offence

Whatever Which The Government Chooses To Allege.

 

It Is Manifest,  Therefore,  That The Jury Must Judge Of And Try The

Whole Case,  And Every Part And Parcel Of The Case,  Free Of Any

Dictation Or Authority On The Part Of The Government. They Must

Judge Of The Existence Of The Law; Of The True Exposition Of The Law;

Of The Justice Of The Law; And Of The Admissibility And Weight Of All

The Evidence Offered; Otherwise The Government Will Have

Everything Its Own Way; The Jury Will Be Mere Puppets In The Hands

Of The Government: And The Trial Will Be,  In Reality,  A Trial By The

Government,  And Not A "Trial By The Country." By Such Trials The

Government Will Determine Its Own Powers Over The People,  Instead

Of The People's Determining Their Own Liberties Against The

Government; And It Will Be An Entire Delusion To Talk,  As For

Centuries We Have Done,  Of The Trial By Jury,  As A "Palladium Of

Liberty," Or As Any Protection To The People Against The Oppression

And Tyranny Of The Government.

 

The Question,  Then,  Between Trial By Jury,  As Thus Described,  And

Trial By The Government,  Is Simply A Question Between Liberty And

Despotism. The Authority To Judge What Are The Powers Of The

Government,  And What The Liberties Of The People,  Must Necessarily

Be Vested In One Or The Other Of The Parties Themselves   The

Government,  Or The People; Because There Is No Third Party To Whom

It Can Be Entrusted. If The Authority Be Vested In The Government,

The Governmnt Is Absolute,  And The People Have No Liberties Except

Such As The Government Sees Fit To Indulge Them With. If,  On The

Other Hand,  That Authority Be Vested In The People,  Then The People

Have All Liberties,  (As Against The Government,) Except Suc As

Substantially The Whole People (Through A Jury) Choose To Disclaim;

And The Government Can Exercise No Power Except Such As

Substantially The Whole People (Through A Jury) Consent That It May

Exercise.

Chapter 1 (The Right Of Juries To Judge Of The Justice Of Laws) Section 2 Pg 6

The Force And. Justice Of The Preceding Argument Cannot Be Evaded

By Saying That The Government Is Chosen By The People; That,  In

Theory,  It Represents The People; That It Is Designed To Do The Will Of

The People; That Its Members Are All Sworn To Observe The

Fundamental Or Constitutional Law Instituted By The People; That Its

Acts Are Therefore Entitled To Be Considered The Acts Of The People;

And That To Allow A Jury,  Representing The People,  To Invalidate The

Acts Of The' Government,  Would Therefore Be Arraying The People

Against Themselves.

 

There Are Two Answers To Such An Argument.

 

One Answer Is,  That,  In A Representative Government,  There Is No

Absurdity Or Contradiction,  Nor Any Arraying Of The People Against

Themselves,  In Requiring That The Statutes Or Enactments Of The

Government Shall Pass The Ordeal Of Any Number Of Separate

Tribunals,  Before It Shall Be Determined That They Are To Have The

Chapter 1 (The Right Of Juries To Judge Of The Justice Of Laws) Section 2 Pg 7

Force Of Laws. Our American Constitutions Have Provided Five Of

These Separate Tribunals,  To Wit,  Representatives,  Senate,

Executive,[2] Jury,  And Judges; And Have Made It Necessary That

Each Enactment Shall Pass The Ordeal Of All These Separate Tribunals,

Before Its Authority Can Be Established By The Punishment Of Those

Who Choose To Transgress It. And There Is No More Absurdity Or

Inconsistency In Making A Jury One Of These Several Tribunals,  Than

There Is In Making The Representatives,  Or The Senate,  Or The

Executive,  Or The Judges,  One Of Them. There Is No More Absurdity

In Giving A Jury A Veto Upon The Laws,  Than There Is In Giving A Veto

To Each Of These Other Tribunals. The People Are No More Arrayed

Against Themselves,  When A Jury Puts Its Veto Upon A Statute,  Which

The Other Tribunals Have Sanctioned,  Than They Are When The Same

Veto Is Exercised By The Representatives,  The Senate,  The Executive,

Or The Judges.

 

But Another Answer To The Argument That The People Are Arrayed

Against Themselves,  When A Jury Hold An Enactment Of The

Government Invalid,  Is,  That The Government,  And All The

Departments Of The Government,  Are Merely The Servants And Agents

Of The People; Not Invested With Arbitrary Or Absolute Authority To

Bind The People,  But Required To Submit All Their Enactments To The

Judgment Of A Tribunal More Fairly Representing The Whole People,

Before They Carry Them Into Execution,  By Punishing Any Individual

For Transgressing Them. If The Government Were Not Thus Required To

Submit Their Enactments To The Judgment Of "The Country," Before

Executing Them Upon Individuals   If,  In Other Words,  The People

Had Reserved To Themselves No Veto Upon The Acts Of The

Government,  The Government,  Instead Of Being A Mere Servant And

Agent Of The People,  Would Be An Absolute Despot Over The People.

It Would Have All Power In Its Own Hands; Because The Power To

Punish Carries All Other Powers With It. A Power That Can,  Of Itself,

And By Its Own Authority,  Punish Disobedience,  Can Compel

Obedience And Submission,  And Is Above All Responsibility For The

Character Of Its Laws. In Short,  It Is A Despotism.

 

And It Is Of No Consequence To Inquire How A Government Came By

This Power To Punish,  Whether By Prescription,  By Inheritance,  By

Usurpation. Or By Delegation From The People's If It Have Now But

Got It,  The Government Is Absolute.

 

It Is Plain,  Therefore,  That If The People Have Invested The

Government With Power To Make Laws That Absolutely Bind The

People,  And To Punish The People For Transgressing Those Laws,  The

People Have Surrendered Their Liberties Unreservedly Into The Hands

Of The Government.

 

It Is Of No Avail To Say,  In Answer To This View Of The Ease,  That In

Surrendering Their Liberties Into The Hands Of The Government,  The

People Took An Oath From The Government,  That It Would Exercise Its

Power Within Certain Constitutional Limits; For When Did Oaths Ever

Restrain A Government That Was Otherwise Unrestrained? Orwhen

Did A Government Fail To Determine That All Its Acts Were Within The

Constitutional And Authorized Limits Of Its Power,  If It Were

Chapter 1 (The Right Of Juries To Judge Of The Justice Of Laws) Section 2 Pg 8

Permitted To Determine That Question For Itself?

 

Neither Is It Of Any Avail To Say,  That,  If The Government Abuse Its

Power,  And Enact Unjust And Oppressive Laws,  The Government May

Be Changed By The Influence Of Discussion,  And The Exercise Of The

Right Of Suffrage. Discussion Can Do Nothing To Prevent The

Enactment,  Or Procure The Repeal,  Of Unjust Laws,  Unless It Be

Understood That,  The Discussion Is To Be Followed By Resistance.

Tyrants Care Nothing For Discussions That Are To End Only In

Discussion. Discussions,  Which Do Not Interfere With The

Enforcement Of Their Laws,  Are But Idle Wind To Them. Suffrage Is

Equally Powerless And Unreliable. It Can Be Exercised Only

Periodically; And The Tyranny Must At Least Be Borne Until The Time

For Suffrage Comes. Be Sides,  When The Suffrage Is Exercised,  It

Gives No Guaranty For The Repeal Of Existing Laws That Are

Oppressive,  And No Security Against The Enactment Of New Ones That

Are Equally So. The Second Body Of Legislators Are Liable And Likely

To Be Just As Tyrannical As The First. If It Be Said That The Second

Body May Be Chosen For Their Integrity,  The Answer Is,  That The First

Were Chosen For That Very Reason,  And Yet Proved Tyrants. The

Second Will Be Exposed To The Same Temptations As The First,  And

Will Be Just As Likely To Prove Tyrannical. Who Ever Heard That

Succeeding Legislatures Were,  On The Whole,  More Honest Than Those

That Preceded Them? What Is There In The Nature Of Men Or Things To

Make Them So? If It Be Said That The First Body Were Chosen From

Motives Of Injustice,  That Fact Proves That There Is A Portion Of

Society Who Desire To Establish Injustice; And If They Were Powerful

Or Artful Enough To Procure The Election Of Their Instruments To

Compose The First Legislature,  They Will Be Likely To Be Powerful Or

Artful Enough To Procure The Election Of The Same Or Similar

Instruments To Compose The Second. The Right Of Suffrage,

Therefore,  And Even A Change Of Legislators,  Guarantees No Change

Of Legislation   Certainly No Change For The Better. Even If A Change

For The Better Actually Comes,  T Cmes Too Late,  Because It Comes

Only After More Or Less Injustice Has Been Irreparably Done.

 

But,  At Best,  The Right Of Suffrage Can Be Exercised Only

Periodically; And Between The Periods The Legislators Are Wholly

Irresponsible. No Despot Was Ever More Entirely Irresponsible Than

Are Republican Legislators During The Period For Which They Are

Chosen. They Can Neither,  Be Removed From Their Office,  Nor Called

To Account While In Their Office,  Nor Punished After They Leave Their

Office,  Be Their Tyranny What It May. Moreover,  The Judicial And

Executive Departments Of The Government Are Equally Irresponsible

To The People,  And Are Only Responsible,  (By Impeachment,  And

Dependence For Their Salaries),  To These Irresponsible Legislators.

This Dependence Of The Judiciary And Executive Upon The

Legislature Is A Guaranty That They Will Always Sanction And Execute

Its Laws,  Whether Just Or Unjust. Thus The Legislators Hold The Whole

Power Of The Government In Their Hands,  And Are At The Same Time

Utterly Irresponsible For The Manner In Which They Use It.

 

If,  Now,  This Government,  (The Three Branches Thus Really United In

Chapter 1 (The Right Of Juries To Judge Of The Justice Of Laws) Section 2 Pg 9

One),  Can Determine The Validity Of,  And Enforce,  Its Own Laws,  It Is,

For The Time Being,  Entirely Absolute,  And Wholly Irresponsible To

The People.

 

But This Is Not All. These Legislators,  And This Government,  So

Irresponsible While In Power,  Can Perpetuate Their Power At

Pleasure,  If They Can Determine What Legislation Is Authoritative

Upon The People,  And Can Enforce Obedience To It,  For They Can Not

Only Declare Their Power Perpetual,  But They Can Enforce

Submission To All Legislation That Is Necessary To Secure Its

Perpetuity. They Can,  For Example,  Prohibit All Discussion Of The

Rightfulness Of Their Authority; Forbid The Use Of The Suffrage;

Prevent The Election Of Any Successors; Disarm,  Plunder,  Imprison,

And Even Kill All Who Refuse Submission. If,  Therefore,  The

Government (All Departments United) Be Absolute For A Day   That Is,

If It Can,  For A Day,  Enforce Obedience To Its Own Laws   It Can,  In

That Day,  Secure Its Power For All Time   Like The Queen,  Who Wished

To Reign But For A Day,  But In That Day Caused The King,  Her Husband,

To Be Slain,  And Usurped His Throne.

 

Nor Will It Avail To Say That Such Acts Would Be Unconstitutional,

And That Unconstitutional Acts May Be Lawfully Resisted; For

Everything A Government Pleases To Do Will,  Of Course,  Be

Determined To Be Constitutional,  If The Government Itself Be

Permitted To Determine The Question Of The Constitutionality Of Its

Own Acts. Those Who Are Capable Of Tyranny,  Are Capable Of Perjury

To Sustain It.

 

The Conclusion,  Therefore,  Is,  That Any Government,  That Can,  For A

Day,  Enforce Its Own Laws,  Without Appealing To The People,  (Or To A

Tribunal Fairly Representing The People,) For Their Consent,  Is,  In

Theory,  An Absolute Government,  Irresponsible To The People,  And

Can Perpetuate Its Power At Pleasure.

 

The Trial By Jury Is Based Upon A Recognition Of This Principle,  And

Therefore Forbids The Government To Execute Any Of Its Laws,  By

Punishing Violators,  In Any Case Whatever,  Without First Getting The

Consent Of "The Country," Or The People,  Through A Jury. In This Way,

The People,  At All Times,  Hold Their Liberties In Their Own Hands,  And

Never Surrender Them,  Even For A Moment,  Into The Hands Of The

Government.

 

The Trial By Jury,  Then,  Gives To Any And Every Individual The

Liberty,  At Any Time,  To Disregard Or Resist Any Law Whatever Of The

Government,  If He Be Willing To Submit To The Decision Of A Jury,  The

Questions,  Whether The Law Be Intrinsically Just And Obligatory? And

Whether His Conduct,  In Disregarding Or Resisting It,  Were Right In

Itself? And Any Law,  Which Does Not,  In Such Trial,  Obtain The

Unanimous Sanction Of Twelve Men,  Taken At Random From The

People,  And Judging According To The Standard Of Justice In Their

Own Minds,  Free From All Dictation And Authority Of The

Government,  May Be Transgressed And Resisted With Impunity,  By

Whomsoever Pleases To Transgress Or Resist It.[3]

Chapter 1 (The Right Of Juries To Judge Of The Justice Of Laws) Section 2 Pg 10

 

The Trial By Jury Authorizes All This,  Or It Is A Sham And A Hoax,

Utterly Worthless For Protecting The People Against Oppression. If It

Do Not Authorize An Individual To Resist The First And Least Act Of

Injustice Or Tyranny,  On The Part Of The Government,  It Does Not

Authorize Him To Resist The Last And The Greatest. If It Do Not

Authorize Individuals To Nip Tyranny In The Bud,  It Does Not

Authorize Them To Cut It Down When Its Branches Are Filled With The

Ripe Fruits Of Plunder And Oppression.

 

Those Who Deny The Right Of A Jury To Protect An Individual In

Resisting An Unjust Law Of The Government,  Deny Him All Defence

Whatsoever Against Oppression. The Right Of Revolution,  Which

Tyrants,  In Mockery,  Accord To Mankind,  Is No Legal Right Under A

Government; It Is Only A Natural Right To Overturn A Government.

The Government Itself Never Acknowledges This Right. And The Right

Is Practically Established Only When And Because The Government,

No Longer Exists To Call It In Question. The Right,  Therefore,  Can Be

Exercised With Impunity,  Only When It Is Exercised Victoriously. All

Unsuccessful Attempts At Revolution,  However Justifiable In

Themselves,  Are Punished As Treason,  If The Government Be

Permitted To Judge Of The Treason. The Government Itself Never

Admits The Injustice Of Its Laws,  As A Legal Defence For Those Who

Have Attempted A Revolution,  And Failed. The Right Of Revolution,

Therefore,  Is  Right Of No Practical Value,  Except For Those Who Are

Stronger Than The Government. So Long,  Therefore,  As The

Oppressions Of A Government Are Kept Within Such Limits As Simply

Not To Exasperate Against It A Power Greater Than Its Own,  The Right

Of Revolution Cannot Be Appealed To,  And Is Therefore Inapplicable

To The Case. This Affords A Wide Field For Tyranny; And,  If A Jury

Cannot Here Intervene,  The Oppressed Are Utterly Defenceless.

 

It Is Manifest That The Only Security Against The Tyranny Of The

Government Lies In Forcible Resistance To The Execution Of The

Injustice; Because The Injustice Will Certainly Be Executed,  Unless It

Be Forcibly Resisted. And If It Be But Suffered To Be Executed,  It

Must Then Be Borne; For The Government Never Makes

Compensation For Its Own Wrongs.

 

Since,  Then,  This Forcible Resistance To The Injustice Of The

Government Is The Only Possible Means Of Preserving Liberty,  It Is

Indispensable To All Legal Liberty That This Resistance Should Be

Legalized. It Is Perfectly Self-Evident That Where There Is No Legal

Right To Resist The Oppression Of The Government,  There Can Be No

Lgal Liberty. And Here It Is All-Important To Notice,  That,  Practically

Speaking,  There Can Be No Legal Right To Resist The Oppressions Of The

Government,  Unless There Be Some Legal Tribunal,  Other Than The

Government,  And Wholly Independent Of,  And Above,  The

Government,  To Judge Between The Government And Those Who

Resist Its Oppressions; In Other Words,  To Judge What Laws Of The

Government Are To Be Obeyed,  And What May Be Resisted And Held

For Nought. The Only Tribunal Known To Our Laws,  For This Purpose,

Is A Jury. If A Jury Have Not The Right To Judge Between The

Government And Those Who Disobey Its Laws,  And Resist Its

Chapter 1 (The Right Of Juries To Judge Of The Justice Of Laws) Section 2 Pg 11

Oppressions,  The Government Is Absolute,  And The People,  Legally

Speaking Are Slaves. Like Many Other Slaves They May Have

Sufficient Courage And Strength To Keep Their Masters Somewhat In

Check; But They Are Nevertheless Known To The Law Only As Slaves.

 

That This Right Of Resistance Was Recognized As A Common Law

Right,  When The Ancient And Genuine Trial By Jury Was In Force,  Is

Not Only Proved By The Nature Of The Trial Itself,  But Is

Acknowledged By History. [4]

 

This Right Of Resistance Is Recognized By The Constitution Of The

United States,  As A Strictly Legal And Constitutional Right. It Is So

Recognized,  First By The Provision That "The Trial Of All Crimes,

Except In Cases Of Impeachment,  Shall Be By Jury"   That Is,  By The

Country   And Not By The Government; Secondly,  By The Provision

That "The Right Of The People To Keep And Bear Arms Shall Not Be

Infringed." This Constitutional Security For "The Right To Keep And

Bear Arms," Implies The Right To Use Them   As Much As A

Constitutional Security For The Right To Buy And Keep Food Would

Have Implied The Right To Eat It. The Constitution,  Therefore,  Takes It

For Granted That

 

The People Will Judge Of The Conduct Of The Government,  And That,

As They Have The Right,  They Will Also Have The Sense,  To Use Arms,

Whenever The Necessity Of The Case Justifies It. And It Is A Sufficient

And Legal Defence For A Person Accused Of Using Arms Against The

Government,  If He Can Show,  To The Satisfaction Of A Jury,  Or Even

Any One Of A Jury,  That The Law He Resisted Was An Unjust One.

 

In The American State Constitutions Also,  This Right Of Resistance To

The Oppressions Of The Government Is Recognized,  In Various Ways,

As A Natural,  Legal,  And Constitutional Right. In The First Place,  It Is

So Recognized By Provisions Establishing The Trial By Jury; Thus

Requiring That Accused Persons Shall Be Tried By "The Country,"

Instead Of The Government. In The Second Place,  It Is Recognized By

Many Of Them,  As,  For Example,  Those Of Massachusetts,  Maine,

Vermont,  Connecticut,  Pennsylvania,  Ohio,  Indiana,  Michigan,

Kentucky,  Tennessee,  Arkansas,  Mississippi,  Alabama,  And

Florida,  By Provisions Expressly Declaring That The People Shall

Have The Right To Bear Arms. In Many Of Them Also,  As,  For Example,

Those Of Maine,  New Hampshire,  Vermont,  Massachusetts,  New

Jersey,  Pennsylvania,  Delaware,  Ohio,  Indiana,  Illinois,  Florida,

Iowa,  And Arkansas,  By Provisions,  In Their Bills Of Rights,  Declaring

That Men Have A Natural,  Inherent,  And Inalienable Right Of

"Defending Their Lives And Liberties." This,  Of Course,  Means That

They Have A Right To Defend Them Against Any Injustice On The Part

Of The Government,  And Not Merely On The Part Of Private

Individuals; Because The Object Of All Bills Of Rights Is To Assert The

Rights Of Individuals And The People,  As Against The Government,

And Not As Against Private Persons. It Would Be A Matter Of

Ridiculous Supererogation To Assert,  In A Constitution Of

Government,  The Natural Right Of Men To Defend Their Lives And

Chapter 1 (The Right Of Juries To Judge Of The Justice Of Laws) Section 2 Pg 12

Liberties Against Private Trespassers.

 

Many Of These Bills Of Rights Also Assert The Natural Right Of All Men

To Protect Their Property   That Is,  To Protect It Against The

Government. It Would Be Unnecessary And Silly Indeed To Assert,  In

A Constitution Of Government,  The Natural Right Of Individuals To

Protect Their Property Against Thieves And Robbers.

 

The Constitutions Of New Hampshire And Tennessee Also Declare

That "The Doctrine Of Non-Resistance Against Arbitrary Power And

Oppression Is Absurd,  Slavish,  And Destructive Of The Good And

Happiness Of Mankind."

 

The Legal Effect Of These Constitutional Recognitions Of The Right Of

Individuals To Defend Their Property,  Liberties,  And Lives,  ' Against

The Government,  Is To Legalize Resistance To All Injustice And

Oppression,  Of Every Name And Nature Whatsoever,  On The Part Of

The Government.

 

But For This Right Of Resistance,  On The Part Of The People,  All

Governments Would Become Tyrannical To A Degree Of Which Few

People Are Aware. Constitutions Are Utterly Worthless To Restrain The

Tyranny Of Governments,  Unless It Be Understood That The People

Will,  By Force,  Compel The Government To Keep Within The

Constitutional Limits. Practically Speaking,  No Government Knows

Any Limits To Its Power,  Except The Endurance Of The People. But

That The People Are Stronger Than The Government,  And Will Resist In

Extreme Cases,  Our Governments Would Be Little Or Nothing Else

Than Organized Systems Of Plunder And Oppression. All,  Or Nearly

All,  The Advantage There Is In Fixing Any Constitutional Limits To The

Power Of A Government,  Is Simply To Give Notice To The Government

Of The Point At Which It Will Meet With Resistance. If The People Are

Then As Good As Their Word,  They May Keep The Government Within

The Bounds They Have Set For It; Otherwise It Will Disregard Them   As

Is Proved By The Example Of All Our American Governments,  In

Which The Constitutions Have All Become Obsolete,  At The Moment

Of Their Adoption,  For Nearly Or Quite All Purposes Except The

Appointment Of Officers,  Who At Once Become Practically Absolute,

Except So Far As They Are Restrained By The Fear Of Popular

Resistance.

 

The Bounds Set To The Power Of The Government,  By The Trial By

Jury,  As Will Hereafter Be Shown,  Are These   That The Government

Shall Never Touch The Property,  Person,  Or Natural Or Civil Rights Of

An Individual,  Against His Consent,  {Xcept For The Purpose Of

Bringing Them Before A Jury For Trial,) Unless In Pursuance And

Execution Of A Judgment,  Or Decree,  Rendered By A Jury In Each

Individual Case,  Upon Such Evidence,  Nd Such Law,  As Are

Satisfactory To Their Own Understandings And Consciences,

Irrespective Of All Legislation Of The Government.

 

[1]To Show That This Supposition Is Not An Extravagant One,  It May

Be Mentioned That Courts Have Repeatedly Questioned Jurors To

Ascertain Whether They Were Prejudiced Against The Government  

Chapter 1 (The Right Of Juries To Judge Of The Justice Of Laws) Section 2 Pg 13

That Is,  Whether They Were In Favor Of,  Or Opposed To,  Such Laws Of

The Government As Were To Be Put In Issue In The Then Pending Trial.

This Was Done (In 1851) In The United States District Court For The

District Of Massachusetts,  By Peleg Sprague,  The United States

District Judge,  In Empanelling Three Several Juries For The Trials Of

Scott,  Hayden,  And Morris,  Charged With Having Aided In The Rescue

Of A Fugitive Slave From The Custody Of The United States Deputy

Marshal. This Judge Caused The Following Question To Be

Propounded To All The Jurors Separately; And Those Who Answered

Unfavorably For The Purposes Of The Government,  Were Excluded

From The Panel.

 

"Do You Hold Any Opinions Upon The Subject Of The Fugitive Slave

Law,  So Called,  Which Will Induce You To Refuse To Convict A Person

Indicted Under It,  If The Facts Set Forth,  In The Indictment,  And

Constituting The Offence,  Are Proved Against Him,  And The Court

Direct You That The Law Is Constitutional?"

 

The Reason Of This Question Was,  That "The Fugitive Slave Law,  So

Called," Was So Obnoxious To A Large Portion Of The People,  As To

Render A Conviction Under It Hopeless,  If The Jurors Were Taken

Indiscriminately From Among The People.

 

A Similar Question Was Soon Afterwards Propounded To The Persons

Drawn As Jurors In The United States Circuit Court For The District

Of Massachusetts,  By Benjamin R. Curtis,  One Of The Justices Of The

Supreme Court Of The United States,  In Empanelling A Jury For The

Trial Of The Aforesaid Morris On The Charge Before Mentioned; And

Those Who Did Not Answer The Question Favorably For The

Government Were Again Excluded From The Panel.

 

It Has Also Been An Habitual Practice With The Supreme Court Of

Massachusetts,  In Empanelling Juries For The Trial Of Capital

Offences,  To Inquire Of The Persons Drawn As Jurors Whether They

Had Any Conscientious Scruples Against Finding Verdicts Of Guilty In

Such Eases; That Is,  Whether They Had Any Conscientious Scruples

Against Sustaining The Law Prescribing Death As The Punishment Of

The Crime To Be Trick; And To Exclude From The Panel All Who

Answered In The Affirmative.

 

The Only Principle Upon Which These Questions Are Asked,  Is This 

That No Man Shall Be Allowed To Serve As Juror,  Unless He Be Ready

To Enforce Any Enactment Of The Government,  However Cruel Or

Tyrannical It May Be.

 

What Is Such A Jury Good For,  As A Protection Against The Tyranny Of

The Government? A Jury Like That Is Palpably Nothing But,  A Mere

Tool Of Oppression In The Hands Of The Government. A Trial By Such

A Jury Is Really A Trial By The Government Itself   And Not A Trial By

The Country   Because It Is A Trial Only By Men Specially Selected By

The Government For Their Readiness To Enforce Its Own Tyrannical

Measures.

 

If That Be The True Principle Of The Trial By Jury,  The Trial Is Utterly

Chapter 1 (The Right Of Juries To Judge Of The Justice Of Laws) Section 2 Pg 14

Worthless As A Security To Liberty. The Czar Might,  With Perfect

Safety To His Authority,  Introduce The Trial By Jury Into Russia,  If He

Could But Be Permitted To Select His Jurors From Those Who Were

Ready To Maintain His Laws,  Without Regard To Their Injustice.

 

This Example Is Sufficient To Show That The Very Pith Of The Trial By

Jury,  As A Safeguard To Liberty,  Consists In The Jurors Being Taken

Indiscriminately From The Whole People,  And In Their Right To Hold

Invalid All Laws Which They Think Unjust.

 

[2] The Executive Has A Qualified Veto Upon The Passage Of Laws,  In

Most Of Our Governments,  And An Absolute Veto,  In All Of Them,

Upon The Execution Of Any Laws Which He Deems Unconstitutional;

Because His Oath To Support The Constitution (As He Understands It)

Forbids Him To Execute Any Law That He Deems Unconstitutional.

 

[3] And If There Be So Much As A Reasonable Doubt Of The Justice Of

The Laws,  The Benefit Of That Doubt Must Be Given To The Defendant,

And Not To The Government. So That The Government Must Keep Its

Laws Clearly Within The Limits Of Justice,  If It Would Ask A Jury To

Enforce Them.

 

[4] Hallam Says,  "The Relation Established Between A Lord And His

Vassal By The Feudal Tenure,  Far From Containing Principles Of Any

Servile And Implicit Obedience,  Permitted The Compact To Be

Dissolved In Case Of Its Violation By Either Party. This Extended As

Much To The Sovereign As To Inferior Lords. * * If A,  Vassal Was

Aggrieved,  And If Justice Was Denied Him,  He Sent A Defiance,  That

Is,  A Renunciation Of Fealty To The King,  And Was Entitled To Enforce

Redress At The Point Of His Sword. It Then Became A Contest Of

Strength As Between Two Independent Potentates,  And Was

Terminated By Treaty,  Advantageous Or Otherwise,  According To The

Fortune Of War. * * There Remained The Original Principle,  That

Allegiance Depended Conditionally Upon Good Treatment,  And That

An Appeal Might Be Lawfully Made To Arms Against An Oppressive

Government. Nor Was This,  We May Be Sure,  Left For Extreme

Necessity,  Or Thought To Require A Long-Enduring Forbearance. In

Modern Times,  A King,  Compelled By His Subjects' Swords To

Abandon Any Pretension,  Would Be Supposed To Have Ceased To

Reign; And The Express Recognition Of Such A Right As That Of

Insurrection Has Been Justly Deemed Inconsistent With The Majesty

Of Law. But Ruder Ages Had Ruder Sentiments. Force Was Necessary

To Repel Force; And Men Accustomed To See The King's Authority

Defied By A Private Riot,  Were Not Much Shocked When It Was

Resisted In Defence Of Public Freedom."   3 Middle Age,  240-2.

 

 

Chapter 2 (The Trial By Jury As Defined By Magna Carta) Pg 15

That The Trial By Jury Is All That Has Been Claimed For It In The

Preceding Chapter,  Is Proved Both By The History And The Language

Of The Great Charter Of English Liberties,  To Which We Are To Look

For A True Definition Of The Trial By Jury,  And Of Which The Guaranty

For That Trial Is The Vital,  And Most Memorable,  Part.

Chapter 2 (The Trial By Jury As Defined By Magna Carta) Section 1 Pg 16

The History Of Magna Carta.

 

In Order To Judge Of The Object And Meaning Of That Chapter Of

Magna Carta Which Secures The Trial By Jury,  It Is To Be Borne In

Mind That,  At The Time Of Magna Carta,  The King (With Exceptions

Immaterial To This Discussion,  But Which Will Appear Hereafter)

Was,  Constitutionally,  The Entire Government; The Sole Legislative,

Judicial,  And Executive Power Of The Nation. The Executive And

Judicial Officers Were Merely His Servants,  Appointed By Him,  And

Removable At His Pleasure. In Addition To This,  "The King Himself

Often Sat In His Court,  Which Always Attended His Person. He There

Heard Causes,  And Pronounced Judgment; And Though He Was

Assisted By The Advice Of Other Members,  It Is Not To Be Imagined

That A Decision Could Be Obtained Contrary To His Inclination Or

Opinion."[1] Judges Were In Those Days,  And Afterwards,  Such Abject

Servants Of The King,  That "We Find That King Edward I. (1272 To

1307) Fined And Imprisoned His Judges,  In The Same Manner As

Alfred The Great,  Among The Saxons,  Had Done Before Him,  By The

Sole Exercise Of His Authority."[2]

 

Parliament,  So Far As There Was A Parliament,  Was A Mere Council Of

The King.[3] It Assembled Only At The Pleasure Of The King; Sat Only

During His Pleasure; And When Sitting Had No Power,  So Far As

General Legislation Was Concerned,  Beyond That Of Simply Advising

The King. The Only Legislation To Which Their Assent Was

Constitutionally Necessary,  Was Demands For Money And Military

Services For Extraordinary Occasions. Even Magna Carta Itself

Makes No Provisions Whatever For Any Parliaments,  Except When

The King Should Want Means To Carry On War,  Or To Meet Some Other

Extraordinary Necessity.[4] He Had No Need Of Parliaments To Raise

Taxes For The Ordinary Purposes Of Government; For His Revenues

From The Rents Of The Crown Lands And Other Sources,  Were Ample

For All Except Extraordinary Occasions. Parliaments,  Too,  When

Assembled,  Consisted Only Of Bishops,  Barons,  And Other Great Men

Of The Kingdom,  Unless The King Chose To Invite Others.[5] There

Was No House Of Commons At That Time,  And The People Had No

Right To Be Heard,  Unless As Petitioners.[6]

 

Even When Laws Were Made At The Time Of A Parliament,  They Were

Made In The Name Of The King Alone. Sometimes It Was Inserted In

The Laws,  That They Were Made With The Consent Or Advice Of The

Bishops,  Barons,  And Others Assembled; But Often This Was Omitted.

Their Consent Or Advice Was Evidently A Matter Of No Legal

Importance To The Enactment Or Validity Of The Laws,  But Only

Inserted,  When Inserted At All,  With A View Of Obtaining A More

Willing Submission To Them On The Part Of The People. The Style Of

Enactment Generally Was,  Either "The King Wills And Commands,"

Chapter 2 (The Trial By Jury As Defined By Magna Carta) Section 1 Pg 17

Or Some Other Form Significant Of The Sole Legislative Authority Of

The King. The King Could Pass Laws At Any Time When It Pleased

Him. The Presence Of A Parliament Was Wholly Unnecessary. Hume

Says,  "It Is Asserted By Sir Harry Spelman,  As An Undoubted Fact,

That,  During The Reigns Of The Norman Princes,  Every Order Of The

King,  Issued With The Consent Of His Privy Council,  Had The Full

Force Of Law."[7] And Other Authorities Abundantly Corroborate This

Assertion.[8]The King Was,  Therefore,  Constitutionally The

Government; And The Only Legal Limitation Upon His Power Seems To

Have Been Simply The Common Law,  Usually Called "The Law Of The

Land," Which He Was Bound By Oath To Maintain; (Which Oath Had

About The Same Practical Value As Similar Oaths Have Always Had.)

This "Law Of The Land" Seems Not To Have Been Regarded At All By

Many Of The Kings,  Except So Far As They Found It Convenient To Do

So,  Or Were Constrained To Observe It By The Fear Of Arousing

Resistance. But As All People Are Slow In Making Resistance,

Oppression And Usurpation Often Reached A Great Height; And,  In The

Case Of John,  They Had Become So Intolerable As To Enlist The Nation

Almost Universally Against Him; And He Was Reduced To The

Necessity Of Complying With Any Terms The Barons Saw Fit To Dictate

To Him.

 

It Was Under These Circumstances,  That The Great Charter Of Englsh

Liberties Was Granted.

 

The Barons Of England,  Sustained By The Common People,  Having

Their King In Their Power,  Compelled Him,  As The Price Of His Throne,

To Pledge Himself That He Would Punish No Freeman For A Violation

Of Any Of His Laws,  Unless With The Consent Of The Peers   That Is,  The

Equals   Of The Accused.

 

The Question Here Arises,  Whether The Barons And People Intended

That Those Peers (The Jury) Should Be Mere Puppets In The Hands Of

The King,  Exercising No Opinion Of Their Own As To The Intrinsic

Merits Of The Accusations They Should Try,  Or The Justice Of The Laws

They Should Be Called On To Enforce? Whether Those Haughty And

Victorious Barons,  When They Had Their Tyrant King At Their Feet,

Gave Back To Him His Throne,  With Full Power To Enact Any

Tyrannical Laws He Might Please,  Reserving Only To A Jury (" The

Country") The Contemptible And Servile Privilege Of Ascertaining,

(Under The Dictation Of The King,  Or His Judges,  As To The Laws Of

Evidence),  The Simple Fact Whether Those Laws Had Been

Transgressed? Was This The Only Restraint,  Which,  When They Had All

Power In Their Hands,  They Placed Upon The Tyranny Of A King,

Whose Oppressions They Had Risen In Arms To Resist? Was It To

Obtain Such A Charter As That,  That The Whole Nation Had United,  As It

Were,  Like One Man,  Against Their King? Was It On Such A Charter

That They Intended To Rely,  For All Future Time,  For The Security Of

Their Liberties? No. They Were Engaged In No Such Senseless Work

As That. On The Contrary,  When They Required Him To Renounce

Forever The Power To Punish Any Freeman,  Unless By The Consent Of

His Peers,  They Intended Those Powers Should Judge Of,  And Try,  The

Whole Case On Its Merits,  Independently Of All Arbitrary Legislation,

Or Judicial Authority,  On The Part Of The King. In This Way They Took

Chapter 2 (The Trial By Jury As Defined By Magna Carta) Section 1 Pg 18

The Liberties Of Each Individual   And Thus The Liberties Of The Whole

People   Entirely Out Of The Hands Of The King,  And Out Of The Power

Of His Laws,  And Placed Them In The Keeping Of The People

Themselves. And This Itwas That Made The Trial B Jury The Palladium

Of Their Liberties.

 

The Trial By Jury,  Be It Observed,  Was The Only Real Barrier

Interposed By Them Against Absolute Despotism. Could This Trial,

Then,  Have Been Such An Entire Farce As It Necessarily Must Have

Been,  If The Jury Had Had No Power To Judge Of The Justice Of The

Laws The People Were Required To Obey? Did It Not Rather Imply That

The Jury Were To Judge Independently And Fearlessly As To

Everything Involved In The Charge,  And Especially As To Its Intrinsic

Justice,  And Thereon Give Their Decision,  (Unbiased By Any

Legislation Of The King,) Whether The Accused Might Be Punished?

The Reason Of The Thing,  No Less Than The Historical Celebrity Of The

Events,  As Securing The Liberties Of The People,  And The Veneration

With Which The Trial By Jury Has Continued To Be Regarded,

Notwithstanding Its Essence And Vitality Have Been Almost Entirely

Extracted From It In Practice,  Would Settle The Question,  If Other

Evidences Had Left The Matter In Doubt.

 

Besides,  If His Laws Were To Be Authoritative With The Jury,  Why

Should John Indignantly Refuse,  As At First He Did,  To Grant The

Charter,  (And Finally Grant It Only When Brought To The Last

Extremity,) On The Ground That It Deprived Him Of All Power,  And

Left Him Only The Name Of A King? He Evidently Understood That The

Juries Were To Veto His Laws,  And Paralyze His Power,  At Discretion,

By Forming Their Own Opinions As To The True Character Of The

Offences They Were To Try,  And The Laws They Were To Be Called On To

Enforce; And That "The King Wills And Commands" Was To Have No

Weight With Them Contrary To Their Own Judgments Of What Was

Intrinsically Right.[9]

 

The Barons And People Having Obtained By The Charter All The

Liberties They Had Demanded Of The King,  It Was Further Provided By

The Charter Itself That Twenty-Fie Barons Should Be Appointed By The

Barons,  Out Of Their Number,  To Keep Special Vigilance In The

Kingdom To See That The Charter Was Observed,  With Authority To

Make War Upon The King In Case Of Its Violation. The King Also,  By

The Charter,  So Far Absolved All The People Of The Kingdom From

Their Allegiance To Him,  As To Authorize And Require Them To Swear

To Obey The Twenty-Five Barons,  In Case They Should Make War Upon

The King For Infringement Of The Charter. It Was Then Thought By The

Barons And People,  That Something Substantial Had Been Done For

The Security Of Their Liberties.

 

This Charter,  In Its Most Essential Features,  And Without Any

Abatement As To The Trial By Jury,  Has Since Been Confirmed More

Than Thirty Times; And The People Of England Have Always Had A

Traditionary Idea That It Was Of Some Value As A Guaranty Against

Oppression. Yet That Idea Has Been An Entire Delusion,  Unless The

Jury Have Had The Right To Judge Of The Justice Of The Laws They Were

Called On To Enforce.

Chapter 2 (The Trial By Jury As Defined By Magna Carta) Section 2 Pg 19

The Language Of Magna Carta

 

The Language Of The Great Charter Establishes The Same Point That

Is Established By Its History,  Viz.,  That It Is The Right And Duty Of The

Jury To Judge Of The Justice Of The Laws.

 

The Chapter Guaranteeing The Trial By Jury Is In These Words:

"Nullus Liber Homo Capiatur,  Vel Imprisonetur,  Aut Disseisetur,  Aut

Utlagetor,  Aut Exuletur,  Aut Aliquo Modo Destruatur; Nec Super Eum

Ibimus,  Nec Super Eum Mittemus,  Nisi Per Legale Judicium Parium

Suorum,  Vel Per Legem Terrae."[10]

 

The Corresponding Chapter In The Great Charter,  Granted By Henry

Iii,  (1225) And Confirmed By Edward I,  (1297,) (Which Charter Is

Now Considered The Basis Of The English Laws And Constitution,) Is

In Nearly The Same Words,  As Follows:

 

"Nullus Liber Homo Capiatur,  Vel Imprisonetur,  Aut Disseisetur De

Libero Tenemento,  Vel Libertatibus,  Vel Liberis Consuetudinibus Suis,

Aut Utlagetur,  Aut Exuletur,  Aut Aliquo Modo Destruatur,  Nec Super

Eum Ibimus,  Nec Super Eum Mittemus,  Nisi Per Legale Judicium

Parium Suorum,  Vel Per Legem Terrae."

 

The Most Common Translation Of These Words,  At The Present Day,  Is

As Follows:

 

"No Freeman Shall Be Arrested,  Or Imprisoned,  Or Deprived Of His

Freehold,  Or His Liberties,  Or Free Customs,  Or Outlawed,  Or Exiled,  Or

In Any Manner Destroyed,  Nor Will We (The King) Pass Upon Him,  Nor

Condemn Him,  Unless By The Judgment Of His Peers,  Or The Law Of

The Land."

 

"Nec Super Eum Ibimus,  Nec Super Eum Mittemus."

 

There Has Been Much Confusion And Doubt As To The True Meaning

Of The Words,  "Nec Super Eum Ibimus,  Neo Super Eum Mittemus."

The More Common Rendering Has Been,  "Nor Wilt We Pass Upon

Him,  Nor Condemn Him." But Some Have Translated Them To Mean,

"Nor Will We Pass Upon Him,  Nor Commit Him To Prison." Coke

Gives Still A Different Rendering,  To The Effect That "No Man Shall Be

Condemned At The King's Suit,  Either Before The King In His Bench,

Nor Before Any Other Commissioner Or Judge Whatsoever." [11]

 

But All These Translations Are Clearly Erroneous. In The First Place,

"Nor Will We Pass Upon Him,"   Meaning Thereby To Decide Upon His

Guilt Or Innocence Judicially   Is Not A Correct Rendering Of The

Words,  "Nec Super Eum Ibimus." There Is Nothing Whatever,  In

These Latter Words,  That Indicates Judicial Action Or Opinion At All.

The Words,  In Their Common Signification,  Describe Physical Action

Chapter 2 (The Trial By Jury As Defined By Magna Carta) Section 2 Pg 20

Alone. And The True Translation Of Them,  As Will Hereafter Be Seen,

Is,  "Nor Will We Proceed Against Him," Executively.

 

In The Second Place,  The Rendering,  "Nor Will We Condemn Him,"

Bears Little Or No Analogy To Any Common,  Or Even Uncommon,

Signification Of The Words "Nec Super Eum Mittemus." There Is

Nothing In These Latter Words That Indicates Judicial Action Or

Decision. Their Common Signification,  Like That Of The Words Nec

Super Eum Ibimus,  Describes Physical Action Alone. "Nor Will We

Send Upon (Or Against) Him," Would Be The Most Obvious

Translation,  And,  As We Shall Hereafter See,  Such Is The True

Translation.

 

But Although These Words Describe Physical Action,  On The Part Of

The King,  As Distinguished From Judicial,  They Nevertheless Do Not

Mean,  As One Of The Translations Has It,  "Nor Will We Commit Him To

Prison;" For That Would Be A Mere Repetition Of What Had Been

Already Declared By The Words "Nec Imprisonetur." Besides,  There Is

Nothing About Prisons In The Words "Nec Super Eum Mittemus;"

Nothing About Sending Him Anywhere; But Only About Sending

(Something Or Somebody) Upon Him,  Or Against Him   That Is,

Executively.

 

Coke's Rendering Is,  If Possible,  The Most Absurd And Gratuitous Of

All. What Is There In The Words,  "Nec Super Eum Mittemus," That Can

Be Made To Mean "Nor Shall He Be Condemned Before Any Other

Commissioner Or Judge Whatsoever."? Clearly There Is Nothing. The

Whole Rendering Is A Sheer Fabricatin. And The Whole Object Of It Is

To Give Color For The Exercise Of A Judicial Power,  By The King,  Or

His Judges,  Which Is Nowhere Given Them.

 

Neither The Words,  "Nec Super Eum Ibimus,  Nec Super Eum

Mittemus," Nor Any Other Words In The Whole Chapter,  Authorize,

Provide For,  Describe,  Or Suggest,  Any Judicial Action Whatever,  On

The Part Either Of The King,  Or Of His Judges,  Or Of Anybody,  Except

The Peers,  Or Jury. There Is Nothing About The King's Judges At All.

And,  There Is Nothing Whatever,  In The Whole Chapter,  So Far As

Relates To The Action Of The King,  That Describes Or Suggests Anything

But Executive Action.[12]

 

But That All These Translations Are Certainly Erroneous,  Is Proved By

A Temporary Charter,  Granted By John A Short Time Previous To The

Great Charter,  For The Purpose Of Giving An Opportunity For

Conference,  Arbitration,  And Reconciliation. Between Him And His

Barons. It Was To Have Force Until The Matters In Controversy

Between Them Could Be Submitted To The Pope,  And To Other Persons

To Be Chosen,  Some By The King,  And Some By The Barons. The

Words Of The Charter Are As Follows:

 

"Sciatis Nos Concessisse Baronibus Nostris Qui Contra Nos Sunt Quod

Nec Eos Nec Homines Suos Capiemus,  Nec Disseisiemus Nec Super

Eos Per Vim Vel Per Arma Ibimus Nisi Per Legem Regni Nostri Vel Per

Judicium Parium Suorum In Curia Nostra Donec Consideratio Facta

Fuerit," &C;.,  &C;.

 

Chapter 2 (The Trial By Jury As Defined By Magna Carta) Section 2 Pg 21

 

That Is,  "Know That We Have Granted To Our Barons Who Are

Opposed To Us,  That We Will Neither Arrest Them Nor Their Men,  Nor

Disseize Them,  Nor Will We Proceed Against Them By Force Or By

Arms,  Unless By The Law Of Our Kingdom,  Or By The Judgment Of

Their Peers In Our Court,  Until Consideration,  Shall Be Had," &C;.,

&C;.

 

A Copy Of This Charter Is Given In A Note In Blackstone's

Introduction To The Charter.[13]

 

Mr. Christian Speaks Of This Charter As Settling The True Meaning Of

The Corresponding Clause Of Magna Carta,  On The Principle Tat Laws

And Charters On The Same Subject Are To Be Construed With Reference

To Each Other. See 3 Christin's Blackstone,  41,  Note.

 

The True Meaning Of The Words,  Nec Super Eum Ibimus,  Nec Super

Eum Mittemus,  Is Also Proved By The "Articles Of The Great Charter

Of Liberties," Demanded Of The King By The Barons,  And Agreed To By

The King,  Under Seal,  A Few Days Before The Date Of The Charter,  And

From Which The Charter Was Framed. [14]

Here The Words Used Are These:

 

"Ne Corpus Liberi Hominis Capiatur Nec Imprisonetur Nec

Disseisetur Nec Ut1agetur Nec Exuletur Nec Aliquo Modo Destruatur

Nec Rex Eat Vel Mittat Super Eun Vi Nisi Per Judicium Pariurn

Suorum Vel Per Legem Terrae."

 

That Is,  "The Body Of A Freeman Shall Not Be Arrested,  Nor

Imprisoned,  Nor Disseized,  Nor Outlawed,  Nor Exiled,  Nor In Any

Manner Destroyed,  Nor Shall The King Proceed Or Send (Any One)

Against Him,  With Force,  Unless By The Judgment Of His Peers,

Or The Law Of The Land."

 

The True Translation Of The Words Nec Super Eum Ibimus,  Nec Super

Eum Mittemus,  In Magna Carta,  Is Thus Made Certain,  As Follows,

"Nor Will We (The King) Proceed Against Him,  Nor Send (Any One)

Against Him,  With Force Or Arms. [15]

 

It Is Evident That The Difference Between The True And False

Translations Of The Words,  Nec Super Eum Ibius,  Nec Super Eum

Mittemus,  Is Of The Highest Legal Importance,  Inasmuch As The True

Translation,  Nor Will We (The King) Proceed Against Him,  Nor Send

(Any One) Against Him By Force Of Arms,  Represents The King Only In

An Executive Character,  Carrying The Judgment Of The Peers And "The

Law Of The Land" Into Execution; Where As The False Translation,  Nor

Will We Pass Upon Him,  Nor Condemn Him,   Gives Color For The

Exercise Of A Judicial Power,  On The Part Of The King,  To Which The

King Had No Right,  But Which,  According To The True Translation,

Belongs Wholly To Th Jury.

 

"Per Legale Judicium Parium Suorum."

 

The Foregoing Interpretation Is Corroborated,  (If It Were Not Already

Chapter 2 (The Trial By Jury As Defined By Magna Carta) Section 2 Pg 22

Too Plain To Be Susceptible Of Corroboration,) By The True

Interpretation Of The Phrase "Per Legale Judicium Parium Suorum."

 

In Giving This Interpretation,  I Leave Out,  For The Present,  The Word

Legale,  Which Will Be Defined Afterwards.

 

The True Meaning Of The Phrase,  Per Judicium Parium Suorum,  Is,

According To The Sentence Of His Eers. The Word  Judicium,

Judgment,  Has A Technical Meaning In The Law,  Signifying The

Decree Rendered In The Decision Of A Cause. In Civil Suits This

Decision Is Called A Judgment; In Chancery Proceedngs It Is Called A

Decree; In Criminal Actions It Is Called A Sentence,  Or Judgment,

Indifferently. Thus,  In A Criminal Suit,  "A Motion In Arrest Of

Judgment," Means A Motion In Arrest Of Sentence. [16]

In Cases Of Sentence,  Therefore,  In Criminal Suits,  The Words

Sentence And Judgment Are Synonymous Terms. They Are,  To This

Day,  Commonly Used In Law Books As Synonymous Terms. And The

Phrase Per Jndicium Parium Suorum,  Therefore,  Implies That The

Jury Are To Fix The Sentence. 

 

The Word Per Means According To. Otherwise There Is No Sense In

The Phrase Per Judicium Paruim Suorum. There Would Be No Sense

In Saying That A King Might Imprison,  Disseize,  Outlaw,  Exile,  Or

Otherwise Punish A Man,  Or Proceed Against Him,  Or Send Any One

Against Him,  By Force Or Arms,  By A Judgment Of His Peers; But There

Is Sense In Saying That The King May Imprison,  Disseize,  And Punish

A Man,  Or Proceed Against Him,  Or Send Any One Against Him,  By

Force Or Arms,  According To A Judgment,  Or Sentence,  Of His Peers;

Because In That Case The King Would Be Merely Carrying The

Sentence Or Judgment Of The Peers Into Execution.

 

The Word Per,  In The Phrase "Per Judicium Parium Suorum," Of

Course Means Precisely What It Does In The Next Phrase,  "Per Legem

Terrae;" Where It Obviously Means According To,  And Not By,  As It Is

Usually Translated. There Would Be No Sense In Saying That The King

Might Proceed Against A Man By Force Or Arms,  By The Law Of The

Land; But There Is Sense In Saying That He May Proceed Against Him,

By Force Or Arms,  According To The Law Of The Land; Because The

King Would Then Be Acting Only As An Executive Officer,  Carrying

The Law Of The Land Into Execution. Indeed,  The True Meaning Of The

Word By,  As Used In Similar Cases Now,  Always Is According To; As,

For Example,  When We Say A Thing Was Done By The Government,  Or

By The Executive,  By Law,  We Mean Only That It Was Done By Them

According To Law; That Is,  That They Merely Executed The Law.

 

Or,  If We Say That The Word By Signifies By Authority Of,  The Result

Will Still Be The Same; For Nothing Can Be Done By Authority Of Law,

Except What The Law Itself Authorizes Or Directs To Be Done; That Is,

Nothing Can Be Done By Authority Of Law,  Except Simply To Carry The

Law Itself Into Execution. So Nothing Could Be Done By Authority Of

The Sentence Of The Peers,  Or By Authority Of "The Law Of The Land,"

Except What The Sentence Of The Peers,  Or The Law Of The Land,

Themselves Authorized Or Directed To Be Done; Nothing,  In Short,  But

To Carry The Setence Of The Peers,  Or The Law Of The Land,  Themselves

Chapter 2 (The Trial By Jury As Defined By Magna Carta) Section 2 Pg 23

Into Execution.

 

Doing A Thing By Law,  Or According To Law,  Is Only Carrying The Law

Into Execution. And Punishing A Man By,  Or According To,  The

Sentence Or Judgment Of His Peers,  Is Only Carrying That Sentence Or

Judgment Into Execution.

 

If These Reasons Could Leave Any Doubt That The Word Per Is To Be

Translated According To,  That Doubt Would Be Removed By The Terms

Of An Antecedent Guaranty For The Trial By Jury,  Granted By The

Emperor Conrad,  Of Germany,   [17] Two Hundred Years Before

Magna Carta. Blackstone Cites It As Follows:   (3 Blackstone,  350.)

"Nemo Beneficium Suum Perdat,  Nisi Secundum Consuetu-Dinem

Antecessorum Nostrorum,  Et Judicium Parium Suorum." That Is,  No

One Shall Lose His Estate,   [18] Unless According To ("Secundum")

The Custom (Or Law) Of Our Ancestors,  And (According To) The

Sentence (Or Judgment) Of His Peers.

 

The Evidence Is Therefore Conclusive That The Phrase Per Judicium

Parian Suorum Means According To The Sentence Of His Peers; Thus

Implying Hat The Jury,  And Not The Government,  Are To Fix The

Sentence.

 

If Any Additional Proof Were Wanted That Juries Were To Fix The

Sentence,  It Would Be Found In The Following Provisions Of Magna

Carta,  Viz.:

 

"A Freeman Shall Not Be Amerced For A Small Crime,  (Delicto,) But

According To The Degree Of The Crime; And For A Great Crime In

Proportion To The Magnitude Of It,  Saving To Him His Contenement;

[19] And After The Same Manner A Merchant,  Saving To Him His

Merchandise. And A Villein Shall Be Amerced After The Same

Manner,  Aving To Him His Waynage,   [20] If He Fall Under Our Mercy;

And None Of The Aforesaid Amercements Shall Be Imposed,  (Or

Assessed,  Ponatur,) But By The Oath Of Honest Men Of The

Neighborhood. Earls And Barons Shall Not Be Amerced But By Their

Peers,  And According To The Degree Of Their Crime." [21]

 

Pecuniary Punishments Were The Most Common Punishments At

That Day,  And The Foregoing Provisions Of Magna Carta Show That

The Amount Of Those Punishments Was To Be Fixed By The Jury.

Fines Went To The King,  And Were A Source Of Revenue; And If The

Amounts Of The Fines Had Been Left To Be Fixed By The King,  He

Would Have Had A Pecuniary Temptation To Impose Unreasonable

And Oppressive Ones. So,  Also,  In Regard To Other Punishments Than

Fines. If It Were Left To The King To Fix The Punishment,  He Might

Often Have Motives To Inflict Cruel And Oppressive Ones. As It Was

The Object Of The Trial By Jury To Protect The People Against All

Possible Oppression From The King,  It Was Necessary That The Jury,

And Not The King,  Should Fix The Punishments. [22]

 

"Legale."

 

The Word "Legale," In The Phrase "Per Legale Judicium Parium

Chapter 2 (The Trial By Jury As Defined By Magna Carta) Section 2 Pg 24

Suorum,"Doubtless Means Two Things.1. That The Sentence Must Be

Given In A Legal Manner; That Is,  By The Legal Number Of Jurors,

Legally Empanelled And Sworn To Try The Cause; And That They Give

Their Judgment Or Sentence After A Legal Trial,  Both In Form And

Substance,  Has Been Had. 2. That The Sentence Shall Be For A Legal

Cause Or Offence. If,  Therefore,  A Jury Should Convict And Sentence A

Man,  Either Without Giving Him A Legal Trial,  Or For An Act That Was

Not Really And Legally Criminal,  The Sentence Itself Would Not Be

Legal; And Consequently This Clause Forbids The King To Carry Such A

Sentence Into Execution; For The Clause Guarantees That He Will

Execute No Judgment Or Sentence,  Except It Be Legale Judicium,A

Legal Sentence. Whether A Sentence Be A Legal One,  Would Have To

Be Ascertained By The King Or His Judges,  On Appeal,  Or Might Be

Judged Of Informally By The King Himself.

 

The Word "Legale"Clearly Did Not Mean That The Judicium Parium

Suorum (Judgment Of His Peers) Should Be A Sentence Which Any

Law (Of The King) Should Require The Peers To Pronounce; For In That

Case The Sentence Would Not Be The Sentence Of The Peers,  But Only

The Sentence Of The Law,  (That Is,  Of The King); And The Peers Would

Be Only A Mouthpiece Of The Law,  (That Is,  Of The King,) In Uttering

It.

 

"Per Legem Terrae."

 

One Other Phrase Remains To Be Explained,  Viz.,  "Per Legem Terrae,"

"By The Law Of The Land."

 

All Writers Agree That This Means The Common Law.Thus,  Sir

Matthew Hale Says:

 

"The Common Law Is Sometimes Called,  By Way Of Eminence,  Lex

Terrae,As In The Statute Of Magna Carta,Chap. 29,  Where Certainly

The Common Law Is Principally Intended By Those Words,  Aut Per

Legem Terrae;As Appears By The Exposition Thereof In Several

Subsequent Statutes; And Particularly In The Statute Of 28 Edward

Iii.,  Chap. 3,  Which Is But An Exposition And Explanation Of That

Statute. Sometimes It Is Called Lex Angliae,As In The Statute Of

Merton,  Cap. 9,  "Olurnus Leqes Angliae Mutari,"&C;.,  (We Will That

The Laws Of England Be Not Changed). Sometimes It Is Called Lex Et

Consuetudo Regni(The Law And Custom Of The Kingdom); As In All

Commissions Of Oyer And Terminer; And In The Statutes Of 18

Edward I.,  Cap.  ,  And De Quo Warranto,And Divers Others. But Most

Commonly It Is Called The Common Law,  Or The Common Law Of

England; As In The Statute Articuli Super Chartas,Cap. 15,  In The

Statute 25 Edward Iii.,  Cap. 5,  (4,) And Infinite More Records And

Statutes."   1 Hale's History Of The Common Law,  128.

 

This Common Law,  Or "Law Of The Land," The King Was Sworn To

Maintain.This Fact Is Recognized By A Statute Made At Westminster,

In 1346,  By Edward Iii.,  Which Commences In This Manner:

 

"Edward,  By The Grace Of God,  &C;.,  &C;.,  To The Sheriff Of

Stafford,  Greeting: Because That By Divers Complaints Made To Us,

Chapter 2 (The Trial By Jury As Defined By Magna Carta) Section 2 Pg 25

We Have Perceived That The Law Of The Land,  Which We By Oath Are

Bound Fo Maintain,"&C;. St. 20 Edward Iii

 

The Foregoing Authorities Are Cited To Show To The Unprofessional

Reader,  What Is Well Known To The Profession,  That Legem Terrae,  The

Law Of The Land,Mentioned In Magna Carta,  Was The Common,

Ancient,  Fundamental Law Of The Land,  Which The Kings Were Bound

By Oath To Observe; And That It Did Not Include Any Statutes Or Laws

Enacted By The King Himself,  The Legislative Power Of The Nation.

 

If The Term Legem Terraehad Included Laws Enacted By The King

Himself,  The Whole Chapter Of Magna Carta,  Now Under Discussion,

Would Have Amounted To Nothing As A Protection To Liberty; Because

It Would Have Imposed No Restraint Whatever Upon The Power Of The

King. The King Could Make Laws At Any Time,  And Such Ones As He

Pleased. He Could,  Therefore,  Have Done Anything He Pleased,  By

The Law Of The Land,As Well As In Any Other Way,  If His Own Laws Had

Been "The Law Of The Land."If His Own Laws Had Been "The Law Of The

Land," Within The Meaning Of That Term As Used In Magna Carta,  This

Chapter Of Magna Carta Woold Have Been Sheer Nonsense,

Inasmuch As The Whole Purpot Of It Would Have Been Simply That

"No Man Shall Be Arrested,  Imprisoned,  Or Deprived Of His Freehold,

Or His Liberties,  Or Free Customs,  Or Outlawed,  Or Exiled,  Or In Any

Manner Destroyed (By The King); Nor Shall The King Proceed Against

Him,  Nor Send Any One Againist Him With Force And Arms,  Unless By

The Judgment Of His Peers,  Or Uness The King Shall Please To Do So."

 

This Chapter Of Magna Carta Would,  Therefore,  Have Imposed Not

The Slightest Restraint Upon The Power Of The King,  Or Afforded The

Slightest Protection To The Liberties Of The People,  If The Laws Of The

King Had Been Embraced In Theterm Legem Terrae. But If Legem

Terrae Was The Common Law,  Which The King Was Sworn To

Maintain,  Then A Real Restriction Was Laid Upon His Power,  And A Real

Guaranty Given To The People For Their Liberties.

 

Such,  Then,  Being The Meaning Of Legem Terrae,  The Fact Is

Established That Magna Carta Took An Accused Person Entirely Out

Of The Hands Of The Legislative Power,  That Is,  Of The King; And

Placed Him In The Power And Under The Protection Of His Peers,  And

The Common Law Alone; That,  In Short,  Magna Carta Suffered No

Man To Be Punished For Violating Any Enactment Of The Legislative

Power,  Unless The Peers Or Equals Of The Accused. Freely Consented

To It,  Or The Common Law Authorized It; That The Legislative Power,

Of Itself,  Was Wholly Incompetent To Require The Conviction Or

Punishment Of A Man For Any Offence Whatever.

 

Whether Magna Carta Allowed Of Any Other Trial Than By Jury.

 

The Question Here Arises,  Whether "Legem Terrae Did Not Allow Of

Some Other Mode Of Trial Than That By Jury.

 

The Answer Is,  That,  At The Time Of Magna Carta,  It Is Not Probable,

(For The Reasons Given In The Note,) That Legem Terrae Authorized,  In

Chapter 2 (The Trial By Jury As Defined By Magna Carta) Section 2 Pg 26

Criminal Cases,  Any Other Trial Than The Trial By Jury; But,  If It Did,  It

Certainly Authorized None But The Trial By Battle,  The Trial By Ordeal,

And The Trial By Compurgators. These Were The Only Modes Of Trial,

Except By Jury,  That Had Been Knownin England,  In Criminal Cases,

For Some Centuries Previous To Magna Carta. All Of Them Had

Become Nearly Extinct At The Time Of Magna Carta,  And It Is Not

Probable That They Were Included In "Legem Terrae," As That Term Is

Used In That Instrument. But If They Were Included In It,  They Have

Now Been Long Obsolete,  And Were Such As Neither This Nor Any

Future Age Will Ever Return To. [23]

 

For All Practical Puposes Of The Present Day,  Therefore,  It May Be

Asserted That Magna Carta Allows No Trial Whatever But Trial By

Jury.

 

Whether Magna Carta Allowed Sentence To Be Fixed Otherwise Than

By The Jury.

 

Still Another Question Arises On The Words Legem Terrae,  Viz.,

Whether,  In Cases Where The Question Of Guilt Was Determined By

The Jury,  The Amount Of Punishment May Not Have Been Fixed By

Legem Terrae,  The Common Law,  Instead Of Its Being Fixed By The

Jury.

 

I Think We Have No Evidence Whatever That,  At The Time Of Magna

Carta,  Or Indeed At Any Other Time,  Lex Terrae,  The Common Law,

Fixed The Punishment In Cases Where The Question Of Guilt Was Tried

By A Jury; Or,  Indeed,  That It Did In Any Other Case. Doubtless Certain

Punishments Were Common And Usual For Certain Offences; But I Do

Not Think It Can Be Shown That The Common Law,   The  Lex Terrae, 

Which The King Was Sworn To Maintain,  Required Any One Specific

Punishment,  Or Any Precise Amount Of Punishment,  For Any One

Specific Offence. If Such A Thing Be Claimed,  It Must Be Shown,  For

It Cannot Be Presumed. In Fact,  The Contrary Must Be Presumed,

Because,  In The Nature Of Things,  The Amount Of Punishment Proper

To Be Inflicted On Any Particular Case,  Is A Matter Requiring The

Exercise Of Discretion At The Time,  In Order To Adapt It To The Moral

Quality Of The Offence,  Which Is Different In Each Case,  Varying With

The Mental And Moral Constitutions Of The Offenders,  And The

Circumstances Of Temptation Or Provocation. And Magna Carta

Recognizes This Principle Distinctly,  As Has Before Been Shown,  In

Providing That Freemen,  Merchants,  And Villeins,  "Shall Not Be

Amerced For A Small Crime,  But According To The Degree Of The

Crime; And For A Great Crime In Proportion To The Magnitude Of It,"

And That "None Of The Aforesaid Amercements Shall Be Imposed (Or

Assessed) But By The Oaths Of Honest Men Of The Neighborhood;"

And That "Earl And Barons Shall Not Be Amerced But By Their Peers,

And According To The Quality Of The Offence."

 

All This Implies That The Moral Quality Of The Offence Was To Be

Judged Of At The Rial,  And That The Punishment Was To Be Fixed By

The Discretion Of The Peers,  Or Jury,  And Not By Any Such Unvarying

Rule As A Common Law Rule Would Be.

Chapter 2 (The Trial By Jury As Defined By Magna Carta) Section 2 Pg 27

 

I Think,  Therefore,  It Must Be Conceded That,  In All Cases,  Tried By A

Jury,  Magna Carta Intended That The Punishment Should Be Fixed By

The Jury,  And Not By The Common Law,  For These Several Reasons.

 

1. It Is Uncertain Whether The Common Law Fixed The Punishment Of

Any Offence Whatever.

 

2. The Words  "Per Judicium Parium Suorum," According To The

Sentence Of His Peers,   Imply That The Jury Fixed The Sentence In

Some  Cases Tried By Them; And If They Fixed The Sentence In Some

Cases,  It Must Be Presumed They Did In All,  Unless The Contrary Be

Clearly Shown.

 

3. The Express Provisions Of Magna Carta,  Before Adverted To,  That

No Amercements,  Or Fines,  Should Be Imposed Upon. Freemen,

Merchants,  Or Villeins,  "But By The Oath Of Honest Men Of The

Neighborhood," And "According To The Degree Of The Crime," And

That "Earls And Barons Shout Not Be Amerced But By Their Peers,  And

According To The Quality Of The Offence,"  Proves That,  At Least,  There

Was No Common Law Fixing The Amount Of  Fines,  Or,  If There Were,

That It Was To Be No Longer In Force. And If There Was No Common

Law Fixing The Amount Of Fines,  Or If It Was To Be No Longer In Force,

It Is Reasonable To Infer,  (In The Absence Of All Evidence To The

Contrary,) Either That The Common Law Did Not Fix The Amount Of

Any Other Punishment,  Or That It Was To Be No Longer In Force For

That Purpose. [25]

 

Under The Saxon Laws,  Fines,  Payable To The Injured Party,  Seem To

Have Been The Common Punishments For All Offences. Even Murder

Was Punishable By A Fine Payable To The Relatives Of The Deceased.

The Murder Of The King Even Was Punishable By Fine. When A

Criminal Was Unable To Pay His One,  His Relatives Often Paid It For

Him. But If It Were Not Paid,  He Was Put Out Of The Protection Of The

Law,  And The Injured Parties,  (Or,In The Case Of Murder,  The Kindred

Of The Deceased,)Were Allowed To Inflict Such Punishment As They

Pleased. And If The Relatives Of The Criminal Protected Him,  It Was

Lawful To Take Vengeance On Them Also. Afterwards The Custom

Grew Up Of Exacting Fines Also To The King As A Punishment For

Offences.  [26]

 

And This Latter Was,  Doubtless,  The Usual Punishment At The Time Of

Magna Carta,  As Is Evidenced By The Fact That For Many Years

Immediately Following Magna Carta,  Nearly Or Quite All Statutes

That Prescribed Any Punishment At All,  Prescribed That The Offender

Should "Be Grievously  Amerced," Or "Pay A Great Fine To The King,"

Or A "Grievous Ransom,"     With The Alternative In Some Cases

(Perhaps Understood In All) Of Imprisonment,  Banishment,  Or

Outlawry,  In Case Of Non-Payment. [27]

 

Judging,  Therefore,  From The Special Provisions In Magna Carta,

Requiring Fines,  Or Amercements,  To Be Imposed Only By Juries,

(Without Mentioning Any Other Punishments;) Judging,  Also,  From

Chapter 2 (The Trial By Jury As Defined By Magna Carta) Section 2 Pg 28

The Statutes Which Immediately Followed Magna Carta,  It Is

Probable That,  The Saxon Custom Of Punishing All,  Or Nearly All,

Offences By Fines,  (With The Alternative To The Criminal Of Being

Imprisoned,  Banished,  Or Outlawed,  And Exposed To Private

Vengeance,  In Case Of Non-Payment,) Continued Until The Time Of

Magna Carta; And That In Providing Expressly That Fines Should Be

Fixed By The Juries,  Magna Carta Provided For Nearly Or Quite All

The Punishments That Were Expected To Be Inflicted; That If There

Were To Be Any Others,  They Were To Be Fixed By The Juries; And

Consequently That Nothing Was Left To Be Fixed By "Legem Terrae."

But Whether The Common Law Fixed The Punishment Of Any

Offences,  Or Not,  Is A Matter Of Little Or No Practical Importance At

This Day; Because We Have No Idea Of Going Back To Any Common

Law Punishments Of Six Hundred Years Ago,  If,  Indeed,  There Were

Any Such At That Time. It Is Enough For Us To Know   And This Is What

Is Material For Us Know   That The Jury Fixed The Punishments,  In All

Cases,  Unless They Were Fixed By The Common Law; That Magna

Carta Allowed No Punishments To Be Prescribed By Statute   That Is,

By The Legislative Power   Nor In Any Other Manner By The King,  Or

His Judges,  In Any Case Whatever; And,  Consequently,  That All

Statutes Prescribing Particular Punishmnts For Particular Offences,

Or Giving The King's Judges Any Authority To Fix Punishments,  Were

Void.

 

If The Power To Fix Punishments Had Been Left In The Hands Of The

King,  It Would Have Given Him A Power Of Oppression,  Which Was

Liable To Be Greatly Abused; Which There Was No Occasion To Leave

With Him; And Which Would Have Been Incongruous With The Whole

Object Of This Chapter Of Magna Carta; Which Object Was To Take All

Discretionary Or Arbitrary Power Over Individuals Entirely Out Of The

Hands Of The King,  And His Laws,  And Entrust It Only To The Common

Law,  And The Peers,  Or Jury   That Is,  The People. What Lex Terrae

Did Authorize.

 

But Here The Question Arises,  What Then Did Legem Terrae" Authorize

The King,  (That Is,  The Government,) To Do In The Case Of An Accused

Person,  If It Neither Authorized Any Other Trial Than That By Jury,  Nor

Any Other Punishments Than Those Fixed By Juries?

 

The Answer Is,  That,  Owing To The Darkness Of History On The Point,

It Is Probably Wholly Impossible,  At This Day,  To State,  With Any

Certainty Or Precision,  Anything Whatever That The Legem Terrae Of

Magna Carta Did Authorize The King,  (That Is,  The Government,) To

Do,  (If,  Indeed,  It Authorized Him To Do Anything,) In The Case Of

Criminals,  Other Than To Have Them,  Tried And Sentenced By Their

Peers,  For Common Law Crimes; And To Carry That Sentence Into

Execution.

 

The Trial By Jury Was A Part Of Legem Terrae,  And We Have The Means

Of Knowing What The Trial By Jury Was. The Fact That The Jury Were

To Fix The Sentence,  Implies That They Were To Try The Accused;

Otherwise They Could Not Know What Sentence,  Or Whether Any

Sentence,  Ought To Be Inflicted Upon Him. Hence It Follows That The

Jury Were To Judge Of Everything Involved In The Trial; That Is,  They

Chapter 2 (The Trial By Jury As Defined By Magna Carta) Section 2 Pg 29

Were To Judge Of The Nature Of The Offence,  Of The Admissibility And

Weight Of Testimony,  And Of Everything Else Whatsoever That Was Of

The Essence Of The Trial. If Anything Whatever Could Be Dictated To

Them,  Either Of Law Or Evidence,  The Sentence Would Not Be Theirs,

But Would Be Dictated To Them By The Power That Dictated To Them

The Law Or Evidence. The Trial Nd Sentence,  Then,  Were Wholly In The

Hands Of The Jury.

 

We Also Have Sufficient Evidence Of The Nature Of The Oath

Administered To Jurors In Criminal Cases. It Was Simply,  That They

Would Neither Convict The Innocent,  Nor Acquit The Guilty. This Was

The Oath In The Saxon Times,  And Probably Continued To Be Until

Magna Carta.

 

We Also Know That,  In Case Of Conviction,  The Sentence Of The Jury

Was Not Necessarily Final; That The Accused Had The Right Of Appeal

To The King And His Judges,  And To Demand Either A New Trial,  Or An

Acquittal,  If The Trial Or Conviction Had Been Against Law. So Much, 

Therefore,  Of The Legem Terrae Of Magna Carta,  We Know With

Reasonable Certainty.

 

We Also Know That Magna Carta Provides That "No Bailiff (Balivus)

Shall Hereafter Put Any Man To His Law,  (Put Him On Trial,) On His

Single Testimony,  Without Credible Witnesses Brought To Support It."

Coke Thinks "That Under This Word Balivus,  In This Act,  Is

Comprehended Every Justice,  Minister Of The King,  Steward Of The

King,  Steward And Bailiff." (2 Inst. 44.) And In Support Of This Idea

He Quotes From A Very Ancient Law Book,  Called The Mirror Of

Justices,  Written In The Time Of Edward I.,  Within A Century After

Magna Carta. But Whether This Were Really A Common Law

Principle,  Or Whether The Provision Grew Out Of That Jealousy Of The

Government Which,  At The Time Of Magna Carta,  Had Reached Its

Height,  Cannot Perhaps Now Be Determined.

 

We Also Know That,  By Magna Carta,  Amercements,  Or Fines,  Could

Not Be Imposed To The Ruin Of The Criminal; That,  In The Case Of A

Freeman,  His Contenement,  Or Means Of Subsisting In The Condition

Of A Freeman,  Must Be Saved To Him; That,  In The Case Of A Merchant,

His Merchandise Must Be Spared; And In The Case Of A Villein,  His

Waynage,  Or Plough-Tackle And Carts. This Also Is Likely To Have

Been A Principle Of The Common Law,  Inasmuch As,  In That Rude Age,

When The Means Of Gettin Employment As Laborers Were Not What

They Are Now,  The Man And His Family Would Probably Have Been

Liable To Starvation,  If These Means Of Subsistence Had Been Taken

From Him.

 

We Also Know,  Generally,  That,  At The Time Of Magna Carta,  All Acts

Intrinsically Criminal,  All Trespasses Against Persons And Property,

Were Crimes,  According To Lex Terra,  Or The Common Law.

Beyond The Points Now Given,  We Hardly Know Anything,  Probably

Nothing With Certainty,  As To What The "Legem Terran" Of Magna

Carta Did Authorize,  In Regard To Crimes. There Is Hardly Anything

Extant That Can Give Us Any Real Light On The Subject.

It Would Seem,  However,  That There Were,  Even At That Day,  Some

Chapter 2 (The Trial By Jury As Defined By Magna Carta) Section 2 Pg 30

Common Law Principles Governing Arrests; And Some Common Law

Forms And Rules As To Holding A Man For Trial,  (By Bail Or

Imprisonment;) Putting Him On Trial,  Such As By Indictment Or

Complaint; Summoning And Empanelling Jurors,  &C;.,  &C;.

Whatever These Common Law Principles Were,  Magna Carta

Requires Them To Be Observed; For Magna Carta Provides For The

Whole Proceedings,  Commencing With The Arrest,  ("No Freeman

Shall Be Arrested," &C;.,) And Ending With The Execution Of The

Sentence. And It Provides That Nothing Shall Be Done,  By The

Government,  From Beginning To End,  Unless According To The

Sentence Of The Peers,  Or "Legem Terrae," The Common Law. The Trial

By Peers Was A Part Of Legem Terrae,  And We Have Seen That The

Peers Must Necessarily Have Governed The Whole Proceedings At The

Tria1. But All The Proceedings For Arresting The Man,  And Bringing

Him To Trial,  Must Have Been Had Before The Case Could Come Under

The Cognizance Of The Peers,  And They Must,  Therefore,  Have Been

Governed By Other Rules Than The Discretion Of The Peers. We May

Conjecture,  Although We Cannot Perhaps Know With Much Certainty,

That The Lex Terrae,  Or Common Law,  Governing These Other

Proceedings,  Was Somewhat Similar To The Common Law Principle,

On The Same Points,  At The Present Day. Such Seem To Be The

Opinions Of Coke,  Who Says That The Phrase Nisi Per Legem Terrae

Means Unless By Due Process Of Law. Thus,  He Says: "Nisi Per Legem

Terrae. But By The Law Of The Land.

 

For The True Sense And Exposition Of These Words,  See The Statute F

37 Edw. Iii.,  Cap. 8,  Where The Words,  By The Law Of The Land,  Are

Rendered Without Due Process Of Law; For There It Is Said,  Though It

Be Contained In The Great Charter,  That No Man Be Taken,

Imprisoned,  Or Put Out Of His Freehold,  Without Process Of The Law;

That Is,  By Indictment Or Presentment Of Good And Lawful Men,

Where Such Deeds Be Done In Due Manner,  Or By Writ Original Of The

Common Law.

 

"Without Being Brought In To Answer But By Due Process Of The

Common Law."

 

"No Man Be Put To Answer Without Presentment Before Justices,  Or

Thing Of Record,  Or By Due Process,  Or By Writ Original,  According To

The Old Law Of The Land."   2 Inst. 50.

 

The Foregoing Interpretations Of The Words Nisi Per Legem Terrae

Are Corroborated By The Following Statutes,  Enacted In The Next

Century After Magna Carta.

 

"That No Man,  From Henceforth; Shall Be Attached By Any

Accusation,  Nor Forejudged Of Life Or Limb,  Nor His Land,  Tenements,

Goods,  Nor Chattels,  Seized Into The King's Hands,  Against The Form

Of The Great Charter,  And The Law Of The Land."   St,  5 Edward Iii.,

Ch. 9. (1331.)

 

"Whereas It Is Contained In The Great Charter Of The Franchises Of

England,  That None Shall Be Imprisoned,  Nor Put Out Of His Freehold,

Nor Of His Franchises,  Nor Free Customs,  Unless It Be By The Law Of

Chapter 2 (The Trial By Jury As Defined By Magna Carta) Section 2 Pg 31

The Land; It Is Accorded,  Assented,  And Established,  That From

Henceforth None Shall Be Taken By Petition,  Or Suggestion Made To

Our Lord The King,  Or To His Council,  Unless It Be By Indictment Or

Presentment Of Good And Lawful People Of The Same Neighborhood

Where Such Deeds Be Done In Due Manner,  Or By Process Made By

Writ Original At The Common Law; Nor That None Be Put Out Of His

Franchises,  Nor Of His Freehold,  Unless He Be Duly Brought Into

Answer,  And Forejudged Of The Same By The Course Of The Law; And

If Anything Be Done Against The Same,  It Shall Be Redressed,  And

Holden For None."   8t. 95 Edward Iii.,  Ch. 4. (1350.)

 

"That No Man,  Of What Estate Or Condition That He Be,  Shall Be Put

Out Of Land Or Tenement,  Nor Taken,  Nor Imprisond,  Nor Disinherited,

Nor Put To Death,  Without Being Brought In Answer By Due Process

Of Law."   8t. 28 Aboard Iii.,  Ch. 3. (1354.)

 

"That No Man Be Put To Answer Without Presentment Before

Justices,  Or Matter Of Record,  Or By Due Process And Writ Original,

According To The Old Law Of The Land. And If Anything From

Henceforth Be Done To The Contrary,  It Shall Be Void In Law,  And

Holden For Error."   8t. 42 Edward Iil,  Ch. 3. (1368.)

 

The Foregoing Interpretation Of The Words Nisi Per Legem Terrae 

That Is,  By Due Process Of Law   Including Indictment,  &C;.,  Has

Been Adopted. As The True One By Modern Writers And Courts; As,  For

Example,  By Kent,  (2 Comm. 13,) Story,  (3 Comm. 661,) And The

Supreme Court Of New York,  (19 Wendell,  6t6; 4 Hill,  146.)

The Fifth Amendment To The Constitution Of The United States Seems

To Have Been Framed On The Same Idea,  Inasmuch As It Provides That

"No Person Shall Be Deprived Of Life,  Liberty,  Or Property,  Without

Due Process Of Law." [28]

 

Whether The Word Vel Should Be Rendered By Or,  Or By And.

 

Having Thus Given The Meanings,  Or Rather The Applications,  Which

The Words Vel Per Legem Terrae Will Reasonably,  And Perhaps Must

Necessarily,  Bear,  It Is Proper To Suggest,  That It Has Been Supposed

By Some That The Word Vel,  Instead Of Being Rendered By Or,  As It

Usually Is,  Ought To Be Rendered By And,  Inasmuch As The Word Vel

Is Often Used For Et,  And The Whole Phrase Nisi Per Judicium Parian

Suorun,  Vel Per Legem Terrae,  (Which Would Then Read,  Unless By The

Sentence Of His Peers,  And The Law Of The Land,) Would Convey A

More Intelligible And Harmonious Meaning Than It Otherwise Does.

 

Blackstone Suggests That This May Be The True Reading. (Charters,  P.

41.) Also Mr. Hallam,  Who Says:"Nisi Per Legale Judicium Parium

Suorum,  Vel Per Legem Terra;. Several Explanations Have Been

Offered Of The Alternative Clause; Which Some Have Referred To

Judgment By Default,  Or Demurrer; Others To The Process Of

Attachment For Contempt. Certainly There Are Many Legal

Procedures Besides Trial By Jury,  Through Which A Party's Goods Or

Person May Be Taken. But One May Doubt Whether These Were In

Contemplation Of The Framers Of Magna Carta. In An Entry Of The

Charter Of 1217 By A Contemporary Hand,  Preserved In The

Chapter 2 (The Trial By Jury As Defined By Magna Carta) Section 2 Pg 32

Town-Clerk's Office In London,  Called Liber Custumarum Et

Regum Antiquarum,  A Various Reading,  Et Per Legem Terrae,  Occurs.

Blackstone's Charters,  P. 42 (41.) And The Word Vel Is So Frequently

Used For Et,  That I Amnot Wholly Free From A Suspicion That It  Was

So Intended In This Place. The Meaning Will Be,  That No Person Shall

Be Disseized,  &C;.,  Except Upon A Lawful Cause Of Action,  Found By

The Verdict Of A Jury. This Really Seems As Good As Any Of The

Disjunctive Interpretatios; But I Do Not  Offer It With Much

Confidence."   2 Hallam's Middle Ages,    Ch. 8,  Part 2,  P. 449,

Note."  [29]

 

The Idea That The Word Vel,   Should Be Rendered By And,  Is

Corroborated,  If Not Absolutely Confirmed,  By The Following Passage

In Blackstone,  Which Has Before Been Cited. Speaking Of The Trial

By Jury,  As Established By Magna Carta,  He Calls It,  "A Privilege

Which Is Couched In Almost The Same Words With That Of The

Emperor Conrad Two Hundred Years Before: 'Nemo Beneficium

Suum Perdat,  Nisi Secundum Consuetudinem Antecessorum

Nostrorum,  Et,   Judicium Parium Suorum. ' (No One Shall Lose His

Estate Unless According To The Custom Of Our Ancestors,  And,   The

Judgment Of His Peers.)   3 Blackstone,  350., 

 

If The Word Vel,   Be Rendered By And,,   (As I Think It Must Be,  At Least

In Some Cases,) This Chapter Of Magna Carta Will Then Read That No

Freeman Shall Be Arrested Or Punished,  "Unless According To The

Sentence Of His Peers,  And,   The Law Of The Land."

 

The Difference Between This Reading And The Other Is Important. In

The One Case,  There Would Be,  At First View,  Some Color Of Ground

For Saying That A Man Might Be Punished In Either Of Two Ways,  Viz.,

According To The Sentence Of His Peers,  Or According To The Law Of

The Land. In The Other Case,  It Requires Both The Sentence Of His Peers

And,   The Law Of The Laud (Common Law) To Authorize His

Punishment.

 

If This Latter Reading Be Adopted,  The Provision Would Seem To

Exclude All Trials Except Trial By Jury,  And All Causes Of Action

Except Those Of The Common Law., 

 

But I Apprehend The Word Vel,   Must Be Rendered Both By And,,   And

By Or;,   That In Cases Of A Judgment,,   It Should Be Rendered By And,, 

So As To Require The Concurrence Both Of "The Judgment Of The Peers

And,   The Law Of The Land," To Authorize The King To Make Execution

Upon A Party's Goods Or Person; But That In Cases Of Arrest And

Imprisonment,  Simply For The Purpose Of Bringing A Man To Trial,

Vel,   Should Be Rendered By Or,  ,  Because There Can Have Been No

Judgment Of A Jury In Such A Case,  And "The Law Of The Land" Must

Therefore Necessarily Be The Only Guide To,  And Restraint Upn,  The

King. If This Guide And Restraint Were Taken Away,  The King Would

Be Invested With An Arbitrary And Most Dangerous Power In.

Making Arrests,  And Confining In Prison,  Under Pretence Of An

Intention To Bring To Trial.

 

Chapter 2 (The Trial By Jury As Defined By Magna Carta) Section 2 Pg 33

Having Thus Examined The Language Of This Chapter Of Magna Cart,

So Far As It Relates To Criminal Cases,  Its Legal Import May Be Stated

As Follows,  Viz.:

 

No Freeman Shall Be Arrested,  Or Imprisoned,  Or Deprived Of His

Freehold,  Or His Liberties,  Or Free Customs,  Or Be Outlawed,  Or

Exiled,  Or In Any Manner Destroyed,  (Harmed,) Nor Will We (The

King) Proceed. Against Him,  Nor Send Any One Against Him,  By Force

Or Arms,  Unless According To (That Is,  In Execution. Of) The Sentence

Of His Peers,  And (Or Or,  As The Case May Require) The Common Law

Of England,  (As It Was At The Time Of Magna Carta,  In 1215.)

 

[1] Hume,  Appendix 2, 

 

[2] Crabbe's History Of The English Law,  236.

 

[3] Coke Says,  "The King Of England Is Armed With Divers Councils,

One Whereof Is Called Commune Concilium,  (The Common Council,)

And That Is The Court Of Parliament And So It Is Legally Called In

Writs And Judicial Proceedings Comanche Concilium Regni

Anglicae,  (The Common Council Of The Kingdom Of England.) And

Another Is Called Magnum Concilium,  (Great Council;) This Is

Sometimes Applied To The Upper House Of Parliament,  And

Sometimes,  Out Of Parliament Time,  To The Peers Of The Realm,  Lords

Of Parliament,  Who Are Called Magnum Concilium Regis,  (The Great

Council Of The King;) [4] Thirdly,  (As Every Man Knoweth,) The King

Hath A Privy Council For Matters Of State. * * The Fourth Council Of

The King Are His Judges For Law Matters." 1 Coke's Institutes,  110 A.

 

[4] The Great Charter Of Henry Iii.,  (1216 And 1225,) Confirmed By

Edward I.,  (1297,) Makes No Provision Whatever For,  Or Mention

Of,  A Parliament,  Unless The Provision,  (Ch. 37,) That "Escuage,  (A

Military Contribution,) From Henceforth Shall Be Taken Like As It Was

Wont To Be In The Time Of King Henry Our Grandfather," Mean That A

Parliament Shall Be Summoned For That Purpose.

 

[5]The Magna Carta Of John,  (Ch. 17 And 18,) Defines Those Who

Were Entitled To Be Summoned To Parliament,  To Wit,  "The

Archbishops,  Bishops,  Abbots,  Earls,  And Great Barons Of The

Realm,  * * And All Others Who Hold Of Us In Chief." Those Who Held

Land Of The King In Chief Included None Below The Rank Of Knights.

 

[6] The Parliaments Of That Time Were,  Doubtless,  Such As Carlyle

Describes Them,  When He Says,  "The Parliament Was At First A Most

Simple Assemblage,  Quite Cognate To The Situation; That Red

William,  Or Whoever Had Taken On Him The Terrible Task Of Being

King Of England,  Was Wont To Invite,  Oftenest About Christmas

Time,  His Subordinate Kinglets,  Barons As He Called Them,  To Give

Him The Pleasure Of Their Company For A Week Or Two; There,  In

Earnest Conference All Morning,  In Freer Talk Over Christmas Cheer

All Evening,  In Some Big Royal Hall Of Westminster,  Winchester,  Or

Wherever It Might Be,  With Log Fires,  Huge Rounds Of Roast And

Boiled,  Not Lacking Malmsey And Other Generous Liquor,  They Took

Counsel Concerning The Arduous Matters Of The Kingdom." 

Chapter 2 (The Trial By Jury As Defined By Magna Carta) Section 2 Pg 34

 

[7] Hume,  Appendix 2.

 

[8] This Point Will Be More Fully Established Hereafter.

 

[9] It Is Plain That The King And All His Partisans Looked Upon The

Charter As Utterly Prostrating The King's Legislative Supremacy

Before The Discretion Of Juries. When The Schedule Of Liberties

Demanded By The Barons Was Shown To Him,  (Of Which The Trial By

Jury Was The Most Important,  Because It Was The Only One That

Protected All The Rest,) "The King,  Falling Into A Violent Passion,

Asked,  Why The Barons Did Not With These Exactions Demand His

Kingdom? * * And With A Solemn Oath Protested,  That He Would

Never Grant Such Liberties As Would Make Himself A Slave." * * But

Afterwards,  "Seeing Himself Deserted,  And Fearing They Would Seize

His Castles,  He Sent The Earl Of Pembroke And Other Faithful

Messengers To Them,  To Let Them Know He Would Grant Them The

Laws And Liberties They Desired." * * But After The Charter Had Been

Granted,  "The King's Mercenary Soldiers,  Desiring War More Than

Peace,  Were By Their Leaders Continually Whispering In His Ears,  That

He Was Now No Longer King,  But The Scorn Of Other Princes; And That

It Was More Eligible To Be No King,  Than Such A One As He." * * He

Applied To The Pope,  That He Might By His Apostolic Authority Make

Void What The Barons Had Done.* * At Rome He Met With What

Success He Could Desire,  Where All The Transactions With The Barons

Were Fully Represented To The Pope,  And The Charter Of Liberties

Shown To Him,  In Writing; Which,  When He Had Carefully Perused,

He,  With A Furious Look,  Cried Out,  What! Do The Barons Of England

Endeavor To Dethrone A King,  Who Has Taken Upon Him The Holy

Cross,  And Is Under The Protection Of The Apostolic See,  And Would

They Force Him To Transfer The Dominions Of The Roman Church To

Others? By St. Peter,  This Injury Must Not Pass Unpunished. Then

Debating The Matter With The Cardinals,  He,  By A Definitive Sentence,

Damned And Cassated Forever The Charter Of Liberties,  And Sent The

King A Bull Containing That Sentence At Large."   Echard's History Of

England,  P. 106-7

 

These Things Show That The Nature And Effect Of The Charter Were

Well Understood By The King And His Friends; That They All Agreed

That He Was Effectually Stripped Of Power. Yet The Legislative Power

Had Not Been Taken From Him; But Only The Power To Enforce His

Laws,  Unless Juries Should Freely Consent To Their Enforcement.

 

[10] The Laws Were,  At That Time,  All Written In Latin.

 

[11]"No Man Shall Be Condemned At The King"S Suit,  Either Before

The King In His Bench,  Where Pleas Are Coram Rege,  (Before The

King,) (And So Are The Words Nec Super Eum Ibimus,  To Be

Understood,) Nor Before Any Other Commissioner Or Judge

Whatsoever,  And So Are The Words Nec Super Eum Mittemus,  To Be

Understood,  But By The Judgment Of His Peers,  That Is,  Equals,  Or

According To The Law Of The Land."   2 Coke's Inst.,  46.

 

[12] Perhaps The Assertion In The Text Should Be Made With This

Chapter 2 (The Trial By Jury As Defined By Magna Carta) Section 2 Pg 35

Qualification   That The Words "Per Legem Terrae," (According To The

Law Of The Land,) And The Words "Per Legale Judiciun Parium

Suorum," (According To The Legal Judgment Of His Peers,) Imply That

The King,  Before Proceeding To Any Executive Action,  Will Take

Notice Of "The Law Of The Land," And Of The Legality Of The Judgment

Of The Peers,  And Will Execute Upon The Prisoner Nothing Except

What The Law Of The Land Authorizes,  And No Judgments Of The Peers,

Except Legal Ones. With This Qualification,  The Assertion In The Text

Is Strictly Correct   That There Is Nothing In The Whole Chapter That

Grants To The King,  Or His Judges,  Any Judicial Power At All. The

Chapter Only Describes And Limits His Executive Power.

 

[13] See Blackstone'a Law Tracts,  Page 294,  Oxford Edition

 

[14] These Articles Of The Charter Are Given In Blackstone's

Collection Of Charters,  And Are Also Printed With The Statutes Of The

Realm. Also In Wilkins' Laws Of The Anglo- Saxons,  P. 350.

 

[15] Lingard Says,  " The Words,  ' We Will Not Destroy Him Nor Will

We Go Upon Him,  Nor Will We Send Upon Him,' Have Been Very

Differently Expounded By Different Legal Authorities. Their Real

Meaning May Be Learned From John Himself,  Who The Next Year

Promised By His Letters Patent,... Nec Super Eos Per Vim Vel Per

Arma Ibimus,  Nisi Per Legem Regni Nostri,  Vel Per Judicium Parium

Suorum In Curia Nostra,  (Nor Will We Go Upon Them By Force Or By

Arms,  Unless By The Law Of Our Kingdom,  Or The Judgment Of Their

Peers In Our Court.) Pat. 16 Johan,  Apud Drad. 11,  App. No. 124.

 

He Had Hitherto Been In The Habit Of Going With An Armed Force,  Or

Sending An Armed Force On The Lands,  And Against The Castles,  Of All

Whom He Knew Or Suspected To Be His Secret Enemies,  Without

Observing Any Form Of Law."   3 Lingard,  47 Note.

 

[16] "Judgment,  Judicium. * * The Sentence Of The Law,

Pronounced By The Court,  Upon The Matter Contained In The Record."

  8 Blackstone,  895. Jacob's Law Dictionary. . Tomlin's Do.

 

"Judgment Is The Decision Or Sentence Of The Law,  Given By A Court

Of Justice Or Other Competent Tribunal,  As The Result Of The

Proceedings Instituted Therein,  For The Redress Of An Injury." 

Bouvier's Law Dict.

 

"Judgment,  Judicium. * * Sentence Of A Judge Against A Criminal. *

* Determination,  Decision In General."   Bailey's Dict.

 

"Judgment. * * In A Legal Sense,  A Sentence Or Decision Pronounced

By Authority Of A King,  Or Other Power,  Either By Their Own Mouth,

Or By That Of Their Judges Andofficers,  Whom They Appoint,  To

Administer Justice In Their Stead."   Chambers' Dict.

 

"Judgment. * * In Law,  The Sentence Or Doom Pronounced In Any

Case,  Civil Orcriminal,  By The Judge Or Court By Which It Is Tried." 

Webster's Dict.

 

Chapter 2 (The Trial By Jury As Defined By Magna Carta) Section 2 Pg 36

Sometimes The Punishment Itself Is Called Judicium,  Judgment; Or,

Rather,  It Was At The Time Of Magna Carta. For Example,  In A Statute

Passed Fifty-One Years After Magna Carta,  It Was Said That A Baker,

For Default In The Weight Of His Bread,  " Debeat Amerciari Vel Subire

Judicium Pillorie;" That Is,  Ought To Be Amerced,  Or Suffer The

Punishment,  Or Judgment,  Of The Pillory. Also That A Brewer,  For

"Selling Ale Contrary To The Assize," "Debeat Amerciari,  Vel Pati

Judicium Tumbrelli "; That Is,  Ought To Be Amerced,  Or Suffer The

Punishment,  Or Judgment,  Of The Tumbrel.   51 Henry 3,  St. 6.

(1266.)

 

Also The "Statutes Of Uncertain Date," (But Supposed To Be Prior To

Edward Iii.,  Or 1326,) Provide,  In Chapters 6,  7,  And 10,  For

"Judgment Of The Pillory."   See 1 Rughead's Statutes,  187,  188. 1

Statutes Of The Realm,  203.

 

Blackstone,  In His Chapter "Of Judgment,  And Its Consequences,"

Says,  "Judgment (Unless Any Matter Be Offered In Arrest Thereof) Follows

Upon Conviction F Being The Pronouncing Of That Punishment Which

Is Expressly Ordained By Law."   Blackstone's Analysis Of The Laws

Of England,  Book 4,  Ch. 29,  Sec. 1. Blackstone's Law Tracts,  126.

 

Coke Says,  "Judicium .. The Judgment Is The Guide And Direction Of

The Execution." 3 Inst. 210.

 

[17] This Precedent From Germany Is Good Authority,  Because The

Trial By Jury Was In Use,  In The Northern Nations Of Europe

Generally,  Long Before Magna Carta,  And Probably From Time

Immemorial; And The Saxons And Normans Were Familiar With It

Before They Settled In England.

 

[18] Beneficium Was The Legal Name Of An Estate Held By A Feudal

Tenure. See Spelman's Glossary.

 

[19]] Contenement Of A Freeman Was The Means Of Living In The

Condition Of A Freeman.

 

[20] Waynage Was A Villein's Plough-Tackle And Carts.

 

[21] Tomlin Says,  "The Ancient Practice Was,  When Any Such Fine

Was Imposed,  To Inquire By A Jury Quantum Inde Regi Dare Valeat

Per Annum,  Salva Sustentatione Sua Et Uxoris Et Libe- Rorum Suorum,

(How Much Is He Able To Give To The King Per Annum,  Saving His

Own Maintenance,  And That Of His Wife And Children). And Since The

Disuse Of Such Inquest,  It Is Never Usual To Assess A Larger Fine Than

A Man Is Able To Pay,  Without Touching The Implements Of His

Livelihood; But To Inflict Corporal Punishment,  Or A Limited

Imprisonment,  Instead Of Such A Fine As Might Amount To

Imprisonment For Life. And This Is The Reason Why Fines In The

King's Courts Are Frequently Denominated Ransoms,  Because The

Penalty Must Otherwise Fall Upon A Man's Person,  Unless It Be

Redeemed Or Ransomed By A Pecuniary Fine."   Tomlin's Law Dict.,

Word Fine.

 

Chapter 2 (The Trial By Jury As Defined By Magna Carta) Section 2 Pg 37

22] Because Juries Were To Fix The Sentence,  It Must Not Be

Supposed That The King Was Obliged To Carry The Sentence Into

Execution; But Only That He Could Not Go Beyond The Sentence. He

Might Pardon,  Or He Might Acquit On Grounds Of Law,  Not

Withstanding The Sentence; But He Could Not Punish Beyond The

Extent Of The Sentence. Magna Carta Does Not Prescribe That The

King Shall Punish According To The Sentence Of The Peers; But Only

That He Shall Not Punish "Unless According To" That Sentence. He

May Acquit Or Pardon,  Notwithstanding Their Sentence Or Judgment;

But He Cannot Punish,  Except According To Their Judgment.

 

[23] The Trial By Battle Was One In Which The Accused Challenged

His Accuser To Single Combat,  And Staked Tbe Question Of His Guilt Or

Innocence On The Result Of The Duel. This Trial Was Introduced Into

England By The Normans,  Within One Hundred And Fifty Years

Before Magna Carta. It Was Not Very Often Resorted To Even By The

Normans Themselves; Probably Never By The Anglo-Saxons,  Unless

In Their Controversies With The Normans. It Was Strongly

Discouraged By Some Of The Norman Princes,  Particularly By Henry

Ii.,  By Whom The Trial By Jury Was Especially Favored. It Is Probable

That The Trial By Battle,  So Far As It Prevailed At All In England,  Was

Rather Tolerated As A Matter Of Chivalry,  Than Authorized As A Matter

Of Law. At Any Rate,  It Is Not Likely That It Was Included In The

"Legem Terrae" Of Magna Carta,  Although Such Duels Have

Occasionally Occurred Since That Time,  And Have,  By Some,  Been

Supposed To Be Lawful. I Apprehend That Nothing Can Be Properly

Said To Be A Part Of Lex Terrae,  Unless It Can Be Shown Either To Have

Been Of Saxon Origin,  Or To Have Been Recognized By Magna Carta.

 

The Trial By Ordeal Was Of Various Kinds. In One Ordeal The Accused

Was Required To Take Hot Iron In His Hand; In Another To Walk

Blindfold Among Red-Hot Ploughshares; In Another To Thrust His Arm

Into Boiling Water; In Another To Be Thrown,  With His Hands And Feet

Bound,  Into Cold Water; In Another To Swallow The Morsel Of

Execration; In The Confidence That His Guilt Or Innocence Would Be

Miraculously Made Known. This Mode Of Trial Was Nearly Extinct At

The Time Of Magna Carta,  And It Is Not Likely That It Was Included In

"Legem Terrae," As That Term Is Used In That Instrument. This Idea Is

Corroborated By The Fact That The Trial By Ordeal Was Specially

Prohibited Only Four Years After Magna Carta,  "By Act Of Parliament

In 3 Henry Iii.,  According To Sir Edward Coke,  Or Rather By An

Order Of The King In Council."   3 Blacks,One 345,  Note.

 

I Apprehend That This Trial Was Never Forced Upon Accused Persons,

But Was Only Allowed To Them,  As An Appeal To God,  From The

Judgment Of A Jury. [24]

 

The Trial By Compurgators Was One In Which,  If The Accused Could

Bring Twelve Of His Neighbors,  Who Would Make Oath That They

Believed Him Innocent,  He Was Held To Be So. It Is Probable That This

Trial Was Really The Trial By Jury,  Or Was Allowed As An Appeal From

A Jury. It Is Wholly Improbable That Two Diferent Modes Of Trial,  So

Nearly Resembling Each Other As This And The Trial By Jury Do,  Should

Prevail At The Same Time,  And Among A Rude People,  Whose Judicial

Chapter 2 (The Trial By Jury As Defined By Magna Carta) Section 2 Pg 38

Proceedings Would Naturally Be Of The Simplest Kind. But If This

Trial Really Were Any Other Than The Trial By Jury,  It Must Have Been

Nearly Or Quite Extinct At The Time Of Magna Carta; And There Is No

Probability That It Was Included In "Legem Terrae."

 

[24] Hallam Says,  "It Appears As If The Ordeal Were Permitted To

Persons Already Convicted By The Verdict Of A Jury."   2 Middle

Ages,  446,  Note.

 

[25] Coke Attempts To Show That There Is A Distinction Between

Amercements And Fines   Admitting That Amercements Must Be

Fixed By One's Peers,  But,  Claiming That,  Fines May Be Fixed By The

Government. (2 Inst. 27,  8 Coke's Reports 38) But There Seems To

Have Been No Ground Whatever For Supposing That Any Such

Distinction Existed At The Time Of Magna Carta. If There Were Any

Such Distinction In The Time Of Coke,  It Had Doubtless Grown Up

Within The Four Centuries That Had Elapsed Since Magna Carta,  And

Is To Be Set Down As One Of The Numberless Inventions Of

Government For Getting Rid Of The Restraints Of Magna Carta,  And

For Taking Men Out Of The Protection Of Their Peers,  And Subjecting

Them To Such Punishments As The Government Chooses To Inflict.

 

The First Statute Of Westminster,  Passed Sixty Years After Magna

Carta,  Treats The Fine And Amercement As Synonymous,  As Follows.

 

"Forasmuch As The Common Fine And Amercement Of The Whole

County In Eyre Of The Justices For False Judgments,  Or For Other

Trespass,  Is Unjustly Assessed By Sheriffs And Baretors In The Shires,

* * It Is Provided,  And The King Wills,  That Frown Henceforth Such

Sums Shall Be Assessed Before The Justices In Eyre,  Afore Their

Departure,  By The Oath Of Knights And Other Honest Men," &C.   3

Edward I.,  Ch. 18. (1275)

 

And In Many Other Statutes Passed After Magna Carta,  The Terms

Fine And Amercement Seem To Be Used Indifferently,  In Prescribing

The Punishments For Offences. As Late As 1461,  (246 Years After

Magna Carta,) The Statute 1 Edward Iv.,  Ch 2,  Speaks Of "Fines.,

Ransoms,  And Amerciaments" As Being Levied Upon Criminals,  As If

They Were The Common Punishments Of Offences.

 

St. 2 And 3 Philip And Mary,  Ch 8,  Uses The Terms,  "Fines,

Forfeitures,  And Amerciaments" Five Times. (1555)

 

St. 5 Elizabeth,  Ch. 13,  Sec. 10,  Uses The Terms "Fines,  Forfeitures,

And Amerciaments."

 

That Amercements Were Fines,  Or Pecuniary Punishments,  Inflicted

For Offences,  Is Proved By The Following Statutes,  (All Supposed To

Have Been Passed Within One Hundred And Fifteen Years After

Magna Cart,) Which Speak Of Amercements As A Species Of

"Judgment," Or Punishment,  And As Being Inflicted For The Same

Offences As Other "Judgments."

 

Thus One Statute Declares That A Baker,  For Default In The Weight Of

Chapter 2 (The Trial By Jury As Defined By Magna Carta) Section 2 Pg 39

His Bread,  "Ought To Be Amerced,  Or Suffer The Judgment Of The

Pillory; And That A Brewer,  For "Selling Ale Contrary To The Assize,"

"Ought To Be Amerced,  Or Suffer The Judgment Of The Tumbrel," -- 51

Henry Iii.,  St. 6. (1266)

 

Among The "Statutes Of Uncertain Date," But Supposed To Be Prior

To Edward Iii.,  (1326),  Are The Following:

 

Chap. 6 Provides That "If A Brewer Break The Assize,  (Fixing The

Price Of Ale,) The First,  Second,  And Third Time,  He Shall Be Amerced;

But The Fourth Time He Shall Suffer Judgment Of The Pillory Without

Redemption."

 

Chap. 7 Provides That "A Butcher That Selleth Swine's Flesh

Measeled,  Or Flesh Dead Of The Murrain,  Or That Buyeth Flesh Of

Jews,  And Selleth The Same Unto Christians,  After He Shall Be

Convict Thereof,  For The First Time He Shall Be Grievously Amerced;

The Second Time He Shall Suffer Judgment Of The Pillory; And The

Third Time He Shall Be Imprisoned And Make Fine; And The Fourth

Time He Shall Forswear The Town."

 

Chap. 10,  A Statute Against Forestalling,  Provides That,  "He That Is

Convict Thereof,  The First Time Shall Be Amerced,  And Shall Lose The

Thing So Bought,  And That According To The Custom Of The Town; He

That Is Convicted The Second Time Shall Have Judgment Of The

Pillory; At The Third Time He Shall Be Imprisoned And Make Fine; The

Fourth Time He Shall Abjure The Town. And This Judgment Shall Be

Given Upon All Manner Of Forestallers,  And Likewise Upon Them That

Have Given Them Counsel,  Help,  Or Favor."   1 Ruffheads Statutes,

187,  188. 1 Statutes Of The Realm,  203.

 

[26] 1 Hume,  Appendix,  L.

 

[27] Blackstone Says,  "Our Ancient Saxon Laws Nominally Punished

Theft With Death,  If Above The Value Of Twelve Pence; But The

Criminal Was Permitted To Redeem His Life By A Pecuniary Ransom,

As Among Their Ancestors,  The Germans,  By A Stated Number Of

Cattle. Bit In The Ninth Year Of Henry The First (1109,) This Power Of

Redemption Was Taken Away,  And All Persons Guilty Of Larceny

Above The Value Off Twelve Pence Were Directed To Be Hanged,

Which Law Continues In Force To This Day."   4 Blackstone,  238

 

I Give This Statement Of Blackstone,  Because The Latter Clause May

Seem To Militate With The Idea,  Which The Former Clause

Corroborates,  Viz.,  That At The Time Of Magna Carta,  Fines Were The

Usual Punishment Of Offenses. But I Think There Is No Probability

That A Law So Unreasonable In Itself,  (Unreasonable Even After

Making All Allowance For The Difference In The Value Of Money,)

And So Contrary To Immemorial Custom,  Could And Did Obtain Any

General Or Speedy Acquiescence Among A People Who Cared Little

For The Authority Of Kings.

 

Maddox,  Writing Of The Period From William The Conqueror To

John,  Says: "The Amercement In Criminal And Common Pleas,

Chapter 2 (The Trial By Jury As Defined By Magna Carta) Section 2 Pg 40

Which Were Wont To Be Imposed During This First Period And

Afterwards,  Were Of So Many Several Sorts,  That It Is Not Easy To

Place Them Under Distinct Heads. Let Them,  For Methods' Sake,  Be

Reduced To The Heads Following: Amercements For Or By Reason Of

Murders And Manslaughters,  For Misdemeanors,  For Disseisins,  For

Recreancy,  For Breach Of Assize,  For Defaults,  For Non-Appearance,

For False Judgment,  And For Not Making Suit,  Or Hue And Cry. To

Them May Be Added Miscellaneous Amercements,  For Trespasses Of

Divers Kinds."   1 Maddox' History Of The Exchequer,  542.

 

[28] Coke,  In His Exposition Of The Words Legem Terrae,  Gives Quite

In Detail The Principles Of The Common Law Governing Arrests,  And

Takes It For Granted That The Words "Nisi Per Legem Terre" Are

Applicable To Arrests,  As Well As To The Indictment,  &C.   2 Inst.,  51,

52.

 

[29] I Cite The Above Extract From Mr. Hallam Solely For The Sake Of

His Authority For Rendering The Word Vel By And; And Not By Any

Means For The Purpose Of Indorsing The Opinion He Suggests,  That

Legem Terrae Authorized "Judgments By Default Or Demurrer,*'

Without The Intervention Of A Jury. He Seems To Imagine That Lex

Terrae,  The Common Law,  At The Time Of Magna Carta,  Included

Everything,  Even To The Practice Of Courts,  That Is,  At This Day,  Called

By The Name Of Common Law; Whereas Much Of What Is Now

Called Common Law Has Grown Up,  By Usurpation,  Since The Time

Of Magna Carta,  In Palpable Violation Of The Authority Of That

Charter. He Says,  "Certainly There Are Many Legal Procedures,

Besides Trial By Jury,  Through Which A Party's Goods Or Person May

Be Taken." Of Course There Are Now Many Such Ways,  In Which A

Party's Goods Or Person Are Taken,  Besides By The Judgment Of A

Jury; But The Question Is,  Whether Such Takings Are Not In Violation

Of Magna Carta.

 

He Seems To Think That,  In Cases Of "Judgment By Default Or

Demurrer," There Is No Need Of A Jury,  And Thence To Infer That

Legem Terrae May Not Have Required A Jury In Those Cases. But This

Opinion Is Founded On The Erroneous Idea That Juries Are Required

Only For Determining Contested Facts,  And Not For Judging Of The

Law. In Case Of Default,  The Plaintif Must Present A Prima Facie Case

Before He Is Entitled To A Judgment; And Magna Carta,  (Supposing It

To Require A Jury Trial In Civil Cases,  As Mr. Hallam Assumes That It

Does,) As Much Requires That This Prima Facie Case,  Both Law And

Fact,  Be Made Out To The Satisfaction Of A Jury,  As It Does That A

Contested Case Shall Be.

 

As For A Demurrer,  The Jury Must Try A Demurrer (Having The Advice

And Assistance Of The Court,  Of Course) As Much As Any Other Matter

Of Law Arising In A Case.

 

Mr. Hallam Evidently Thinks There Is No Use For A Jury,  Except

Where There Is A "Trial"   Meaning Thereby A Contest On Matters Of

Fact. His Language Is,  That "There Are Many Legal Procedures,

Chapter 2 (The Trial By Jury As Defined By Magna Carta) Section 2 Pg 41

Besides Trial By Jury,  Through Which A Party's Goods Or Person May

Be Taken." Now Magna Carta Says Nothing Of Trial By Jury; But Only

Of The Judgment,  Or Sentence,  Of A Jury. It Is Only By Inference That

We Come To The Conclusion That There Must Be A Trial By Jury. Since

The Jury Alone Can Give The Judgment,  Or Sentence,  We Infer That

They Must Try The Case; Because Otherwise They Would Be

Incompetent,  And Would Have No Moral Right,  To Give Judgment.

They Must,  Therefore,  Examine The Grounds,  (Both Of Law And Fact,)

Or Rather Try The Grounds,  Of Every Action Whatsoever,  Whether It Be

Decided On "Default,  Demurrer," Or Otherwise,  And Render Their

Judgment,  Or Sentence,  Thereon,  Before Any Judgment Can Be A Legal

One,  On Which "To Take A Party's Goods Or Person." In Short,  The

Principle Of Magna Carta Is,  That No Judgment Can Be Valid Against

A Party's Goods Or Person,  (Not Even A Judgment For Costs,) Except A

Judgment Rendered By A Jury. Of Course A Jury Must Try Every

Question,  Both Of Law And Fact,  That Is Involved In The Rendering Of

That Judgment. They Are To Have The Assistance And Advice Of The

Judges,  So Far As They Desire Them; But The Judgment Itself Must Be

Theirs,  And Not The Judgment Of The Court.

 

As To "Process Of Attachment For Contempt," It Is Of Course Lawful

For A Judge,  In His Character Of A Peace Officer,  To Issue A Warrant

For The Arrest Of A Man Guilty Of A Contempt,  As He Would For The

Arrest Of Any Other Offender,  And Hold Him To Bail,  (Or,  In Default Of

Bail,  Commit Him To Prison,) To Answer For His Offence Before A

Jury. Or He May Order Him Into Custody Without A Warrant When The

Offence Is Committed In The Judge's Presence.

 

But There Is No Reason Why A Judge Should Have The Power Of

Punishing,  For Contempt,  Any More Than For Any Other Offence. And

It Is One Of The Most Dangerous Powers A Judge Can Have,  Because It

Gives Him Absolute Authority In A Court Of Justice,  And Enables Him

To Tyrannize As He Pleases Over Parties,  Counsel,  Witnesses,  And

Jurors. If A Judge Have Power To Punish For Contempt,  And To

Determine For Himself What Is A Contempt,  The Whole Administration

Of Justice (Or Injustice,  If He Choose To Make It So) Is In His Hands.

And All The Rights Of Jurors,  Witnesses,  Counsel,  And Parties,  Are

Held Subject To His Pleasure,  And Can Be Exercised Only Agreeably

To His Will. He Can Of Course Control The Entire Proceedings In, 

And Consequently The Decision Of,  Every Cause,  By Restraining And

Punishing Every One,  Whether Party,  Counsel,  Witness,  Or Juror, 

Who Presumes To Offer Anything Contrary To His Pleasure. 

 

This Arbitrary Power,  Which Has Been Usurped And Exercised By

Judges To Punish For Contempt,  Has Undoubtedly Had Much To Do In

Subduing Counsel Into Those Servile,  Obsequious,  And Cowardly

Habits,  Which So Universally Prevail Among Them,  And Which Have

Not Only Cost So Many Clients Their Rights,  But Have Also Cost The

People So Many Of Their Liberties.

 

If Any Summary,  Punishment For Contempt Be Ever Necessary,  (As It

Probably Is Not,) Beyond Exclusion For The Time Being From The

Court-Room,  (Which Should Be Done,  Not As A Punishment,  But For

Self-Protection,  And The Preservation Of Order,) The Judgment For It

Chapter 2 (The Trial By Jury As Defined By Magna Carta) Section 2 Pg 42

Should Be Given By The Jury,  (Where The Trial Is Before A Jury,) And

Not By The Court,  For The Jury,  And Not The Court,  Are Really The

Judges. For The Same Reason,  Exclusion From The Court-Room Should

Be Ordered Only By The Jury,  In Cases When The Trial Is Before A Jury,

Because They,  Being The Real Judges And Triers Of The Cause,  Are

Entitled,  If Anybody,  To The Control Of The Court-Room. In Appeal

Courts,  Where No Juries Sit,  It May Be Necessary   Not As A

Punishment,  But For Self-Protection,  And The Maintenance Of Order 

That The Court Should Exercise The Power Of Excluding A Person,  For

The Time Being,  From The Court-Room; But There Is No Reason Why

They Should Proceed To Sentence Him As A Criminal,  Without His

Being Tried By A Jury.

 

If The People Wish To Have Their Rights Respected And Protected In

Courts Of Justice,  It Is Manifestly Of The Last Importance That They

Jealously Guard The Liberty Of Parties,  Counsel,  Witnesses,  And

Jurors,  Against All Arbitrary Power On The Part Of The Court.

 

Certainly Mr. Hallam May Very Well Say That "One May Doubt

Whether These (The Several Eases He Has Mentioned) Were In

Contemplation Of The Framers Of Magna Carta "  That Is,  As

Exceptions To The Rule Requiring That All Judgmcnts,  That Are To Be

Enforced "Against A Party's Goods Or Person,",  Be Rendered By A Jury.

 

Again,  Mr. Hallam Says,  If The Word Vel,  Be Rendered By And,,  "The

Meaning Will Be,  That No Person Shall Be Disseized,  &C.,  Except

Upon A Lawful Cause Of Action.",  This Is True; But It Does Not Follow

That Any Cause Of Action,  Founded On Statute Only,,  Is Therefore A

"Lawful,  Cause Of Action," Within The Meaning Of Legem Terrae,  ,  Or

The Common Law.,  Within The Meaning Of The Legem Terrae,  Of

Magna Carta,  Nothing But A Common Law,  Cause Of Action Is A

"Lawful",  One.

 

 

 

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Pg 43

If Any Evidence,  Extraneous To The History And Language Of Magna

Carta,  Were Needed. To Prove That,  By That Chapter Which

Guaranties The Trial By Jury,  All Was Meant That Has Now Been

Ascribed To It,  And That The Legislation Of The King Was To Be Of

No Authority With The Jury Beyond What They Chose To Allow To It,

And That The Juries Were To Limit The Punishments To Be Inflicted, 

We Should Find That Evidence In Various Sources,  Such As The Laws, 

Customs,  And Characters Of Their Ancestors On The Continent,  And

Of The Northern Europeans Generally; In The Legislation And Customs

That Immediately Succeeded Magna Carta; In The Oaths That Have

At Different Times Been Administered To Jurors,  &C;.,  &C;. This

Evidence Can Be Exhibited Here But Partially. To Give It All Would

Require Too Much Space And Labor

 

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 1 Pg 44

Weakness Of The Regal Authority.

 

Hughes,  In His Preface To His Translation Of Horne's "Mirror Of

Justices," (A Book Written In The Time Of Edward I,  1272 To

1307,) Giving A Concise View Of The Laws Of England Generally,

Says:

 

"Although In The Saxon's Time I Find The Usual Words Of The Acts

Then To Have Been Edictum,  (Edict,) Constitutio,  (Statute,)

Little Mention Being Made Of The Commons,  Yet I Further Find

That,  Tum Demum Leges Vim Et Vigorem Habuerunt,  Cum Fuerunt

Non Modo Institutae Sed Firmatae Approbatione Communitatis." (The

Laws Had Force And Vigor Only When They Were Not Only Enacted,

But Confirmed By The Approval Of The Community.)

 

The Mirror Of Justices Itself Also Says,  (Ch. 1,  Sec. 3,) In

Speaking "Of The First Constitutions Of The Ancient King."

 

"Many Ordinances Were Made By Many Kings,  Until The Time Of The

King That Now Is (Edward I.); The Which Ordinances Were Abused,

Or Not Used By Many,  Nor Very Current,  Because They Were Not Put

In Writing,  And Certainly Published."   Mirror Of Justices,  P. 6.

 

Hallam Says:

 

"The Franks,  Lombards,  And Saxons Seem Alike To Have Been

Jealous Of Judicial Authority; And Averse To Surrendering What Concerned

Every Man's Private Right,  Out Of The Hands Of His Neighbors And

Equals."   1 Middle Ages,  271.

 

The "Judicial Authority," Here Spoken Of,  Was The Authority Of

The Kings,  (Who At That Time United The Office Of Both

Legislators And Judges,),  And Not Of A Separate Department Of

Government,  Called The Judiciary,  Like What Has Existed In More

Modern Times. [1]

 

Hume Says:

 

"The Government Of The Germans,  And That Of All The Northern

Nations,  Who Established Themselves On The Ruins Of Rome,  Was

Always Extremely Free; And Those Fierce People,  Accustomed To

Independence And Inured To Arms,  Were More Guided By

Persuasion,  Than Authority,  In The Submission Which They Paid To Their

Princes. The Military Despotism,  Which Had Taken Place N The

Roman Empire,  And Which,  Previously To The Irruption Of Those

Conquerors,  Had Sunk The Genius Of Men,  And Destroyed Every Noble

Principle Of Science And Virtue,  Was Unable To Resist The

Vigorous Efforts Of A Free People,  And Europe,  As From A New

Epoch,  Rekindled Her Ancient Spirit,  And Shook Off The Base

Servitude To Arbitrary Will And Authority Under Which She Had So

Long Labored. The Free Constitutions Then Established,  However

Impaired By The Encroachments Of Succeeding Princes,  Still

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 1 Pg 45

Impaired By The Encroachments Of Succeeding Princes,  Still

Preserve An Air Of Independence And Legal Administration,  Which

Distinguished The European Nations; And If That Part Of The Globe

Maintain Sentiments Of Liberty,  Honor,  Equity,  And Valor,

Superior To The Rest Of Mankind,  It Owes These Advantages Chiefly

To The Seeds Implanted By Those Generous Barbarians.

 

"The Saxons,  Who Subdued Britain,  As They Enjoyed Great Liberty

In Their Own Country,  Obstinately Retained That Invaluable

Possession In Their New Settlement; And They Imported Into This

Island The Same Principles Of Independence,  Which They Had

Inherited From Their Ancestors. The Chieftains,  ( For Such They

Were,  More Than Kings Or Princes,) Who Commanded Them In Those

Military Expeditions,  Still Possessed A Very Limited Authority;

And As The Saxons Exterminated,  Rather Than Subdued The Ancient

Inhabitants,  They Were,  Indeed,  Transplanted Into A New

Territory,  But Preserved Unaltered All Their Civil And Military

Insfitutions. The Language Was Pure Saxon; Even The Names Of

Places,  Which Often Remain While The Tongue Entirely  Changes,

Were Almost All Affixed By The Conquerors; The Manners And

Customs Were Wholly German; And The Same Picture Of A Fierce And

Bold Liberty,  Which Is Drawn By The Masterly Pen Of Tacitus,  Will

Suit Those Founders Of The English Government. The King,  So Far

From Being Invested With Arbitrary Power,  Was Only Considered As

The First Among The Citizens; His Authority Depended More On His

Personal Qualities Than On His Station; He Was Even So Far On A

Level With The People,  That A Stated Price Was Fixed For His

Head,  And A Legal Fine Was Levied Upon His Murderer,  Which Though

Proportionate To His Station,  And Superior To That Paid For The

Life Of A Subject,  Was A Sensible Mark Of His Subordination To

The Community."   1 Hume,  Appendix,  L.

 

Stuart Says:

 

"The Saxons Brought Along With Them Into Britain Their Own

Customs,  Language,  And Civil Institutions. Free In Germany,  They

Renounced Not Their Independence,  When They Had Conquered.

Proud From Victory,  And With Their Swords In Their Hands,  Would

They Surrender Their Liberties To A Private Man? Would Temporary

Laders,  Limited In Their Powers,  And Unprovided In Resources,

Ever Think To Usurp An Authority Over Warriors,  Who Considered

Themselves As Their Equals,  Were Impatient Of Control,  And

Attached With Devoted Zeal To Their Privileges? Or,  Would They

Find Leisure To Form Resolutions,  Or Opportunities To Put Them In

Practice,  Amidst The Tumult And Confusion Of Those Fierce And

Bloody Wars,  Which Their Nations First Waged With The Britons,

And Then Engaged In Among Themselves? Sufficiently Flattered In

Leading The Armies Of Their Countrymen,  The Ambition Of

Commanders Could As Little Suggest Such Designs,  As The Liberty

Of The People Could Submit To Them. The Conquerors Of Britain

Retained Their Independence; And This Island Saw Itself Again In

That Free State In Which The Roman Arms Had Discovered It.

 

"The Same Firmness Of Character,  And Generosity Of Manners,

Which,  In General,  Distinguished The Germans,  Were Possessed In

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 1 Pg 46

An Eminent Degree By The Saxons; And While We Endeavor To Unfold

Their Political Institutions,  We Must Perpetually Turn Our

Observation To That Masterly Picture In Which The Roman Historian

Has Described These Nations. In The Woods Of Germany Shall We

Find The Principles Which Directed The State Of Land,  In The

Different Kingdoms Of Europe; And There Shall We Find The

Foundation Of Those Ranks Of Men,  And Of Those Civil

Arrangements,  Which The Barbarians Everywhere Established; And

Which The English Alone Have Had The Good Fortune,  Or The Spirit,

To Preserve."   Stuart On The Constitution Of England,  P. 59 - 61.

 

"Kings They (The Germans) Respected As The First Magistrates Of

The State; But The Authority Possessed By Them Was Narrow And

Limited."   Ditto,  P. 134.

 

"Did He,  (The King,) At Any Time,  Relax His Activity And Martial

Ardor,  Did He Employ His Abilities To The Prejudice Of His

Nation,  Or Fancy He Was Superior To The Laws; The Same Power

Which Raised Him To Honor,  Humbled And Degraded Him. The

Customs And Councils Of His Country Pointed Out To Him His

Duty; And If He Infringed On The Former,  Or Disobeyed The Latter, 

A Fierce People Set Aside His Authority.

 

"His Long Hair Was The Only Ornament He Affected,  And To Be

Foremost To Attack An Enemy Was His Chief Distinction.

Engaged In Every Hazardous Expedition,  He Was A Stranger To

Repose; And,  Rivalled By Half The Heroes Of His Tribe,  He Could

Obtain Little Power. Anxious And Watchful For The Public

Interest,  He Felt Every Moment His Dependence,  And Gave

Proofs Of His Suhmission.

 

"He Attended The General Assembly Of His Nation,  And Was Allowed

The Privilege To Harangue It First; But The Arts Of Persuasion,

Though Known And Respected By A Rude People,  Were Unequally

Opposed To The Prejudices And Passions Of Men."   Ditto,  P. 135 - 6.

 

"The Authority Of A Saxon Mnarch Was Not More Considerable. The

Saxons Submitted Not To The Arbitrary Rule Of Princes. They

Administered An Oath To Their Sovereigns,  Which Bound Them To

Aeknowledge The Laws,  And To Defend The Rights Of The Church And

People; And If They Forgot This Obligation,  They Forfeited Their

Office. In Both Countries,  A Price Was Affixed On Kings,  A Fine

Expiated Their Murder,  As Well As That Of The Meanest Citizen;

And The Smallest Violation Of Ancient Usage,Or The Least Step

Towards Tyranny,  Was Always Dangerous,  And Often Fatal To Them." 

Ditto,  P. 189-40.

 

"They Were Not Allowed To Impose Taxes On The Kingdom."   Ditto,

P. 146.

 

"Like The German Monarchs,  They Deliberated In The General

Assembly Of The Nation; But Their Legislative Authority Was Not

Much Respected; And Their Assent Was Considered In No Better

Light Than As A Form. This,  However,  Was Their Chief Prerogative;

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 1 Pg 47

And They Employed It To Acquire An Ascendant In The State. To Art

And Insinuation They Turned,  As Their Only Resource,  And

Flattered A People Whom They Could Not Awe; But Address,  And The

Abilities To Persuade,  Were A Weak Compensation For The Absence

Of Real Power.

 

"They Declared War,  It Is Said,  And Made Peace. In Both Cases,

However,  They Acted As The Instruments Of The State,  And Put In

Execution The Resolutions Which Its Councils Had Decreed. If,

Indeed,  An Enemy Had Invaded The Kingdoms,  And Its Glory And Its

Safety Were Concerned,  The Great Lords Took The Field At The Call

Of Their Sovereign. But Had A Sovereign Declared War Against A

Neighboring State,  Without Requiring Their Advice,  Or If He Meant

To Revenge By Arms An Insult Offered To Him By A Subject,  A

Haughty And Independent Nobility Refused Their Assistance. These

They Considered As The Quarrels Of The King,  And Not Of The

Nation; And In All Such Emergencies He Could Only Be Assisted By

His Retainers And Dependents."   Ditto,  P. 147   8.

 

"Nor Must We Imagine That The Saxon,  Any More Than The German

Monarchs,  Succeeded Each Other In A Lineal Descent,  [2] Or That

They Disposed Of The Crown At Their Pleasure. In Both Countries,

The Free Election Of The People Filled The Throne; And Their

Choice Was The Only Rule By Which Princes Reigned. The

Succession,  Accordingly,  Of Their Kings Was Often Broken And

Interrupted,  And Their Depositions Were Frequent And Groundless.

The Will Of A Prince Whom They Had Long Respected,  And The Favor

They Naturally Transferred To His Descendant,  Made Them Often

Advance Him To The Royal Dignity; But The Crown Of His Ancestor

He Cnsidered As The Gift Of The People,  And Neither Expected Nor

Claimed It As A Right."   Ditto,  P. 151   3.

 

In Germany "It Was The Business Of The Great To Command In War,

And In Peace They Distributed Justice.

 

"The Princes In Germany Were Earls In England. The Great

Contended In Both Countries In The Number Of Their Retainers,  And

In That Splendor And Magnificence Which Are So Alluring To A Rude

People; And Though They Joined To Set Bounds To Regal Power,  They

Were Often Animated Against Each Other With The Fiercest Hatred.

To A Proud And Impatient Nobility It Seemed Little And Unsuiting

To Give Or Accept Compositions For The Injuries They Committed Or

Received; And Their Vassals Adopting Their Resentment And

Passions,  War And Bloodshed Alone Could Terminate Their Quarrels.

What Necessarily Resulted From Their Situation In Society,  Was

Continued As A Privilege; And The Great,  In Both Countries,  Made

War,  Of Their Private Authority,  On Their Enemies. The Saxon

Earls Even Carried Their Arms Against Their Sovereigns; And,

Surrounded With Retainers,  Or Secure In Fortresses And Castles,

They Despised Their Resentment,  And Defied Their Power.

 

"The Judges Of The People,  They Presided In Both Countries In

Courts Of Law. [3] The Particular Districts Over Which They

Exerted Their Authority Were Marked Out In Germany By The Council

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 1 Pg 48

Of The State; And In England Their Jurisdiction Extended Over The

Fiefs And Other Territories They Possessed. All Causes,  Both

Civil And Criminal,  Were Tried Before Them; And They Judged,

Except In Cases Of The Utmost Importance,  Without Appeal. They

Were Even Allowed To Grant Pardon To Criminals,  And To Correct By

Their Clemency The Rigors Of Justice.  Nor Did The Sovereign

Exercise Any Authority In Their Lands. In These His Officers

Formed No Courts,  And His Writ Was Disregarded.

 

"They Had Officers,  As Well As The King,  Who Collected Their

Revenues,  And Added To Their Greatness; And The Inhabitants Of

Their Lands They Distinguished By The Name Of Subjects.

 

"But To Attend The General Assembly Of Their Nation Was The Chief

Prerogative Of The German And Saxon Princes; And As They

Consulted The Interest Of Their Country,  And Eliberated

Concerning Matters Of State,  So In The King's Court,  Of Which

Also They Were Members,  They Assisted To Pronounce Judgment In

The Complaints And Appeals Which Were Lodged In It."   Ditto,  P.

158 To 165.

 

Henry Says:

 

"Nothing Can Be More Evident Than This Important Truth; That Our

Anglo-Saxon Kings Were Not Absolute Monarchs; But That Their

Powers And Prerogatives Were Limited By The Laws And Customs Of

The Country. Our Saxon Ancestors Had Been Governed By Limited

Monarchs In Their Native Seats On The Continent; And There Is Not

The Least Appearance Or Probability That They Relinquished Their

Liberties,  And Submitted To Absolute Government In Their New

Settlements In This Island. It Is Not To Be Imagined That Men,

Whose Reigning Passion Was The Love Of Liberty,  Would Willingly

Resign It; And Their New Sovereigns,  Who Had Been Their

Fellow-Soldiers,  Had Certainly No Power To Compel Them To Such A

Resignation."   3 Henry's History Of Great Britain,  358.

 

Mackintosh Says:"The Saxon Chiefs,  Who Were Called. Kings,

Originally Acquired Power By The Same Natural Causes Which Have

Gradually,  And Everywhere,  Raised A Few Men Above Their Fellows.

They Were,  Doubtless,  More Experienced,  More Skillful,  More

Brave,  Or More Beautiful,  Than Those Who Followed Them. * * A

King Was Powerful In War By The Lustre Of His Arms,  And The

Obvious Necessity Of Obedience. His Influence In Peace Fluctuated

With His Personal Character. In The Progress Of Usage His Power

Became More Fixed And More Limited. * * It Would Be Very

Unreasonable To Suppose That The Northern Germans Who Had

Conquered England,  Had So Far Changed Their Characteristic Habits

From The Age Of Tacitus,  That The Victors Became Slaves,  And That

Their Generals Were Converted Into Tyrants."   Mackintosh's Hist.

Of England,  Ch. 2. 45 Lardner's Cab. Cyc.,  73-4.

 

Rapin,  In His Discourse On The "Origin And Nature Of The English

Constitution," Says:

 

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 1 Pg 49

"There Are But Two Things The Saxons Did Not Think Proper To

Trust Their Kings With; For Being Of Like Passions With Other

Men,  They Might Very Possibly Abuse Them; Namely,  The Power Of

Changing The Laws Enacted By Consent Of King And People; And The

Power Of Raising Taxes At Pleasure.From These Two Articles Sprung

Numberless Branches Concerning The Liberty And Property Of The

Subject,  Which The King Cannot Touch,  Without Breaking The

Constitution,  And They Are The Distinguishing Character Of The

English Monarchy. The Prerogatives Of The Crown,  And The Rights

And Privileges Of The People,  Flowing From The Two Fore-Mentioned

Articles,  Are The Ground Of All The Laws That From Time To Time

Have Been Made By Unanimous Consent Of King And People. The

English Government Consists In The Strict Union Of The King's

Prerogatives With The People's Liberties. * * But When Kings

Arose,  As Some There Were,  That Aimed At Absolute Power,  By

Changing The Old,  And Making New Laws,  At Pleasure; By Imposing

Illegal Taxes On The People; This Excellent Government Being,  In

A Manner,  Dissolved By These Destructive Measures,  Confusion And

Civil Wars Ensued,  Which Some Very Wrongfully Ascribe To The

Fickle And Restless Temper Of The English."   Rapin's Preface To

His History Of England.

 

Hallam Says That Among The Saxons,  "The Royal Authority Was

Weak."   2 Middle Ages,  403.

 

But Although The King Himself Had So Little Authority,  That It

Cannot Be Supposed For A Moment That His Laws Were Regarded As

Imperative By The People,  It Has Nevertheless Been Claimed,  In

Modern Times,  By Some Who Seem Determined To Find Or Make A

Precedent For The Present Legislative Authority Of Parliament,

That His Laws Were Authoritative,  When Assented To By The Witena

- Gemote,  Or Assembly Of Wise Men   That Is,  The Bishops And

Barons. But This Assembly Evidently Had No Legislative Power ,

Whatever. The King Would Occasionally Invite The Bishops And

Barons To Meet Him For Consultation On Public Affairs,  Simply As

A Council,  And Not As A Legislative Body. Such As Saw Fit To

Attend,  Did So. If They Were Agreed Upon What Ought To Be Done,

The King Would Pass A Law Accordingly,  And The Barons And Bishops

Would Then Return And Inform The People Orally What Laws Had Been

Passed,  And Use Their Influence With Them To Induce Them To

Conform To The Law Of The King,  And The Recommendation Of The

Council. ' And The People No Doubt Were Much More Likely To

Accept A Law Of The King,  If It Had Been Approved By This

Council,  Than If It Had Not. But It Was Still Only A Law Of The

King,  Which They Obeyed Or Disregarded According To Their Own

Notions Of Expediency. The Numbers Who Usually Attended This

Council Were Too Small To Admit Of The Supposition That They Had

Any Legislative Authority Whatever,  To Impose Laws Upon The

People Against Their Will.

 

Lingard Says:

 

"It Was Necessary That The King Should Obtain The Assent Of These

(The Members O The Witena-Gemotes) To All Legislative Enactments;

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 1 Pg 50

Because,  Without Their Acquiescence And Support,  It Was

Impossible To Carry Them Into Execution. To Many Charters (Laws)

We Have The Signatures Of The Witan. They Seldom Exceed Thirty In

Number; They Never Amount To Sixty."   1 Lingard; 486.

 

It Is Ridiculous To Suppose That The Assent Of Such An Assembly

Gave Any Authority To The Laws Of The King,  Or Had Any Influence

In Securing Obedience To Them,  Otherwise Than By Way Of

Persuasion. If This Body Had Had Any Real Legislative Authority,

Such As Is Accorded To Legislative Bodies Of The Present Day,

They Would Have Made Themselves At Once The Most Conspicuous

Portion Of The Government,  And Would Have Left Behind Them

Abundant Evidence Of Their Power,  Instead Of The Evidence Simply

Of Their Assent To  A Few Laws Passed By The King.

 

More Than This. If This Body Had Had Any Real Legislative

Authority,  They Would Have Constituted An Aristocracy,  Having,  In

Conjunction With The King,  Absolute Power Over The People.

Assembling Voluntarily,  Merely On The Invitation Of The King;

Deputed By Nobody But Themselves; Representing Nobody But

Themselves; Responsible To Nobody But Themselves; Their

Legislative Authority,  If They Had Had Any,  Would Of Necessity

Have Made The Government The Government Of An Aristocracy

Merely,  And The People Slaves,  Of Course. And This Would

Necessarily Have Been The Picture That History Would Have

Given Us Of The Anglo-Saxon Government,  And Of Anglo-Saxon

Liberty.

 

The Fact That The People Had No Representation In This Assembly,

And The Further Fact That,  Through Their Juries Alone,  They

Nevertheless Maintained That Noble Freedom,  The Very Tradition Of

Which (After The Substance Of The Thing Itself Has Ceased To

Exist) Has Constituted The Greatest Pride And Glory Of The Nation

To This Day,  Prove That This Assembly Exercised No Authority

Which Juries Of The People Acknowledged,  Except At Their Own

Discretion. [4]

 

There Is Not A More Palpable Truth,  In The History Of The

Anglo-Saxon Government,  Than That Stated In The Introduction To

Gilbert's History Of The Common Pleas,  [5] Viz.. "That The

County Aud Hundred Courts," (To Which Should Have Been Added

The Other Courts In Which Juries Sat,  The Courts-Baron And

Court-Leet,) "In Those Times Were The Real And Only Parliaments

Of The Kingdom." And Why Were They The Real And Only Parliaments

Of The Kingdom? Solely Because,  As Will Be Hereafter Shown,  The

Juries In Those Courts Tried Causes On Their Intrinsic Merits,

According To Their Own Ideas Of Justice,  Irrespective Of The Laws

Agreed Upon By Kings,  Priests,  And Barons; And Whatever

Principles They Uniformly,  Or Perhaps Generally,  Enforced,  And

None Others,  Became Practically The Law Of The Land As Matter Of

Course. [6]

 

Finally,  On This Point. Conclusive Proof That The Legislation Of

The King Was Of Little Or No Authority,  Is Found In The Fact That

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 1 Pg 51

The Kings Enacted So Few Laws. If Their Laws Had Been Received As

Authoritative,  In The Manner That Legislative Enactments Are At

This Day,  They Would Have Been Making Laws Continually. Yet The

Codes Of The Most Celebrated Kings Are Very Small,  And Were

Little More Than Compilations Of Immemorial Customs. The Code Of

Alfred Would Not Fill Twelve Pages Of The Statute Book Of

Massachusetts,  And Was Little Or Nothing Else Than A Compilation

Of The Laws Of Moses,  And The Saxon Customs,  Evidently Collected

From Considerations Of Convenience,  Rather Than Enacted On The

Principle Of Authority. The Code Of Edward The Confessor Would

Not Fill Twenty Pages Of The Statute Book Of Massachusetts,  And,

Says Blackstone,  "Seems To Have Been No More Than A New Edition,

Or Fresh Promulgation Of Alfred's Code,  Or Dome-Book,  With Such

Additions And Improvements As The Experience Of A Century And A

Half Suggested."   1 Blackstone,  66. [7]

 

The Code Of Wiliiam The Conqueror [8] Would Fill Less Than Seven

Pages Of The Statute Book Of Massachusetts; And Most Of The Laws

Contained In It Are Taken From The Laws Of The Preceding Kings,

And Especially Of Edward The Confessor (Whose Laws William

Swore To Observe); But Few Of His Own Being Added.

 

The Codes Of The Other Saxon And Norman Kings Were,  As A General

Rule,  Less Voluminous Even Than These That Have Been Named; And

Probably Did Not Exceed Them In Originality. [9] The Norman

Princes,  From William The Conqueror To John,  I Think Without

Exception,  Bound Themselves,  And,  In Order To Mqintain Their

Thrones,  Were Obliged To Bind Themselves,  To Observe The Ancient

Laws And Customs,  In Other Words; The "Lex Terrae," Or "Common

Law" Of The Kingdom. Even Magna Carta Contains Hardly Anything

Other Than This Same "Common Law," With Some New Securities For

Its Observance. 

 

How Is This Abstinence From Legislation,  On The Part Of The

Ancient Kings,  To Be Accounted For,  Except On The Supposition

That The People Would Accept,  And Juries Enforce,  Few Or No New

Laws Enacted By Their Kings? Plainly It Can Be Accounted. For In

No Ether Way. In Fact,  All History Informs Us That Anciently The

Attempts Of The Kings To Introduce Or Establish New Laws,  Met

With Determined Resistance From The People,  And Generally

Resulted In Failure "Nolumus Leges Angliae Mutari" (We Will That

The Laws Of England Be Not Changed,) Was A Determined Principle

With The Anglo-Saxons,  From Which They Seldom Departed,  Up To

The Time Of Magna Carta,  And Indeed Until Long After. [10]

 

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 2 Pg 52

The Ancient Common Law Juries Were Mere Courts Of

Conscience.

 

But It Is In The Administration Of Justice,  Or Of Law,  That The

Freedom Or Subjection Of A People Is Tested. If This

Administration Be In Accordance With The Arbitrary Will Of The

Legislator   That Is,  If His Will,  As It Appears In His Statutes,

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 2 Pg 53

Be The Highest Rule Of Decision Known To The Judicial Tribunals,  

The Government Is A Despotism,  And The People Are Slaves. If,  On

The Other Hand,  The Rule Of Decision Be These Principles Of

Natural Equity And Justice,  Which Constitute,  Or At Least Are

Embodied In,  The General Conscience Of Mankind,  The People Are

Free In Just So Far As That Conscience Is Enlightened.

 

That The Authority Of The King Was Of Little Weight With The

Judicial Tribunals,  Must Necessarily Be Inferred From The Fact

Already Stated,  That His Authority Over The People Was But Weak.

If The Authority Of His Laws Had Been Paramount In The Judicial

Tribunals,  It Would Have Been Paramount With The People,  Of

Course; Because They Would Have Had No Alternative But

Submission. The Fact,  Then,  That His Laws Were Not Authoritative

With The People,  Is Proof That They Were Not Authoritative With

The Tribunals   In Other Words,  That They Were Not,  As Matter Of

Course,  Enforced By The Tribunals.

 

But We Have Additional Evidence That,  Up To The Time Of Magna

Carta,  The Laws Of The King Were Not Binding Upon The Judicial

Tribunals; And If They Were Not Binding Before That Time,  They

Certainly Were Not Afterwards,  As Has Already Been Shown From

Magna Carta Itself. It Is Manifest From All The Accounts We Have

Of The Courts In Which Juries Sat,  Prior To Magna Carta,  Such As

The Court-Baron,  The Hundred Court,  The Court-Leet,  And The

County Court,  That They Were Mere Courts Of Conscience,  And That

The Juries Were The Judges,  Deciding Causes According To Their

Own Notions Of Equity,  And Not According To Any Laws Of The King,

Unless They Thought Them Just.

 

These Courts,  It Must Be Considered,  Were Very Numerous,  And Held

Very Frequent Sessions. There Were Probably Seven,  Eight,  Or Nine

Hundred Courts A Month,  In The Kingdom; The Object Being,  As

Blackstone Says,  "To Bring Justice Home To Every Man's Door." (3

Blackstone,  80.) The Number Of The County Courts,  Of Course,

Corresponded To The Number Of Counties,  (36.) The Court-Leet Was

The Criminal Court For A District Less Than A County. The Hundred

Court Was The Court For One Of Those Districts Anciently Called A

Hundred,  Because,  At The Time Of Their First Organization For

Judicial Purposes,  They Comprised,  (As Is Supposed) But A Hundred

Families. [11] The Court-Baron Was The Court For A Single Manor,

And There Was A Court For Every Manor In The Kingdom. All These

Courts Were Holden As Often As Once In Three Or Five Weeks; The

County Court Once A Month. The King's Judges Were Present At None

Of These Courts; The Only Officers In Attendance Being Sheriffs

Bailiff's,  And Stewards,  Merely Ministerial,  And Not Judicial,

Officers; Doubtless Incompetent,  And,  If Not Incompetent,

Untrustworthy,  For Giving The Juries Any Reliable Information In

Matters Of Law,  Beyond What Was Already Known To The Jurors

Themselves.

 

And Yet These Were The Courts,  In Which Was Done All The Judicial

Business,  Both Civil And Criminal,  Of The Nation,  Except Appeals, 

And Some Of The More Important And Difficult Cases. [12] It Is 

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 2 Pg 54

Plain That The Juries,  In These Courts,  Must,  Of Necessity,  Have

Been  The Sole Judges Of All Matters Of Law Whatsoever; Because

There Was No One Present,  But Sheriffs,  Bailiffs,  And Stewards, 

To Give Them Any Instructions; And Surely It Will Not Be Pretended

That The Jurors Were Bound To Take Their Law From Such Sources

As These.

 

In The Second Place,  It Is Manifest That The Principles Of Law,

By Which The Juries Determined Causes,  Were,  As A General Rule,

Nothing Else Than Their Own Ideas Of Natural Equity,  And Not Any

Laws Of The King; Because But Few Laws Were Enacted,  And Many Of

Those Were Not Written,  But Only Agreed Upon In Council. [13] Of

Those That Werewritten,  Few Copies Only Were Made,  (Printing

Being Then Unknown,) And Not Enough To Supply A11,  Or Any

Considerable Number,  Of These Numerous Courts. Beside And

Beyond All This,  Few Or None Of The Jurors Could Have Read The Laws,  If

They Had Been Written; Because Few Or None Of The Common People

Could,  At Thattime,  Read. Not Only Were The Common People Unable

To Read Their Own Language,  But,  At The Time Of Magna Carta,  The

Laws Were Written In Latin,  A Language That Could Be Read By Few

Persons Except The Priests,  Who Were Also The Lawyers Of The

Nation. Mackintosh Says,  "The First Act Of The House Of Commons

Composed And Recorded In The English Tongue," Was In 1415,  Two

Centuries After Magna Carta. [14]. Up To This Time,  And For Some

Seventy Years Later,  The Laws Were Generally Written Either In Latin

Or French; Both Languages Incapable Of Being Read By The Common

 People,  As Well Normans As Saxons; And One Of Them,  The Latin, 

 Not Only Incapable Of Being Read By Them,  But Of Beingeven

Understood When It Was Heard By Them.

 

To Suppose That The People Were Bound To Obey,  And Juries To

Enforce,  Laws,  Many Of Which Were Unwritten,  None Of Which They

Could Read,  And The Larger Part Of Which (Those Written In Latin)

They Could Not Translate,  Or Understand When They Heard Them

Read,  Is Equivalent To Supposing The Nation Sunk In The Most

Degrading Slavery,  Instead Of Enjoying A Liberty Of Their Own

Choosing.

 

Their Knowledge Of The Laws Passed By The King Was,  Of Course,

Derived Only From Oral Information; And The Good Laws,"As Some Of

Them Were Called,  In Contradistinction To Others   Those Which

The People At Large Esteemed To Be Good Laws   Were Doubtless

Enforced By The Juries,  And The Others,  As A General Thing,

Disregarded. [15]

 

That Such Was The Nature Of Judicial Proceedings,  And Of The

Power Of Juries,  Up To The Time Of Magna Carta,  Is Further Shown

By The Following Authorities.

 

"The Sheriff's And Bailiffs Caused The Free Tenants Of Their

Bailiwics To Meet At Their Counties And Hundreds; At Which

Justice Was So Done,  That Every One So Judged His Neighbor By

Such Judgment As A Man Could Not Elsewhere Receive In The Like

Cases,  Until Such Times As The Customs Of The Realm Were Put In

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 2 Pg 55

Writing,  And Certainly Published.

 

"And Although A Freeman Commonly Was Not To Serve (As A Juror Or

Judge) Without His Assent,  Nevertheless It Was Assented Unto That

Free Tenants Should Meet Together In The Counties And Hundreds,

And Lords Courts,  If They Were Not Specially Exempted To Do Such

Suits,  And There Judged Their Neighbors."   Mirror Of Justices,

P. 7,  8.

 

Gilbert,  In His Treatise On The Constitution Of England,  Says:

 

"In The County Courts,  If The Debt Was Above Forty Shillings,

There Issued A Justicies (A Commission) To The Sheriff,  To Enable

Him To Hold Such A Plea,  Where The Suitors (Jurors) Are Judges Of

The Law And Fact."   Gilbert's Cases In Law And Equity,  &C;.,

&C;.,  456.

 

All The Ancient Writs,  Given In Glanville,  For Summoning Jurors,

Indicate That The Jurors Judged Of Everything,  On Their

Consciences Only. The Writs Are In This Form:

 

"Summon Twelve Free And Legal Men (Or Sometimes Twelve

Knights)

To Be In Court,  Prepared Upon Their Oaths To Declare Whether A Or

B Have The Greater Right To The Land {Or Other Thing) In

Question." See Writs In Beames' Glanville,  P. 54 To 70,  And 233 

306 To 832.

 

Crabbe,  Speaking Of The Time Of Henry I.,  (1100 To 1135,)

Recognizes The Fact That The Jurors Were The Judges. He Says:

 

"By One Law,  Every One Was To Be Tried By His Peers,  Who Were Of

The Same Neighborhood As Himself. * *By Another Law,  The Judges,

For So The Jury Were Called,  Were To Be Chosen By The Party

Impleaded,  After The Manner Of The Danish Nem-Bas; By Which,

Probably,  Is To Be Understood That The Defendant Had The Liberty

Of Taking Exceptions To,  Or Challenging The Jury,  As It Was

Afterwards Called."   Crabbe's History Of The English Law,  P. 55.

 

Reeve Says:

 

"The Great Court For Civil Business Was The County Court; Held

Once Every Four Weeks. Here The Sheriff Presided; But The Suitors

Of The Court,  As They Were Called,  That Is,  The Freemen Or

Landholders Of The County,  Were The Judges; And The Sheriff Was

To Execute The Judgment.

 

"The Hundred Court Was Held Before Some Bailiff; The Leet Before

The Lord Of The Manor's Steward.[16]

 

"Out Of The County Court Was Derived An Inferior Court Of Civil

Jurisdiction,  Called The Court-Baron. This Was Held From Three

Weeks To Three Weeks,  And Was In Every Respect Like The County

Court;" (That Is,  The Jurors Were Judges In It;) "Only The Lord

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 2 Pg 56

To Whom This Franchise Was Granted,  Or His Steward Presided

Instead Of The Sheriff;"   1 Reeve's History Of The English Law,

P. T., 

 

Chief Baron Gilbert Says:

 

"Besides The Tenants Of The King,  Which Held Per Baroniam,  (By

The Right Of A Baron,) And Did Suit And Service (Served As

Judges) At His Own Court; And The Burghers And Tenants In Ancient

Demesne,  That Did Suit And Service (Served As Jurors Or Judges)

In Their Own Court In Person),  And In The King's By Proxy,  There

Was Also A Set Of Freeholders,  That Did Suit Aud Service (Served

As Jurors) At The County Court. These Were Such As Anciently Held

Of The Lord Of The County,  And By The Escheats Of Earldoms Had

Fallen To The King; Or Such As Were Granted Out By Service To

Hold Of The King,  But With Particular Reservation To Do Suit And

Service (Serve As Jurors) Before The Kng's Bailiff; Because It

Was Necessary The Sheriff,  Or Bailiff Of The King,  Should Have

Suitors (Jurors) At The County Court,  That The Business Might Be

Despatched. These Suitors Are The Pares (Peers) Of The County

Court,  And Indeed The Judges Of It; As The Pares (Peers) Were The

Judges In Every Court-Baron; And Therefore The King's Bailiff

Having A Court Before Him,  There Must Be Pares Or Judges,  For The

Sheriff Himself Is Not A Judge; And Though The Style Of The Court

Is Curia Prima Comitatus E. C. Milit.' Vicecom' Comitat' Praed'

Tent' Apud B.,  &C;. (First Court Of The County,  E. C. Knight,

Sheriff Of The Aforesaid County,  Held At B.,  &C;.); By Which It

Appears That The Court Was The S1ieriff's; Yet,  By The Old Feudal

Constititions,  The Lord Was Not Judge,  But The Pares (Peers)

Only; So That,  Even In A Justicies,  Which Was A Commission To The

Sheriff To Hold Plea Of More Than Was Allowed Hy The Natural

Jurisdiction Of A County Court,  The Pares (Peers,  Jurors) Only

Were Judges,  And Not The Sheriff; Because It Was To Hold Plea In

The Same Manner As They Used To Do In That (The Lord's) Court." 

Gilbert On The Court Of Exchequer,  Ch. 5.  61- 2.

 

"It Is A Distinguishing Feature Of The Feudal System,  To Make

Civil Jurisdiction Necessarily,  And Criminal Jurisdiction

Ordinarily,  Coextensive With Tenure; And Accordingly There Is

Inseparably Incident To Every Manor A Court-Baron (Curia

Baronum),  Being A Court In Which The Freeholders Of The Manor Are

The Sole Judges,  But In Which The Lord,  By Himself Or More

Commonly By His Steward,  Presides."   Political Dictionary,  Word

Manor.

 

The Same Work,  Speaking Of The County Court,  Says: "The Judges

Were The Freeholders Who Did Suit To The Court." See Word Courts.

 

"In The Case Of Freeholders Attending As Suitors,  The County

Court Or Court-Baron.,  (As In The Case Of The Ancient Tenants Per

Baroniam Attending Parliament,) The Suitors Are The Judges Of The

Court,  Both For Law And For Fact,  And The Sheriff Or The Under

Sheriff In The County Court,  And The Lord Or His Steward In The

Court-Baron,  Are Only Presiding Officers,  With No Judicial

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 2 Pg 57

Authority."   Political Dictionary,  Word Suit.

 

"Court,  (Curtis,  Curia Aula); The Space Enclosed By The Walls Of

A Feudal Residence,  In Which The Followers Of A Lord Used To

Assemble In The Middle Ages,  To Administer Justice,  And Decide

Respecting Affairs Of Common Interest,  &C;. It Was Next Used For

Those Who Stood In Immediate Connexion With The Lord And Master,

The Pares Curiae,  (Peers Of The Court,) The Limited Portion Of

The General Assembly,  To Which Was Entrusted The Pronouncing Of

Judgment," &C;.  Encyclopedia Americana,  Word Court.

 

"In Court-Barons Or County Courts The Steward Was Not Judge,  But

The Pares (Peers,  Jurors); Nor Was The Speaker In The House Of

Lords Judge,  But The Barons Only."   Gilbert On The Court Of

Rxchequer,  Ch. 3,  P. 42.

 

Crabbe,  Speaking Of The Saxon Times,  Says:

 

"The Sheriff Presided At The Hundred Court,  * * And Sometimes Sat

In The Place Of The Alderman (Earl) In The County Court." 

Crabbe,  23.

 

The Sheriff Afterwards Became The Sole Presiding Officer Of The

County Court.

 

Sir Thomas Smith,  Secretary Of State To Queen Elizabeth,  Writing

More Than Three Hundred Years After Magna Carta,  In Describing

The Difference Between The Civil Law And The English Law,  Says:

 

"Judex Is Of Us Called Judge,  But Our Fashion Is So Divers,  That

They Which Give The Deadly Stroke,  And Either Condemn Or Acquit

The Man For Guilty Or Not Guilty,  Are Not Called Judges,  But The

Twele Men. And The Same Order As Well In Civil Matters And

Pecuniary,  As In Matters Criminal."   Smith's Commonwealth Of

England,  Ch. 9,  P. 53,  Edition Of 1621.

 

Court-Leet. "That The Leet Is The Most Ancient Court In The Land

For Criminal Matters,  (The Court-Baron Being Of No Less Antiquity

In Civil,) Has Been Pronounced By The Highest Legal Authority. *

* Lord Mansfield States That This Court Was Coeval With The

Establishment Of The Saxons Here,  And Its Activity Marked Very

Visibly Both Among The Saxons And Danes. * * The Leet Is A Court

Of Record For The Cognizance Of Criminal Matters,  Or Pleas Of The

Crown; And Necessarily Belongs To The King; Though A Subject,

Usually The Lord Of The Manor,  May Be,  And Is,  Entitled To The

Profits,  Consisting Of The Essoign Pence,  Fines,  And Amerciaments

 

"It Is Held Before The Steward,  Or Was,  In Ancient Times,  Before

The Bailiff,  Of The Lord."   Tomline's Law Dict.,  Word

Court-Leet.

 

Of Course The Jury Were The Judges In This Court,  Where Only A

"Steward" Or "Bailiff" Of A Manor Presided.

 

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 2 Pg 58

"No Cause Of Consequence Was Determined Without The King's Writ;

For Even In The County Courts,  Of The Debts,  Which Were Above

Forty Shillings,  There Issued A Justicies (Commission) To The

Sheriff,  To Enable Him To Hold Such Plea,  Where The Suitors Are

Judges Of The Law And Fact."   Gilbert's History Of The Common

Pleas,  Introduction,  P. 19.

 

"This Position" (That " The Matter Of Law Was Decided By The

King's Justices,  But The Matter Of Fact By The Pares ") "Is Wholly

Incompatible With The Common Law,  For The Jurata ( Jury)

Were The Sole Judges Both Of The Law And The Fact."   Gilbert's

History Of The Common Pleas,  P. 70,  Note.

 

"We Come Now To The Challenge: And Of Old The Suitors In Court,

Who Were Judge,  Could Not He Challenged; Nor By The Feudal Law

Could The Pares Be Even Challenged. Pares Qui Ordinariam

Jurisdictionem Habent Recusari Non Possunt; (The Peers Who Have

Ordinary Jurisdiction Cannot Be Rejected;) "But Those Suitors Who

Are Judges Of The Court,  Could Not Be Challenged; And The Reason

Is,  That There Are Several Qualifications Required By The Writ,

Viz.,  That They Be Liberos Et Legales Homines De Vincineto (Free

And Legal Men Of The Neighborhood) Of The Place Laid In The

Declaration," &C;.,  &C;.   Ditto,  P.93.

 

"Ad Questionem Juris Non Respondent Juratores." (To The Question

Of Law The Jurors Do Not Answer.) "The Annotist Says,  That This

Is Indeed A Maxim In The Civil-Law Jurisprudence,  But It Does Not

Bind An English Jury,  For By The Common Law Of Theland The Jury

Are The Judges As Well Of The Matter Of Law,  As Of The Fact,  With

This Difference Only,  That The [A Saxon Word] Or Judge On The

Bench Is To Give Them No Assistance In Determining The Matter Of

Fact,  But If They Have Any Doubt Among Themselves Relating To

Matter Of Law,  They May Then Request Him To Explain It To Them,

Which When He Hath Done,  And They Are Thus Become Well

Informed,  They,  And They Only,  Become Competent Judges Of The

Matter Of Law. And This Is The Province Of The Judge On The Bench, 

Namely,  To Show,  Or Teach The Law,  But Not To Take Upon Him The

Trial Of The Delinquent,  Either In Matter Of Fact Or In Matter Of Law."

(Here Various Saxon Laws Are Quoted.) "In Neither Of These

Fundamental Laws Is There The Least Word,  Hint,  Or Idea,  That The

Earl Or Alderman (That Is To Say,  The Prepositus (Presiding

Officer) Of The Court,  Which Is Tantamount To The Judge On The

Bench) Is To Take Upon Him To Judge The Delinquent In Any Sense

Whatever,  The Sole Purport Of His Office Is To Teach The Secular

Or Worldly Law."   Ditto,  P. 57,  Note.

 

"The Administration Of Justice Was Carefully Provided For; It Was

Not The Caprice Of Their Lord,  But The Sentence Of Their Peers,

That They Obeyed. Each Was The Judge Of His Equals,  And Each By

His Equals Was Judged."   Introd. To Gilbert On Tenures,  P. 12.

 

Hallam Says:

 

"A Respectable Class Of Free Socagers,  Having,  In General,  Full 

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 2 Pg 59

Rights Of Alienating Their Lands,  And Holding Them Probably At

A Small Certain Rent From The Lord Of The Manor,  Frequently

Occur In Domes-Day Book. * * They Undoubtedly Were Suitors

To The Court-Baron Of The Lord,  To Whose Soc,  Or Right Of

Justice,  They Belonged. They Where Consequently Judges In Civil

Causes,  Determined Before The Manorial Tribunal."   2 Middle

Ages,  481.

 

Stephens Adopts As Correct The Following Quotations From Blackstone:

"The Court-Baron Is A Court Incident To Every Manor In The Kingdom, 

To Be Holden By The Steward Within The Said Manor." * *

 

It "Is A Court Of Common Law,  And It Is The Court Before The

Freeholders Who Owe Suit And Service To The Manor," (Are Bound To

Serve As Jurors In The Courts Of The Manor,) "The Steward Being

Rather The Registrar Than The Judge. * * The Freeholders' Court

Was Composed Of The Lord's Tenants,  Who Were The Pares(Equals) Of

Each Other,  And Were Bound By Their Feudal Tenure To Assist Their

Lord In The Dispensation Of Domestic Justice. This Was Formerly

Held Every Three Weeks; And Its Most Important Business Was To

Etermine,  By Writ Of Right,  All Controversies Relating To The Right

Of Lands Within The Manor."   3 Stephens' Commentaries,  392  3.

3 Blackstone,  32-33.

 

"A Hundred Court Is Only A Larger Court-Baron,  Being Held For All

The Inhabitants Of A Particular Hundred,  Instead Of A Manor. The

Free Suitors ( Jurors) Are Here Also The Judges,  And The Steward

The Register."   3 Stephens,  394. 3 Blackstone,  33.

 

"The County Court Is A Court Incident To The Jurisdiction Of The

Sheriff. * * The Freeholders Of The County Are The Real Judges In

This Court,  And The Sheriff Is The Ministerial Officer."   3

Stephens,  395   6. 3 Blackstone,  35-6.

 

Blackstone Describes These Courts,  As Courts "Wherein Injuries

Were Redressed In An Easy And Expeditious Manner,  By The Suffrage

Of Neighbors And Friends."   3 Blackstone,  30.

 

"When We Read Of A Certain Number Of Freemen Chosen By The

Parties To Decide In A Dispute   All Bound By Oath To Vote In

Foro Conscientia   And That Their Decision,  Not The Will Of The

Judge Presiding,  Ended The Suit,  We At Once Perceive That A Great

Improvement Has Been Made In The Old Form Of Compurgation   An

Improvement Which Impartial Observation Can Have No Hesitation

To Pronounce As Identical In Its Main Features With The Trial By

Jury."   Dunham's Middle Ages,  Sec. 2,  B. 2,  Ch. 1. 57 Lardner's

Cab. Cyc.,  60.

 

"The Bishop And The Earl Or,  In His Absence,  The Gerefa,

(Sheriff,) And Sometimes Both The Earl And The Gerefa,  Presided

At The Schyre-Mote (County Court); The Gerefa (Sheriff) Usually

Alone Presided At The Mote (Meeting Or Court) Of The Hundred. In

The Cities And Towns Which Were Not Within Any Peculiar

Jurisdiction,  There Was Held,  At Regular Stated Intervals,  A

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 2 Pg 60

Burgh Mote,  (Borough Court,) For The Administration Of Justice,

At Which A Gerefa,  Or A Magistrate Appointed By The King,

Presided."   Spence's Origin Of The Laws And Political

Institutions Of Modern Europe,  P. 444.

 

"The Right Of The Plaintiff And Defendant,  And Of The Prosecutor

And Criminal,  To Challenge The Judices,  (Judges.) Or Assessors,

[17] Appointed To Try The Cause In Civil Matters,  And To Decide

Upon The Guilt Or Innocence Of The Accused In Criminal Matters,

Is Recognized In The Treatise Called The Laws Of Henry The First;

But I Cannot Discover,  From The Anglo-Saxon Laws Or Histories,

That Before The Conquest The Parties Had Any General Right Of

Challege; Indeed,  Had Such Right Existed,  The Injunctions To All

Persons Standing In The Situation Of Judges (Jurors) To Do Right

According To Their Conscience,  Would Scarcely Have Been So

Frequently And Anxiously Repeated."   Spence,  456.

 

Hale Says:

 

"The Administration Of The Common Justice Of The Kingdom Seems

To Be Wholly Dispensed In The County Courts,  Hundred Courts,  And

Courts-Baron; Except Some Of The Greater Crimes Reformed By The

Laws Of King Henry I.,  And That Part Thereof Which Was Sometimes

Taken Up By The Justitiarius Angliae.

 

This Doubtless Bred Great Inconvenience,  Uncertainty,  And Variety

In The Laws,  Viz.:

 

"First,  By The Ignorance Of The Judges,  Which Were The

Freeholders Of The County.* *

 

"Thirdly,  A Third Inconvenience Was,  That All The Business Of Any

Moment Was Carried By Parties And Factions. For The Freeholders

Being Generally The Judges,  And Conversing One Among Another,  And

Being As It Were The Chief Judges,  Not Only Of The Fact,  But Of

The Law; Every Man That Had A Suit There,  Sped According As He

Could Make Parties."   1 Hale's History Of The Common Law,  P.

246.

 

"In All These Tribunals," (County Court,  Hundred Court,  &C;..)

"The Judges Were The Free Tenants,  Owing Suit To The Court,  And

Afterwards Called Its Peers."   1 Lingard's History Of England,

488.

 

Henry Calls The Twelve Jurors "Assessors," And Says:

"These Assessors,  Who Were In Reality Judges,  Took A Solemn Oath,

That They Would Faithfully Discharge The Duties Of Their Office,

And Not Suffer An Innocent Man To Be Condemned,  Nor Any Guilty

Person To Be Acquitted."   3 Henry's History Of Great Britain,

346.

 

Tyrre11 Says:

 

"Alfred Cantoned His Kingdom,  First Into Trihings And Lathes,  As

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 2 Pg 61

They Are Still Called In Kent And Other Places,  Consisting Of

Three Or Four Hundreds; In Which,  The Freeholders Being Judges,

Such Causes Were Brought As Could Not Be Determined In The

Hundred Court."   Tyrrell's Introduction To The History Of

England,  P. 80.

 

Of The Hundred Court He Says:

 

"In This Court Anciently,  One Of The Principal Inhabitants,

Called The Alderman,  Together With The Barons Of The Hundred [18]

 Id Est The Freeholders   Was Judge."   Ditto,  P. 80.

 

Also He Says:

 

"By A Law Of Edward The Elder,  'Every Sheriff Shall Convene The

People Once A Month,  And Do Equal Right To All,  Putting An End To

Controversies At Times Appointed.'"   Ditto,  P. 86.

 

A Statute,  Emphatically Termed The ' Grand Assize,' Enabled The

Defendant,  If He Thought Proper,  To Abide By The Testimony Of The

Twelve Good And Lawful Knights,  Chosen By Four Others Of The

Vicinage,  And Whose Oaths Gave A Final Decision To The Contested

Claim,."  1 Palgrave's Rise And Progress Of The English

Commonwealth,  261.

 

"From The Moment When The Crown Became Accustomed To The

'Inquest,' A Restraint Was Imposed Upon Every Branch Of The

Prerogative. The King Could Never Be Informed Of His Rights,  But

Through The Medium Of The People. Every 'Extent' By Which He

Claimed The Profits And Advantages Resulting From The Casualties

Of Tenure,  Every Process By Which He Repressed The Usurpations Of

The Baronage,  Depended Upon The 'Good Men And True' Who Were

Impaneled To 'Pass' Between The Subject And The Sovereign; And

The Thunder Of The Exchequer At Westminster Might Be Silenced By

The Honesty,  The Firmness,  Or The Obstinacy,  Of One Sturdy Knight

Or Yeoman In The Distant Shire.

 

Taxation Was Controlled In The Same Manner By The Voice Of Those

Who Were Most Liable To Oppression. * * A Jury Was Impaneled To

Adjudge The Proportion Due To The Sovereign; And This Course Was

Not Essentially Varied,  Even After The Right Of Granting Aids To

The Crown Was Fully Acknowledged To Be Vested In The Parliament

Of The Realm. The People Taxed Themselves; And The Collection Of

The Grants Was Checked And Controlled,  And,  Perhaps,  In Many

Instances Evaded,  By These Virtual Representatives Of The

Community.

 

The Principle Of The Jury Was,  Therefore,  Not Confined To Its

Mere Application As A Mode Of Trying Contested Facts,  Whether In

Civil Or Criminal Cases; And,  Both In Its Form And In Its

Consequences,  It Had A Very Material Influence Upon The General

Constitution Of The Realm. * *The Main-Spring Of The Machinery Of

Remedial Justice Existed In The Franchise Of The Lower And Lowest

Orders Of The Political Hierarchy. Without The Suffrage Of The

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 2 Pg 62

Yeoman,  The Burgess,  And The Churl,  The Sovereign Could Not

Exercise The Most Important And Most Essential Function Of

Royalty; From Them He Received The Power Of Life And Death; He

Could Not Wield The Sword Of Justice Until The Humblest Of His

Subjects Placed The Weapon In His Hand."   1 Palgrave's Rise And

Progress Of The English Constitution,  274   7.

 

Coke Says,

 

"The Court Of The County Is No Court Of Record,  [19]

And The Suitors Are The Judges Thereof."   4 Inst.) 266.

 

Also,  "The Court Of The Hundred Is No Court Of Record,  And The

Suitors Be Thereof Judges."   4 Inst.,  267.

 

 

 

 

 

Also,  "The Court-Baron Is A Court Incident To Every Manor,  And Is

Not Of Record,  And The Suitors Be Thereof Judges."   4 Inst.,

268.

 

Also,  "The Court Of Ancient Demesne Is In The Nature Of A

Court-Baron,  Wherein The Suitors Are Judges,  And Is No Court Of

Record."   4 Inst.,  269.

 

Millar Says,

 

"Some Authors Have Thought That Jurymen Were Originally

Compurgators,  Called By A Defendant To Swear That They

Believed Him Innocent Of The Facts With Which He Was Charged. . .

But . . . Compurgators  Were Merely Witnesses; Jurymen Were,  In

Reality,  Judges. The Former Were Called To Confirm The Oath Of

The Party By Swearing,  According To Their Belief,  That He Had

Told The Truth,  (In His Oath Of Purgation;) The Latter Were

Appointed To Try,  By Witnesses,  And By All Other Means Of Proof,

Whether He  Was Innocent Or Guilty. Juries Were Accustomed To

Ascertain The Truth Of Facts,  By The Defendant's Oath Of

Purgation,  Together With That Of His Compurgators. . . Both Of

Them (Jurymen And Compurgators) Were Obliged To Swear That They

Would Tell Truth.

 

According To The Simple Idea Of Our Forefathers,  Guilt Or Innocence

Was Regarded As A Mere Matter  Of Fact; And It Was Thought That No

Man,  Who Knew The Real Circumstances Of A Case,  Could Be At A

Loss To Determine Whether The Culprit Ought To Be Condemned Or

 Acquitted."   1 Millar's Hist. View Of Eng. Gov.,  Ch. 12,  P. 332 - 4.

 

Also,  "The Same Form  Of Procedure,  Which Took Place In The

Administration Of Justice Among The Vassals Of A Barony,  Was

Gradually Extended To The Courts Eld In The Trading Towns." 

Same,  P. 335.

 

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 2 Pg 63

Also,  "The Same Regulation,  Concerning The Distribution Of

Justice By The Intervention Of Juries,  . . .Were Introduced Into

The Baron Courts Of The King,  As Into Those Of The Nobility,  Or

Such Of His Subjects As Retained Their Allodial Property." 

Same,  P. 337.

 

Also,  "This Tribunal" (The Aula Regis,  Or King's Court,  Afterwards

Divided Into The Courts Of King's Bench,  Common Pleas,

And Exchequer) "Was Properly The Ordinary Baron-Court Of The

King; And,  Being In The Same Circumstances With The Baron Courts

Of The Nobility,  It Was Under The Same Necessity Of Trying Causes

By The Intervention Of A Jury."   Same,  Vol. 2,  P. 292.

 

Speaking Of The Times Of Edward The First,  (1272 To 1307,) Millar

Says:

 

"What Is Called The Petty Jury Was Therefore Introduced Into

These Tribunals,  (The King's Bench,  The Common Pleas,  And The

Exhequer,) As Well As Into Their Anxiliary Courts Employed To

Distribute Justice In The Circuits; And Was Thus Rendered

Essentially Necessary In Determining Causes Of Every Sort,

Whether Civil,  Criminal,  Or Fiscal."   Same,  Vol. 2,  P. 293-4.

 

Also,  "That This Form Of Trial (By Jury) Obtained Universally In

All The Feudal Governments,  As Well As In That Of Eng-1and,  There

Can Be No Reason To Doubt. In France,  In Germany,  And In Other

European Countries,  Where We Have Any Accounts Of The

Constitution And Procedure Of The Feudal Courts,  It Appears That

Lawsuits Of Every Sort Concerning The Freemen Or Vassals Of A

Barony,  Were Determined By The Pares Curiae (Peers Of The Court;)

And That The Judge Took Little More Upon Him Than To Regulate The

Method Of Proceeding,  Or To Declare The Verdict Of The Jury." 

Same,  Vol. 1,  Ch. 12,  P. 329.

 

Also,  "Among The Gothic Nations Of Modern Europe,  The Custom Of

Deciding Lawsuits By A Jury Seems To Have Prevailed Universally;

First In The Allodial Courts Of The County,  Or Of The Hundred,

And Afterwards In The Baron-Courts Of Every Feudal Superior." 

Same,  Vol. 2,  P. 296.

 

Palgrave Says That In Germany "The Graff (Gerefa,  Sheriff) Placed

Himself In The Seat Of Judgment,  And Gave The Charge To The

Assembled Free Echevins,  Warning Them To Pronounce Judgment

According To Right And Justice."   2 Palgrave,  147.

 

Also,  That,  In Germany,  "The Echevins Were Composed Of The

Villanage,  Somewhat Obscured In Their Functions By The Learning

Of The Grave Civilian Who Was Associated To Them,  And Somewhat

Limited By The Encroachments Of Modern Feudality; But They Were

Still Substantially The Judges Of The Court."   Same,  148.

 

Palgrave Also Says,  "Scotland,  In Like Manner,  Had The Laws Of

Burlaw,  Or Birlaw,  Which Were Made And Determined By The

Neighbors,  Elected By Common Consent,  In The Burlaw Or Birlaw

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 2 Pg 64

Courts,  Wherein Knowledge Was Taken Of Complaints Between

Neighbor And Neighbor,  Which Men,  So Chosen,  Were Judges And

Arbitrators,  And Called Birlaw Men."   1 Palgrave's Rise,  &C;.,

P. 80.

 

But,  In Order To Understand The Common Law Trial By Jury,  As It

Existed Prior To Magna Carta,  And As It,  Was Guaranteed. By That

Instrument,  It Is Perhaps Indispensable To Understand More Fully

The Nature Of The Courts In Which Juries Sat,  And The Extent Of

The Powers Exercised By Juries In Those Courts. I Therefore Give

In A Note Extended Extracts,  On These Points,  From Stuart On The

Constitution Of England,  And From Blackstone's Commentaries.

[20]

 

That All These Courts Were Mere Courts Of Conscience,  In Which

The Juries Were Sole Judges,  Administering Justice According To

Their Own Ideas Of It,  Is Not Only Shown By The Extracts Already

Given,  But Is Explicitly Acknowledged In The Following One,  In

Which The Modern "Courts Of Conscience" Are Compared With The

Ancient Hundred And County Courts,  And The Preference Given To

The Latter,  On The Ground That The Duties Of The Jurors In The

One Case,  And Of The Commissioners In The Other,   Are The Same,

And That The Consciences Of A Jury Are  A Safer  And Purer

Tribunal Than The Consciences Of Individuals Specially Appointed,

And Holding Permanent Offices.

 

"But There Is One Species Of Courts Constituted By Act Of

Parliament,  In The City Of London,  And Other Trading And Populous

Districts,  Which,  In Their Proceedings,  So Vary From The Course

Of The Common Law,  That They Deserve A More Particular

Consideration. I Mean The Court Of Requests,  Or Courts Of

Conscience,  For The Recovery Of Small Debts. The First Of These

Was Established In London So Early As The Reign Of Henry Viii.,

By An Act Of Their Common Council; Which,  However,  Was Certainly

Insufficient For That Purpose,  And Illegal,  Till Confirmed By

Statute 3 Jac. I.,  Ch. 15,  Which Has Since Been Explained And

Amended By Statute 14 Geo. Ii.,  Ch. 10. The Constitution Is This:

Two Aldermen And Four Commoners Sit Twice A Week To Hear All

Causes Of Debt Not Exceeding The Value Of Forty Shillings; Which

They Examine In A Summary Way,  By The Oath Of The Parties Or

Other Witnesses,  And Make Such Order Therein As Is Consonant To

Equity And Good Conscience.I * *  * Divers Trading Towns And

Other Districts Have Obtained Acts Of Parliament,  For

Establishing In Them Courts Of Conscience Upon Nearly The Same

Plan As That In The City Of London.

 

"The Anxious Desire That Has Been Shown To Obtain These Several

Acts,  Proves Clearly That The Nation,  Ingeneral,  Is Truly

Sensible Of The Great Inconvenience Arising From The Disuse Of

The Ancient County And Hundred Courts,  Wherein Causes Of This

Small Value Were Always Formerly Decided With Very Little Trouble

And Expense To The Parties. But It Is To Be Feared That The

General Remedy,  Which Of Late Hath Been Principally Applied To

This Inconvenience,  (The Erecting These New Jurisdictions,) May

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 2 Pg 65

Itself Be Attended In Time With Very Ill Consequences; As The

Method Of Proceeding Therein Is Entirely In Derogation Of The

Common Law; And Their Large Discretionary Powers Create A Petty

Tyranny In A Set Of Standing Commissioners; And As The Disuse Of

The Trial By Jury May Tend To Estrange The Minds Of The People

From That Valuable Prerogative Of Englishmen,  Which Has Already

Been More Than Sufficiently Excluded In Many Instances. How

Much Rather Is It To Be Wished That The Proceedings In The County

And Hundred Courts Could Be Again Revived,  Without Burdening

The Freeholders With Too Frequent And Tedious Attendances; And

At The Same Time Removing The Delays That Have Insensibly Crept

Into Their Proceedings,  And The Power That Either Party Has Of

Transferring At Pleasure Their Suits To The Courts At Westminster!

And We May,  With Satisfaction,  Observe,  That This Experiment Has

Been Actually Tried,  And Has Succeeded In The Populous County Of

Middlesex,  Which Might Serve As An Example For Others. For By

Statute 23 Geo. Ii.,  Ch. 33,  It Is Enacted:

 

1. That A Special County Court Shall Be Held At Least Once In A

Month,  In Every Hundred Of The County Of Middlesex,  By The County

Clerk.

 

2. That Twelve Freeholders Of That Hundred,  Qualified To Serve On

Juries,  And Struck By The Sheriff,  Shall Be Summoned To Appear At

Such Court By Rotation; So As None Shall Be Summoned Oftener Than

Once A Year.

 

3. That In All Causes Not Exceeding The Value Of Forty Shillings,

The County Clerk And Twelve Suitors (Jurors) Shll Proceed In A

Summary Way,  Examining The Parties And Witnesses On Oath,

Without The Formal Process Anciently Used; And Shall Make

Such Order Therein As They Shall Judge Agreeable To Conscience."

3 Blackstone,  81   83.

 

What Are These But Courts Of Conscience? And Yet Blackstone Tells

Us They Are A Revival Of The Ancient Hundred And County Courts.

And What Does This Fact Prove,  But That The Ancient Common Law

Courts,  In Which Juries Sat,  Were Mere Courts Of Conscience?

It Is Perfectly Evident That In All These Courts The Jurors Were

The Judges,  And Determined All Questions Of Law For Themselves;

Because The Only Alternative To That Supposition Is,  That The

Jurors Took Their Law From Sheriffs,  Bailiffs,  And Stewards,  Of

Which There Is Not The Least Evidence In History,  Nor The Least

Probability In Reason. It Is Evident,  Also,  That They Judged

Independently Of The Laws Of The King,  For The Reasons Before

Given,  Viz.,  That The Authority Of The King Was Held In Very,

Little Esteem; And,  Secondly,  That The Laws Of The King (Not

Being Printed,  And The People Being Unable To Read Them If They

Had Been Printed) Must Have Been In A Great Measure Unknown To

Them,  And Could Have Been Received By Them Only On The Authority

Of The Sheriff,  Bailiff; Or Steward. If Laws Were To Be Received

By Them On The Authority Of These Officers,  The Latter Would Have

Imposed Such Laws Upon The People As They Pleased.

 

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 2 Pg 66

These Courts,  That Have Now Been Described,  Were Continued In

Full Power Long After Magna Carta,  No Alteration Being Made In

Them By That Instrument,  Nor In The Mode Of Administering Justice

In Them.

 

There Is No Evidence Whatever,  So Far As I Am Aware,  That The

Juries Had Any Less Power In The Courts Held By The King's

Justices,  Than In Those Held By Sheriffs,  Bailiff,  And Stewards;

And There Is No Probability Whatever That They Had. All The

Difference Between The Former Courts And The Latter Undoubtedly

Was,  That,  In The Former,  The Juries Had The Benefit Of The

Advice And Assistance Of The Justices,  Which Would,  Of Course,  Be

Considered Valuable In Difficult Cases,  On Account Of The

Justices Being Regarded As More Learned,  Not Only In The Laws Of

The King,  But Also In The Common Law,  Or "Law Of The Land."

 

The Conclusion,  Therefore,  I Think,  Inevitably Must Be,  That

Neither The Laws Of The King,  Nor The Instructions Of His

Justices,  Had Any Authority Over Jurors Beyond What The Latter

Saw Fit To Accord To Them. And This View Is Confirmed By This

Remark Of Hallam,  The Truth Of Which All Will Acknowledge:

 

"The Rules Of Legal Decision,  Among A Rude People,  Are Always

Very Simple; Not Serving Much To Guide,  Far Less To Control The

Feelings Of Natural Equity."   2 Middle Ages,  Ch. 8,  Part 2,  P. 465.

 

It Is Evident That It Was In This Way,  By The Free And Concurrent

Judgments Of Juries,  Approving And Enforcing Certain Laws And

Rules Of Conduct,  Corresponding To Their Notions Of Right And

Justice,  That The Laws And Customs,  Which,  For The Most Part,

Made Up The Common Law,  And Were Called,  At That Day,  "The

Good Laws,  And Good Customs," And "The Law Of The Land," Were

Established. How Otherwise Could They Ever Have Become

Established,  As Blackstone Says They Were,  "By Long And

Immemorial Usage,  And By Their Universal Reception Throughout

The Kingdom,"- 1 Blackstone,63-67.,  When,  As The Mirror Says, 

"Justice Was So Done,  That Every One So Judged His Neighbor,  By

Such Judgment As A Man Could Not Elsewhere Receive In The Like

Cases,  Until Such Times As The Customs Of The Realm,  Were Put In

Writing And Certainly Published?"

 

 

 

 

 

The Fact That,  In That Dark Age,  So Many Of The Principles Of

Natural Equity,  As Those Then Embraced In The Common Law,

Should Have Been So Uniformly Recognized And Enforced By Juries, 

As To Have Become Established By General Consent As "The Law

Of The Land;" And The Further Fact That This "Law Of The Land" Was

Held So Sacred That Even The King Could Not Lawfully Infringe Or

Alter It,  But Was Required To Swear To Maintain It,  Are Beautiful

And Impressive Illustrations Of The Troth That Men's Minds,  Even

In The Comparative Infancy Of Other Knowledge,  Have Clear And

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 2 Pg 67

Coincident Ideas Of The Elementary Principles,  And The Paramount

Obligation,  Of Justice. The Same Facts Also Prove That The Common

Mind,  And The General,  Or,  Perhaps,  Rather,  The Universal

Conscience,  As Developed In The Untrammeled Judgments Of Juries, 

May Be Safely Relied Upon For The Preservation Of Individual Rights

In Civil Society; And That There Is No Necessity Or Excuse For That

Deluge Of  Arbitrary Legislation,  With Which The Present Age Is

Overwhelmed,   Under The Pretext That Unless Laws Be Made,  The

Law Will Not Be  Known; A Pretext,  By The Way,  Almost Universally

Used For Overturning,  Instead Of Establishing,  The Principles Of

Justice.

 

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 3 Pg 68

 

The Oaths That Have Been Administered To Jurors,  In England,  And

Which Are Their Legal Guide To Their Duty,  All (So Far As I Have

Ascertained Them) Corroborate The Idea That The Jurors Are To Try

All Cases On Their Intrinsic Merits,  Independently Of Any Laws

That They Deem Unjust Or Oppressive. It Is Probable That An Oath

Was Never Administered To A Jury In England,  Either In A Civil Or

Criminal Case,  To Try It According To Law.

 

The Earliest Oath That I Have Found Prescribed By Law To Be

Administered To Jurors Is In The Laws Of Ethelred,  (About The

Year 1015,) Which Require That The Jurors "Shall Swear,  With Their

Hands Upon A Holy Thing,  That They Will Condemn No Man That Is

Innocent,  Nor Acquit Any That Is Guilty."   4 Blackstone,  302.

 2 Turner's History Of The Anglo-Saxons,  155 Wilkins' Laws Of The

Anglo-Saxons,  117. Spelman's Glossary,   Word Jurata.

 

Blackstone Assumes That This Was The Oath Of The Grand Jury

4 Blackstone,  302); But There Was But One Jury At The Time This

Oath Was Ordained. The Institution Of Two Juries,  Grand And Petit, 

Took Place After The Norman Conquest.

 

Hume,  Speaking Of The Administration Of Justice In The Time Of

Alfred,  Says That,  In Every Hundred,

 

"Twelve Freeholders Were Chosen,  Who,  Having Sworn, 

Together With The Hundreder,  Or Presiding Magistrate Of That

Division,  To Administer Impartial Justice,   Proceeded To

The Examination Of That Cause Which Was Submitted To Their

Jurisdiction."   Hume,  Ch. 2.

 

By A Law Of Henry Ii.,  In 1164,  It Was Directed That The Sheriff

"Faciet Jurare Duodecim Legales Homines De Vicineto Seu De

Villa,  Quod Inde Veritatem Secundum Conscientiam Suam

Manifestabunt," (Shall Make Twelve,  Legal Men From The

Neighborhood To Swear That They Will Make Known The Truth

According To Their Conscience.)   Crabbe's History Of The

English Law,  119. 1 Reeves,  87. Wilkins,  321   323.

 

Glanville,  Who Wrote Within The Half Century Previous To

Magna Carta,  Says;

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 3 Pg 69

 

"Each Of The Knights Summoned Far This Purpose (As Jurors)

Ought To Swear That He Will Neither Utter That Which Is False,  Nor

Knowingly Conceal The Truth."   Beames' Glanville,  65.

 

Reeve Calls The Trial By Jury "The Trial By Twelve Men Sworn

To Speak The Truth."   1 Reeve's History Of The English Law,  87.

 

Henry Says That The Jurors "Took A Solemn Oath,  That They

Would Faithfully Discharge The Duties Of Their Office,  And Not

Suffer An Innocent Man To Be Condemned,  Nor Any Guilty Person

To Be Acquitted."   3 Henry's Hist. Of Great Britain,  346.

 

The Mirror Of Justices,  (Written Within A Century After

Magna Carta,) In The Chapter On The Abuses Of The Common

Law,  Says:"It Is Abuse To Use The Words,  To Their Knowledge,

In Their Oaths,  To Make The Jurors Speak Upon Thoughts,  Since

The Chief Words Of Their Oaths Be That They Speak The Truth."   P.

249.

 

Smith,  Writing In The Time Of Elizabeth,  Says That,  In Civil Suits, 

The Jury "Be Sworn To Declare The Truth Of That Issue According To

The Evidence,  And Their Conscience."   Smith's Commonwealth

Of England. Edition Of 1621,  P. 73.

 

In Criminal Trials,  He Says:

 

"The Clerk Giveth The Juror An Oath To Go Uprightly Betwixt The

Prince And The Prisoner."   Ditto,  P. 90. [24]

 

Hale Says:

 

"Then Twelve,  And No Less,  Of Such As Are Indifferent And Are

Returned Upon The Principal Panel,  Or The Tales,  Are Sworn To Try

The Same According To The Evidence."   2 Hale's History Of The

Common Law,  141.

 

It Appears From Blackstone That,  Even At This Day,  Neither In

Civil Nor Criminal Cases,  Are Jurors In England Sworn To Try Causes

According To Law. He Says Tht In Civil Suits The Jury Are "Sworn Well

And Truly To Try The Issue Between The Parties; And A True Verdict To

Give According To The Evidence."   3 Blackstone,  365.

 

"The Issue" To Be Tried Is Whether A Owes B Anything  And If So, 

How Much? Or Whether A Has In His Possession Anything That

Belongs To B; Or Whether A Has Wronged B,  And Ought To Make

Compensation; And If So,  How Much? 

 

No Statute Passed By A Legislature,  Simply As A Legislature,  Can Alter

Either Of These "Issues" In Hardly Any Conceivable Case,  Perhaps In

None. No Unjust Law Could Ever Alter Them In Any. They Are All

Mere Questions Of Natural Justice,  Which Legislatures Have No Power To

Alter,  And With Which They Have No Right To Interfere,  Further Than To

Provide For Having Them Settled By The Most Competent And Impartial

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 3 Pg 70

Tribunal That It Is Practicable To Have,  And Then For Having All Just Decisions

Enforced. And Any Tribunal,  Whether Judge Or Jury,  That Attempts To

Try These Issues,  Has No More Moral Right To Be Swerved From The

Line Of Justice,  By The Will Of A Legislature,  Than By The Will Of Any Other

Body Of Men Whatever. And This Oath Does Not Require Or Permit A Jury To

Be So Swerved.

 

In Criminal Cases,  Blackstone Says The Oath Of The Jury In England

Is:

 

"Well And Truly To Try,  And True Deliverance Make,  Between Our

Sovereign Lord,  The King,  And The Prisoner Whom They Have In

Charge,  And A True Verdict To Give According To The Evidence."   4

Blackstone,  355.

 

"The Issue" To Be Tried,  In A Criminal Case,  Is "Guilty," Or "Not

Guilty." The Laws Passed By A Legislature Can Rarely,  If Ever,  Have Anything

To Do With This Issue. "Guilt" Is An Intrinsic Quality Of Actions,  And Can

Neither Be Created,  Destroyed,  Nor Changed By Legislation. And No Tribunal

That Attempts To Try This Issue Can Have Any Moral Right To Declare A Man

Guilty,  For An Act That Is Intrinsically Innocent,  At The Bidding Of A

Legislature,  Any More Than At The Bidding Of Anybody Else. And This

Oath Does Not Require Or Permit A Jury To Do So.

 

The Words,  "According To The Evidence," Have Doubtless Been

Introduced Into The Above Oaths In Modern Times. They Are Unquestionably In

Violation Of The Common Law,  And Of Magna Carta,  If By Them Be

Meant Such Evidence Only As The Government Sees Fit Ft Allow To Go To The

Jury. If The Government Can Dictate The Evidence,  And Require The Jury To

Decide According To That Evidence,  It Necessarily Dictates The Conclusion To

Which They Must Arrive. In That Case The Trial Is Really A Trial By The

Government,  And Not By The Jury. The Jury Cannot Try An Issue,  Unless They

Determine What Evidence Shall Be Admitted. The Ancient Oaths,  It Will Be

Observed,  Say Nothing About "According To The Evidence." They Obviously

Take It For Granted That The Jury Try The Whole Case; And Of Course That They

Decide What Evidence Shall Be Admitted. It Would Be Intrinsically An

Immoral And Criminal Act For A Jury To Declare A Man Guilty,  Or To Declare

That One Man Owed. Money To Another,  Unless All The Evidence Were

Admitted,  Which They Thought Ought To Be Admitted,  For Ascertaining The Truth.

[25]

 

Grand Jury. If Jurors Are Bound To Enforce All Laws Passed By The

Legislature,  It Is A Very Remarkable Fact Than The Oath Of Grand Juries Does Not

Require Them To Be Governed By The Laws In Finding Indictments. There

Have Been Various Forms Of Oath Administered To Grand Jurors; But By None Of

Them That I Recollect Ever To Have Seen,  Except Those Of The States Of

Connecticut And  Vermont,  Are They Sworn To Present Men According To Law.  

 

The English Form,  As Given In The Essay On Grand Juries,  Written

Near Two Hundred Years Ago,  And Supposed To Have Been Written By Lord

Somers,  Is As Follows:

 

"You Shall Diligently Inquire,  And True Presentment Make,  Of All

Such Articles,  Matters,  And Things,  As Shall Be Given You In Charge,

And Of All Other Matters And Things As Shall Come To Your Knowledge

Touching This Present Service. The King's Council,  Your Fellows,  And Your Own,

You  Shall Keep Secret. You Shall Present No Person For Hatred Or Malice;

Neither Shall You Leave Any One Unpresented For Favor,  Or Affection,

For Love Or Gain,  Or Any Hopes Thereof; But In All Things You Shall Present The

Truth,  The Whole Truth,  And Nothing But The Truth,  To The Best Of Your

Knowledge. So Help You God."

 

This Form Of Oath Is Doubtless Quite Ancient,  For The Essay Says "Our

Ancestors Appointed" It.   See Essay,  P. 33   34.

 

On The Obligations Of This Oath,  The Essay Says:"If It Be Asked How, 

Or In What Manner,  The (Grand) Juries Shall Inquire,  The Answer

Is Ready,  According To The Best Of Their Understandings. They Only,

Not The Judges,  Are Sworn To Search Diligently To Find Out All Treasons,

&C;.,  Within Their Charge,  And They Must And Ought To Use Their Own

Discretion In The Way And Manner Of Their Inquiry. No Directions

Can Legally Be Imposed Upon There By Any Court Or Judges; An Honest

Jury Will Thankfully Accept Good Advice From Judges,  As Their Assistants;

But They Are Bound By Their Oaths To Present The Truth,  The Whole Truth, 

And Nothing But The Truth,  To The Best Of Their Own,  Not The Judge's,

Knowledge. Neither Can They,  Without Breach Of That Oath,  Resign

Their Consciences,  Or Blindly Submit To The Dictates Of Others; And

Therefore Ought  To Receive Or Reject Such Advices,  As They Judge Them

Good Or Bad. * *Nothing Can Be More Plain And Express Than The

Words Of The Oath Are To This Purpose. The Jurors Need Not Search The

Law Books,  Nor Tumble Over Heaps Of Old Records,  For The Explanation

Of Them. Our Greatest Lawyers May From Hence Learn More Certainly

Our Ancient Law In This Case,  Than From All The Books In Their Studies.

The Language Wherein The Oath Is Penned Is Known And Understood By

Every Man,  And The Words In It Have The Same Signification As They Have

Wheresoever Else They Are Used. The Judges,  Without Assuming To

Themselves A Legislative Power,  Cannot Put A New Sense Upon Them, 

Other Than According To Their Genuine,  Common Meaning. They Cannot

Magisterially Impose Their Opinions Upon The Jury,  And Make Them

Forsake The Direct Words Of Their Oath,  To Pursue Their Glosses. The 

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 3 Pg 71

Grand Inquest Are Bound To Observe Alike Strictly Every Part Of Their

Oath,  And To Use All Just And Proper  Ways Which May Enable Them To

Perform It; Otherwise It Were To Say,  That After Men Had Sworn To

Inquire Diligently After The Truth,  According To The Best Of Their

Knowledge,  They Were Bound To Forsake All The Natural And Proper

Means Which Their Understandings Suggest For The Discovery Of It, 

If It Be Commanded By The Judges."   Lord Somers' Essay On Grand

Juries,  P. 88.

 

What Is Here Said So Plainly And Forcibly Of The Oath And Obligations Of

Grand Juries,  Is Equally Applicable To The Oath And Obligations Of

Petit Juries. In Both Cases The Simple Oaths Of The Jurors,  And Not The

Instructions Of The Judges,  Nor The Statutes Of Kings Nor Legislatures,

Are Their Legal Guides To Their Duties. [26]

 

Section Iv. The Right Of Juries To Fix The Sentence.

 

The Nature Of The Common Law Courts Existing Prior To Magna

Carta,  Such As The County Courts,  The Hundred Courts,  The Court-Leet,

And The Court-Baron,  All Prove,  What Has Already Been Proved From

Magna Carta,  That,  In Jury Trials,  The Juries Fixed The Sentence;

Because,  In Those Courts,  There Was No One But The Jury Who Could Fix It,

Unless It Were The Sheriff,  Bailiff,  Or Steward; And No One Will Pretend That

It  Was Fixed By Them. The Juries Unquestionably Gave The "Judgment"

In Both Civil And Criminal Cases.

 

That The Juries Were To Fix The Sentence Under Magna Carta,  Is Also

Shown By Statutes Subsequent To Magna Carta. A Statute Passed

Fifty-One Years After Magna Carta,  Says That A Baker,  For Default In

The Weight Of His Bread,  "Debeat Amerciari Vel Subire Judicium Pilloae,"

 

That Is,  "Ought To Be Amerced,  Or Suffer The Sentence Of The Pillory."

And That A Brewer,  For "Selling Ale,  Contrary To The Assize," "Debeat

Amerciari,  Vel Pati Judicium Tumbrelli;" That Is,  "Ought To Be

Amerced,  Or Suffer Judgment Of The Tumbrel."   51 Henry Iii.,  St. 6. (1266.)

 

If The King (The Legislative Power) Had Had Authority To Fix The

Punishments Of These Offences Imperatively,  He Would Naturally

Have Said These Offenders Shall Be Amerced,  And Shall Suffer

Judgment Of The Pillory And Tumbrel,  Instead Of Thus Simply

Expressing The Opinion That They Ought To Be Punished In That Manner.

 

The Statute Of Westminster,  Passed Sixty Years After Magna Carta, 

Provides That,"No City,  Borough,  Nor Town,  Nor Any Man,  Be Amerced, 

Without Reasonable Cause,  And According To The Quantity Of The Trespass;

That Is To Say,  Every Freeman Saving His Freehold,  A Merchant Saving

His Merchandise,  A Villein His Waynage,  And That By His Or Their

Peers." 3 Edward I.,  Ch. 6. (1275.)

 

The Same Statute (Ch. 18) Provides Further,  That,"Forasmuch As The

Common Fine And Amercement Of The Whole County In Eyre Of The

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 3 Pg 72

Justices For False Judgments,  Or For Other Trespass,  Is Unjustly

Assessed By Sheriff's And Baretors In The Shires,  So That The Sum Is Many

Times Increased,  And The Parcels Otherwise Assessed Than They Ought To

Be,  To The Damage Of The People,  Which Be Many Times Paid To The Sheriffs

And Baretors,  Which Do Not Acquit The Payers; It Is Provided,  And The

King Wills,  That From Henceforth Such Sums Shall Be Assessed Before

The Justices In Eyre,  Afore Their Departure,  By The Oath Of Knights

And Other Honest Men,  Upon All Such As Ought To Pay; And The Justices

Shall Cause The Parcels To Be Put Into Their Estreats,  Which Shall Be

Delivered Up Unto The Exchequer,  And Not The Whole Sum."   St. 3 Edward I.,

Ch. 18,  (1275.) [27]

 

The Following Statute,  Passed In 1341,  One Hundred And Twenty-Five

Years After Magna Carta,  Providing For The Trial Of Peers Of The Realm, 

And The King's Ministers,  Contains A Recognition Of The Principle Of

Magna Carta,  That The Jury Are To Fix The Sentence.

 

"Whereas Before This Time The Peers Of The Land Have Been Arrested

And Imprisoned,  And Their Temporalities,  Lands,  And Teneiments,

Goods And Cattels,  Asseized In The King's Hands,  And Some Put To

Death Without Judgment Of Their Peers: It Is Accorded And Assented,

That No Peer Of The Land,  Officer,  Nor Other,  Because Of His Office, 

Nor Of Things Touching His Office,  Nor By Other Cause,  Shall Be

Brought In Judgment To Lose His Temporalities,  Lands,  Tenements, 

Goods And Cattels,  Nor To Be Arrested,  Nor Imprisoned,  Outlawed, 

Exiled,  Nor Forejudged,  Nor Put To Answer,  Nor Be Judged,  But By

Award (Sentence) Of The Said Peers In Parliament."   15 Edward Iii., 

St. 1,  Sec. 2.

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 4 Pg 73

 

"That In Every Parliament,  At The Third Day Of Every Parliament.

The King Shall Take In His Hands The Offices Of All The Ministers

Aforesaid," (That Is,  "The Chancellor,  Treasurer,  Barons,  And

Chancellor Of The Exchequer,  The Justices Of The One Bench And Of

The Other,  Justices Assigned In The Country,  Steward And Chamberlain

Of The King's House,  Keeper Of The Privy Seal,  Treasurer Of The

Wardrobe,   Controllers,  And They That Be Chief Deputed To Abide Nigh

The King's  Son,  Duke Of Cornwall,") "And So They Shall Abide Four

Or Five Days;  Except The Offices Of Justices Of The One Place Or The

Other,  Justices Assigned,  Barons Of Exchequer; So Always That They

And All Other Ministers Be Put To Answer To Every Complaint; And If

Default Be Found In Any Of The Said Ministers,  By Complaint Or Other

Manner,  And Of That Attainted In Parliament,  He Shall Be Punished

By Judgment Of The Peers,  And Put Out Of His Office,  And Another

Convenient Put In His Place. And Upon The Same Our Said Sovereign

Lord The King Shall Do (Cause) To Be Pronounced And Made  Execution

Without Delay,  According To The Judgment (Sentence) Of The Said Peers

In The Parliament."

 

Here Is An Admission That The Peers Were To Fix The Sentence,  Or 

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 4 Pg 74

Judgment,  And The King Promises To Make Execution "According To"

That Sentence.

 

And This Appears To Be The Law,  Under Which Peers Of The Realm

And The Great Officers Of The Crown Were Tried And Sentenced,  For

Four Hundred Years After Its Passage,  And,  For Aught I Know,  Until This

Day.

 

The First Case Given In Hargrave's Collection Of English State

Trials,  Is That Of Alexander Nevil,  Archbishop Of York,  Robert

Vere Duke Of Ireland; Michael De La Pole,  Earl Of Suffolk,  And

Robert Tresilian,  Lord Chief Justice Of England,  With Several

Others,  Convicted Of Treason,  Before "The Lords Of Parliament," In

1388. The Sentences In These Cases Were Adjudged By The "Lords

Of Parliament," In The Following Terms,  As They Are Reported.

 

"Wherefore The Said Lords Of Parliament,  There Present,  As Judges

In Parliament,  In This Case,  By Assent Of The King,  Pronounced Their

Sentence,  And Did Adjudge The Said Archbishop,  Duke,  And Earl,  With

Robert Tresilian,  So Appealed,  As Aforesaid,  To Be Guilty,  And

Convicted Of Treason,  And To Be Drawn And Hanged,  As Traitors And

Enemies To The King And Kingdom; And That Their Heirs Should Be

Disinherited Forever,  And Their Lands And Tenements,  Goods And

Chattels,  Forfeited To The King,  And That The Temporalities Of The

Archbishop Of York Should Be Taken Into The King's Hands."

 

Also,  In The Same Case,  Sir John Holt,  Sir William Burgh,  Sir John

Cary,  Sir Roger Fulthorpe,  And John Locton,  "Were By The Lords

Temporal,  By The Assent Of The King,  Adjudged To Be Drawn And

Hanged,  As Traitors,  Their Heirs Disinherited,  And Their Lands And

Tenements,  Goods And Chattels,  To Be Forfeited To The King."

 

Also,  In The Same Case,  John Blake,  "Of Council For The King," And

Thomas Uske,  Under Sheriff Of Middlesex,  Having Been Convicted

Of Treason,  "The Lords Awarded,  By Assent Of The King,  That They

Should Both Be Hanged And Drawn As Traitors,  As Open Enemies To

The King And Kingdom,  And Their Heirs Disinherited Forever,  And

Their Lands And Tenements,  Goods And Chattels,  Forfeited To The King."

 

Also,  "Simon Burleigh,  The King's Chamberlain," Being Convicted

Of Treason,  "By Joint Consent Of The King And The Lords,  Sentence

Was Pronounced Against The Said Simon Burleigh,  That He Should Be

Drawn From The Town To Tyburn,  And There Be Hanged Till He Be

Dead,  And Then Have His Head Struck From His Body."

 

Also,  "John Beauchamp,  Steward Of The Household To The King, 

James Beroverse,  And John Salisbury; Knights,  Gentlemen Of The

Privy Chamber,  Were In Like Manner Condemned."   1 Hargrave's

State Trials,  First Case.

 

Here The Sentences Were All Fixed By The Peers,  With The Assent Of

The King. But That The King Should Be Consulted,  And His Assent

Obtained To The Sentence Pronounced By The Peers,  Does Not Imply 

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 4 Pg 75

Any Deficiency Of Power On Their Part To Fix The Sentence

Independently Of The King. There Are Obvious Reasons Why They

Might Choose To Consult The King,  And Obtain His Approbation Of The

Sentence They Were About To Impose,  Without Supposing Any Legal

Necessity For Their So Doing.

 

So Far As We Can Gather From The Reports Of State Trials,  Peers Of The

Realm Were Usually Sentenced By Those Who Tried Them,  With The

Assent Of The King.  But In Some Instances No Mention Is Made Of

The Assent Of The King,  As In The Case Of "Lionel,  Earl Of Middlesex,

Lord High Treasurer Of England," In 1624,  (Four Hundred Years

After Magna Carta,) Where The Sentence Was As Follows:

 

"This High Court Of Parliament Doth Adjudge,  That Lionel,  Earl Of

Middlesex,  Now Lord Treasurer Of England,  Shall Lose All His

Offices Which He Holds In This Kingdom,  And Shall,  Hereafter,  Be

Made Incapable Of Any Office,  Place,  Or Employment In The State

And Commonwealth. That He Shall Be Imprisoned In The Tower Of

London,  During The King's Pleasure. That He Shall Pay Unto Our

Sovereign Lord The King A Fine Of 50,000 Pounds. That He Shall

Never Sit In Parliament Any More,  And That He Shall Never Come

Within The Verge Of The Court."   2 Howell's Stale Trials,  1250.

 

Here Was A Peer Of The Realm,  And A Minister Of The King,  Of The

Highest Grade; And If It Were Ever Necessary To Obtain The Assent Of

The King To Sentences Pronounced By The Peers,  It Would Unquestionably

Have Been Obtained In This Instance,  And His Assent Would Have Appeared

In The Sentence.

 

Lord Bacon Was Sentenced By The House Of Lords,  (L620,) No

Mention Being Made Of The Assent Of The King.   The Sentence Is In

These Words:

 

"And,  Therefore,  This High Court Doth Adjudge,  That The Lord

Viscount St. Albans,  Lord Chancellor Of England,  Shall Undergo

Fine And Ransom Of 40,000 Pounds. That He Shall Be Imprisoned

In The Tower During The King's Pleasure. That He Shall Forever Be

Incapable Of Any Office,  Place,  Or Employment In The State Or

Commonwealth. That He Shall Never Sit In Parliament,  Nor Come

Within The Verge Of The Court."

 

And When It Was Demanded Of Him,  Before Sentence,  Whether It

Were His Hand That Was Subscribed To His Confession,  And Whether

He Would Stand To It; He Made The Following Answer,  Which Implies

That The Lords Were The Ones To Determine His Sentence. "My Lords, 

It Is My Act,  My Hand,  My Heart. I Beseech Your Lordships To Be

Merciful To A Broken Reed."   1 Hargrave's State Trials,  886   7.

 

The Sentence Against Charles The First,  (1648,) After Reciting

The Grounds Of His Condemnation,  Concludes In This Form:

 

"For All Which Treasons And Crimes,  This Court Doth Adjudge,

That He,  The Said Charles Stuart,  As A Tyrant,  Traitor,  Murderer,  And

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 4 Pg 76

Public Enemy To The Good People Of This Nation,  Shall Be  Put

To Death By The Severing His Head From His Body."

 

The Report Then Adds:

 

"This Sentence Being Read,  The President (Of The Court) Spake As

Followeth: 'This Sentence Now Read And Published,  Is The Act, 

Sentence,  Judgment And Resolution Of The Whole Court.'

1 Hargrave's State Trials,  1037.

 

Unless It Had Been The Received "Law Of The Land" That Those Who

Tried A Man Should Fix His Sentence,  It Would Have Required An Act

Of Parliament To Fix The Sentence Of Charles,  And His Sentence

Would Have Been Declared To Be "The Sentence Of The Law,"

Instead Of "The Act,  Sentence,  Judgment,  And Resolution Of

The Court."

 

But The Report Of The Proceedings In "The Trial Of Thomas,  Earl

Of Macclesfield,  Lord High Chancellor Of Great Britain, 

Before The House Of Lords,  For High Crimes And Misdemeanors

In The Execution Of His Office," In 1725,  Is So Full On This Point, 

And Shows So Clearly That It Rested Wholly With The Lords To

Fix The Sentence,  And That The Assent Of The King Was Wholly

Unnecessary,  That I Give The Report Somewhat At Length.

 

After Being Found Guilty,  The Earl Addressed The Lords,  For

A Mitigation Of Sentence,  As Follows:

 

"I Am Now To Expect Your Lordships' Judgment; And I Hope

That You Will Be Pleased To Consider That I Have Suffered

No Small Matter Already In The Trial,  In The Expense I Have

Been At,  The Fatigue,  And What I Have Suffered Otherways.

* * I Have Paid Back 10,800 Pounds Of The Money Already; I Have

Lost My Office; I Have Undergone The Censure Of Both Houses

Of Parliament,  Which Is In Itself A Severe Punishment,' "&C;.,  &C;.

 

On Being Interrupted,  He Proceeded: "My Lords,  I Submit

Whether This Be Not Proper In Mitigation Of Your Lordships'

Sentence; But Whether It Be Or Not,  I Leave Myself To Your

Lordships' Justice And Mercy; I Am Sure Neither Of Them Will Be

Wanting,  And I Entirely Submit.' * * *

 

"Then The Said Earl,  As Also The Managers,  Were Directed To

Withdraw; And The House (Of Lords) Ordered Thomas, 

Earl Of Macclesfield,  To Be Committed To The Custody Of The

Gentleman Usher Of The Black Rod; And Then Proceeded To

The Consideration  Of What Judgment," (That Is,  Sentence, 

For He Had Already Been Found Guilty,) "To Give Upon The

Impeachment Against The Said Earl."

 

"The Next Day,  The Commons,  With Their Speaker,  Being

Present At The Bar Of The House (Of Lords),  * * * The Speaker

Of The House Of Commons Said As Follows:

 

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 4 Pg 77

"My Lords,  The Knights,  Citizens,  And Burgesses In

Parliament Assembled,  In The Name Of Themselves,  And Of

All The Commons Of Great Britain,  Did At This Bar Impeach

Thomas,  Earl Of Macclesfield,  Of High Crimes And

Misdemeanors,  And Did Exhibit Articles Of Impeachment

Against Him,  And Have Made Good Their Charge. I Do, 

Therefore,  In The Name Of The Knights,  Citizens,  And

Burgesses,  In Parliament Assembled,  And Of All The Commons

Of Great Britain,  Demand Judgment (Sentence) Of Your

Lordships Against Thomas,  Earl Of Macclesfield,  For The

Said High Crimes And Misdemeanors.'

 

"Then The Lord Chief Justice King,  Speaker Of The House

Of Lords,  Said: 'Mr. Speaker,  The Lords Are Now Ready

To Proceed To Judgment In The Case By You Mentioned.'

 

"Thomas,  Earl Of Macclesfielg,  The Lords Have

Unanimously Found You Guilty Of High Crimes And

Misdemeanors,  Charged On You By The Impeachment Of

The House Of Commons,  And Do Now,  According To Law, 

Proceed To Judgment Against You,  Which I Am Ordered

To Pronounce. Their Lordships' Judgment Is,  And This High

Court Doth Adjudge,  That You,  Thomas,  Earl Of

Macclesfield,  Be Fined In The Sum Of Thirty Thousand

Pounds Unto Our Sovereign Lord The King; And That You

Shall Be Imprisoned In The Tower Of London,  And There

Kept In Safe Custody,  Until Yon Shall Pay The Said Fine.'"

6 Hargrave's State Trials,  762   3   4.

 

This Case Shows That The Principle Of Magna Carta,  That

A Man Should Be Sentenced Only By His Peers,  Was In Force, 

And Acted Upon As Law,  In England,  So Lately As 1725,  (Five

Hundred Years After Magna Carta,) So Far As It Applied To A

Peer Of The Realm,  A Severe Punishment," Ect.,  Ect.

 

But The Same Principle,  On This Point,  That Applies To A Peer

Of The Realm,  Applies To Every Freeman. The Only

Difference Between The Two Is,  That The Peers Of The Realm

Have Had Influence Enough To Preserve Their Constitutional

Rights; While The Constitutional Rights Of The People Have Been

Trampled Upon And Rendered Obsolete By The Usurpation And

Corruption Of The Government And The Courts.

 

Section V. The Oaths Of Judges

 

As Further Proof That The Legislation Of The King,  Whether

Enacted With Or Without The Assent And Advice Of His Parliaments,

Was Of No Authority Unless It Were Consistent With The Common

Law,  And Unless Juries And Judges Saw Fit To Enforce It,  It May Be

Mentioned That It Is Probable That No Judge In England Was Ever

Sworn To Observe The Laws Enacted Either By The King Alone, 

Or By The King With The Advice And Assent Of Parliament.

 

The Judges Were Sworn To "Do Equal Law,  And Execution Of Right,  

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 4 Pg 78

To All The King's Subjects,  Rich And Poor,  Without Having

Regard To Any Person;" And That They Will "Deny No Man

Common Right;" [28] But They Were Not Sworn To Obey Or

Execute Any Statutes Of The King,  Or Of The King And Parliament.

Indeed,  They Are Virtually Sworn Not To Obey Any Statutes That

Are Against "Common Right," Or Contrary To "The Common Law,"

Or "Law Of The Land;" But To "Certify The King Thereof"  That Is, 

Notify Him That His Statutes Are Against The Common Law; 

And Then Proceed To Execute The Common Law,  Notwithstanding

Such Legislation To The Contrary. The Words Of The Oath On This Point

Are These:

 

"That Ye Deny No Man Common Right By (Virtue Of) The King's

Letters,  Nor None Other Man's,  Nor For None Other Cause; And In

Case Any Letters Come To You Contrary To The Law,  (That Is,  The

Common Law,  As Will Be Seen On Reference To The Entire Oath Given

In The Note,) That Ye Do Nothing By Such Letters,  But Certify The

King Thereof,  And Proceed To Execute The Law,  (That Is,  The

Common Law,) Notwithstanding The Same Letters."

 

Where It Is Considered That The King Was The Sole Legislative

Power,  And That He Exercised This Power,  To A Great Extent,  By

Orders In Council,  And By Writs And "Letters" Addressed

Oftentimes To Some Sheriff,  Or Other Person,  And That His

Commands,  When Communicated To His Justices,  Or Any

Other Person,  "By Letters," Or Writs,  Under Seal,  Had As Much

Legal Authority As Laws Promulgated In Any Other Form

Whatever,  It Will Be Seen That This Oath Of The Justices

Absolutely Required That They Disregard Any Legislation That

Was Contrary To "Common Right," Or "The Common Law,"

And Notify The King That It Was Contrary To Common Right, 

Or The Common Law,  And Then Proceed To Execute The

Common Law,  Notwithstanding Such Legislation. [29]

 

If There Could Be Any Doubt That Such Was The Meaning

Of This Oath,  That Doubt Would Be Removed By A Statute

Passed By The King Two Years Afterwards,  Which Fully

Explains This Oath,  As Follows:

 

"Edward,  By The Grace Of God,  Ect.,  To The Sheriff Of

Stafford,  Greeting: Because That By Divers Complaints

Made To Us,  We Have Perceived That The Law Of The Land, 

Which We By Our Oath Are Bound To Maintain,  Is The Less

Well Kept,  And The Execution Of The Same Disturbed Many

Times By Maintenance And Procurement,  As Well In The

Court As In The Country; We Greatly Moved Of Conscience

In This Matter,  And For This Cause Desiring As Much For

The  Pleasure Of God,  And Ease And Quietness Of Our

Subjects,   As To Save Our Conscience,  And For To Save

And Keep Our Said Oath,  By The Assent Of The Great Men

And Other Wise Men Of Our Council,  We Have Ordained

These Things Following:

 

"First,  We Have Commanded All Our Justices,  That They 

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 4 Pg 79

Shall From Henceforth Do Equal Law And Execution Of

Right To All Our Subjects,  Rich And Poor,  Without Having

Regard To Any Person,  And Without Omitting To Do Right

For Any Letters Or Commandment Which May Come To

Them From Us,  Or From Any Other,  Or By Any Other Cause.

And If That Any Letters,  Writs,  Or Commandments Come

To The Justices,  Or To Other Deputed To Do Law And Right

According To The Usage Of The Realm,  In Disturbance Of

The Law,  Or Of The Execution Of The Same,  Or Of Right To

The Parties,  The Justices And Other Aforesaid Shall

Proceed And Hold Their Courts And Processes, 

Where The Pleas And Matters Be Depending Before

Them,  As If No Such Letters,  Writs,  Or Commandments

Were Come To Them; And They Shall Certify Us And

Our Council Of Such Commandments Which Be

Contrary To The Law,  (That Is,  "The Law Of The Land,"

Or Common Law,) As Afore Is Said." [30] And To The

Intent That Our Justices,  Shall Do Even Right To All

People In The Manner Aforesaid,  Without More

Favor Showing To One Than To Another,  We Have

Ordained And Caused Our Said Justices To Be Sworn, 

That They Shall Not From Henceforth,  As Long As

They Shall Be In The Office Of Justice,  Take Fee Nor

Robe Of Any Man,  But Of Ourself,  And That They Shall

Take No Gift Nor Reward By Themselves,  Nor By Other, 

Privily Nor Apertly,  Of Any Man That Hath To Do Before

Them By Any Way,  Except Meat And Drink,  And That

Of Small Value: And That They Shall Give No Counsel

To Great Men Or Small,  In Case Where We Be Party, 

Or Which Do Or May Touch Us In Any Point,  Upon

Pain To Be At Our Will,  Body,  Lands,  And Goods,  To

Do Thereof As Shall Please Us,  In Case They Do Contrary.

And For This Cause We Have Increased The Fees Of

The Same,  Our Justices,  In Such Manner As It Ought

Reasonably To Suffice Them."   20 Edward Iii., 

Ch. L. (1346.)

 

Other Statutes Of Similar Tenor Have Been Enacted

As Follows:

 

"It Is Accorded And Established,  That It Shall Not

Be Commanded By The Great Seal,  Nor The Little Seal,

To Disturb Or Delay Common Right; And Though Such

Commandments Do Come,  The Justices Shall Not

Therefore Leave (Omit) To Do Right In Any Point."  

St. 2 Edward Iii.,  Ch. 8. (1328.)

 

"That By Commandment Of The Great Seal,  Or Privy

Seal,  No Point Of This Statute Shall Be Put In Delay;

Nor That The Justices Of Whatsoever Place It Be Shall

Let (Omit) To Do The Common Law,  By Commandment, 

Which Shall Come To Them Under The Great Seal,  Or The

Privy Seal."   14 Edward Iii,  St. 1,  Ch. 14. (1340.)

 

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 4 Pg 80

"It Is Ordained And Established,  That Neither Letters

Of The Signet,  Nor Of The King's Privy Seal,  Shall Be

From Henceforth Sent In Damage Or Prejudice Of The

Realm,  Nor In Disturbance Of The Law" (The Common Law). 

11 Richard Ii.,  Ch. 10. (1387.)

 

It Is Perfectly Apparent From These Statutes,  And From

The Oath Administered To The Justices,  That It Was A

Matter Freely Confessed By The King Himself,  That His

Statutes Were Of No Validity,  If Contrary To The Common

Law,  Or "Common Right."

 

The Oath Of The Justices,  Before Given,  Is,  I Presume, 

The Same That Has Been Administered To Judges In

England From The Day When It Was First Prescribed To

Them,  (1344,) Until Now. I Do Not Find From The English

Statutes That The Oath Has Ever Been Changed. The Essay

On Grand Juries,  Before Referred To,  And Supposed To Have

Been Written By Lord Somers,  Mentions This Oath

(Page 73) As Being Still Administered To Judges,  That Is, 

In The Time Of Charles Ii.,  More Than Three Hundred Years

After The Oath Was First Ordained.

 

If The Oath Has Never Been Changed,  It Follows That

Judges Have Not Only Never Been Sworn To Support Any

Statutes Whatever Of The King,  Or Of Parliament,  But That, 

For Five Hundred Years Past,  They Actually Have Been

Sworn To Treat As Invalid All Statutes That Were Contrary

To The Common Law.

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 5 Pg 81

That The Legislation Of The King Was Of No Authority Over

A Jury,  Is Further Proved By The Oath Taken By The Kings

At Their Coronation. This Oath Seems To Have Been

Substantially The Same,  From The Time Of The Saxon Kings, 

Down To The Seventeenth Century,  As Will Be Seen From The

Authorities Hereafter Given.

 

 

 

 

 

The Purport Of The Oath Is,  That The King Swears To Maintain

The Law Of The Land   That Is,  The Common Law. In

Other Words,  He Swears "To Concede And Preserve To

The English People The Laws And Customs Conceded To Them

By The Ancient,  Just,  And Pious English Kings,  * * And

Especially The Laws,  Customs,  And Liberties Conceded To

The Clergy And People By The Illustrious King Edward;" * *

And "The Just Laws And Customs Which The Common People

Have Chosen,  (Quas Vulgus Elegit)."

 

These Are The Same Laws And Customs Which Were Called 

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 5 Pg 82

By The General Name Of "The Law Of The Land," Or "The

Common Law," And,  With Some Slight Additions,  Were

Embodied In Magna Carta.

 

This Oath Not Only Forbids The King To Enact Any Statutes

Contrary To The Common Law,  But It Proves That His Statutes

Could Be Of No Authority Over The Consciences Of A Jury;

Since,  As Has Already Been Sufficiently Shown,  It Was One

Part Of This Very Common Law Itself,    That Is,  Of The

Ancient "Laws,  Customs,  And Liberties," Mentioned In The

Oath,    That Juries Should Judge Of All Questions That Came

Before Them,  According To Their Own Consciences, 

Independently Of The Legislation Of The King.

 

It Was Impossible That This Right Of The Jury Could Subsist

Consistently With Any Right,  On The Part Of The King,  To

Impose Any Authoritative Legislation Upon Them. His

Oath,  Therefore,  To Maintain The Law Of The Land,  Or The

Ancient "Laws,  Customs,  And Liberties," Was Equivalent

To An Oath That He Would Never Assume To Impose Laws Upon

Juries,  As Imperative Rules Of Decision,  Or Take From

Them The Right To Try All Cases According To Their Own

Consciences. It Is Also An Admission That He Had No

Constitutional Power To Do So,  If He Should Ever Desire

It. This Oath,  Then,  Is Conclusive Proof That His Legislation

Was Of No Authority With A Jury,  And That They Were

Under No Obligation Whatever To Enforce It,  Unless It

Coincided With Their Own Ideas Of Justice.

 

The Ancient Coronation Oath Is Printed With The

Statutes Of The Realm,  Vol. I.,  P. 168,  And Is As Follows: [31]

 

Translation.

 

"Form Of The Oath Of The King Of England,  On His

Coronation.

 

(The Archbishop Of Canterbury,  To Whom,  Of Right And

Custom Of The Church Of Canterbury,  Ancient And

Approved,  It Pertains To Anoint And Crown The Kings Of

England,  On The Day Of The Coronation Of The King,  And

Before The King Is Crowned,  Shall Propound The

Underwritten Questions To The King.)

 

The Laws And Customs,  Conceded To The English People

By The Ancient,  Just,  And Pious English Kings,  Will You

Concede And Preserve To The Same People,  With The

Confirmation Of An Oath? And Especially The Laws,  Customs,

And Liberties Conceded To The Clergy And People By The

Illustrious King Edward?

 

(And The King Shall Answer,) I Do Concede,  And Will

Preserve Them,  And Confirm Them By My Oath.

 

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 5 Pg 83

Will Yon Preserve To The Church Of God,  The Clergy,  And

The People,  Entire Peace And Harmony In God,  According

To Your Powers? 

 

(And The King Shall Answer,) I Will.

 

In All Your Judgments,  Will You Cause Equal And Right

Justice And Discretion To Be Done,  In Mercy And Truth, 

According To Your Powers?

 

(And The King Shall Answer,) I Will.

 

Do You Concede That The Just Laws And Customs,  Which

The Common People Have Chosen,  Shall Be Preserved;

And Do You Promise That They Shall Be Protected By You, 

And Strengthened To The Honor Of God,  According To

Your Powers?

 

(And The King Shall Answer,) I Concede And Promise."

 

The Language Used In The Last Of These Questions, 

"Do You Concede That The Just Laws And Customs, 

Which The Common People Have Chosen,  (Quas Vulgus

Elegit,) Shall Be Preserved?" Ect.,  Is Worthy Of Especial

Notice,  As Showing That The Laws,  Which Were To Be

Preserved,  Were Not Necessarily All The Laws Which

The Kings Enacted,  But Only Such Of Them As The Common

People Had Selected Or Approved.

 

And How Had The Common People Made Known Their

Approbation Or Selection Of These Laws? Plainly,  In No

Other Way Than This   That The Juries Composed Of The

Common People Had Voluntarily Enforced Them.

The Common People Had No Other Legal Form Of Making

Known Their Approbation Of Particular Laws.

 

The Word "Concede," Too,  Is An Important Word. In The

English Statutes It Is Usually Translated Grant  As If With

An Intention To Indicate That "The Laws,  Customs,  And

Liberties" Of The English People Were Mere Privileges, 

Granted To Them By The King; Whereas It Should Be

Translated Concede,  To Indicate Simply An Acknowledgment, 

On The Part Of The King,  That Such Were The Laws,  Customs, 

And Liberties,  Which Had Been Chosen And Established

By The People Themselves,  And Of Right Belonged To Them, 

And Which He Was Bound To Respect.

 

I Will Now Give Some Authorities To Show That The Foregoing

Oath Has,  In Substance,  Been The Coronation Oath From

The Times Of William The Conqueror,  (1066,) Down To The

Time Of James The First,  And Probably Until 1688.

 

It Will Be Noticed,  In The Quotation From Kelham,  That He

Says This Oath (Or The Oath Of William The Conqueror) Is 

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 5 Pg 84

In Sense And Substance The Very Same With That Which The

Saxon Kings Used To Take At Their Coronations."

 

Hale Says:

 

"Yet The English Were Very Zealous For Them," (That Is,  For

The Laws Of Edward The Confessor,) "No Less Or Otherwise

Than They Are At This Time For The Great Charter; Insomuch

That They Were Never Satisfied Till The Said Laws Were

Reenforced,  And Mingled,  For The Most Part,  With The

Coronation Oath Of King William I.,  And Some Of His

Successors."   1 Hale's History Of Common Law,  157.

 

Also,  "William,  On His Coronation,  Had Sworn To Govern

By The Laws Of Edward The Confessor,  Some Of Which Had

Been Reduced Into Writing,  But The Greater Part Consisted

Of The Immemorial Customs Of The Realm."   Ditto,  P. 202, 

Note L.

 

Kelham Says:

 

"Thus Stood The Laws Of England At The Entry Of William I., 

And It Seems Plain That The Laws,  Commonly Called The Laws

Of Edward The Confessor,  Were At That Time The Standing

Laws Of The Kingdom,  And Considered The Great Rule Of Their

Rights And Liberties; And That The Eriglish Were So Zealous

For Them,  'That They Were Never Satisfied Till The Said Laws

Were Reenforced,  And Mingled,  For The Most Part,  With The

Coronation Oath.' Accordingly,  We Find That This Great

Conqueror,  At His Coronation On The Christmas Day Succeeding

His Victory,  Took An Oath At The Altar Of St. Peter,  Westminster, 

In Sense And Substance The Very Same With That Which The

Saxon Kings Used To Take At Their Coronations. * * And At

Barkhamstead,  In The Fourth Year Of His Reign,  In The Presence

Of Lanfranc,  Archbishop Of Canterbury,  For The Quieting Of

The People,  He Swore That He Would Inviolably Observe The Good

And Approved Ancient Laws Which Had Been Made By The Devout

And Pious Kings Of England,  His Ancestors,  And Chiefly By King

Edward; And We Are Told That The People Then Departed In Good

Humor."   Kelham's Preliminary Discourse To The Laws Of

William The Conqueror. See,  Also,  1 Hale's History Of The

Common Law,  186.

 

Crabbe Says That William The Conqueror "Solemnly Swore That

He Would Observe The Good And Approved Laws Of Edward The

Confessor."   Crabbe's History Of The English Law,  P. 43.

 

The Successors Of William,  Up To The Time Of Magna Carta, 

Probably All Took The Same Oath,  According To The Custom Of The

Kingdom; Although There May Be No Historical Accounts Extant

Of The Oath Of Each Separate King. But History Tells Us Specially

That Henry I.,  Stephen,  And Henry Ii.,  Confirmed These Ancient

Laws And Customs. It Appears,  Also,  That The Barons Desired Of

John (What He Afterwards Granted By Magna Carta) "That The Laws 

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 5 Pg 85

And Liberties Of King Edward,  With Other Privileges Granted To The

Kingdom And Church Of England,  Might Be Confirmed,  As They

Were Contained In The Charters Of Henry The First; Further Alleging, 

That At The Time Of His Absolution,  He Promised By His Oath To

Observe These Very Laws And Liberties."   Echard's History Of

England,  P. 105 6.

 

It Would Appear,  From The Following Authorities,  That Since

Magna Carta The Form Of The Coronation Oath Has Been

"To Maintain The Law Of The Land,"   Meaning That Law As

Embodied In Magna Carta. Or Perhaps It Is More Probable That

The Ancient Form Has Been Still Observed,  But That,  As Its Substance

And Purport Were "To Maintain The Law Of The Land," This Latter

Form Of Expression Has Been Used,  In The Instances Here Cited,  From

Motives Of Brevity And Convenience. This Supposition Is The

More Probable,  From The Fact That I Find No Statute Prescribing A

Change In The Form Of The Oath Until 1688.

 

That Magna Carta Was Considered As Embodying "The Law Of

The Land," Or "Common Law," Is Shown By A Statute Passed By

Edward I.,  Wherein He "Grants," Or Concedes,

 

"That The Charter Of Liberties And The Charter Of The Forest

* * Shall Be Kept In Every Point,  Without Breach,  * * And That Our

Justices,  Sheriffs,  Mayors,  And Other Ministers,  Which,  Under

Us,  Have The Laws Of Our Land [32] To Guide,  Shall Allow The Said

Charters Pleaded Before Them In Judgment,  In All Their Points, 

That Is,  To Wit,  The Great Charter As The Common Law,  And The

Charter Of The Forest For The Wealth Of The Realm.

 

"And We Will,  That If Any Judgment Be Given From Henceforth, 

Contrary To The Points Of The Charters Aforesaid,  By The Justices,  Or

By Any Other Our Ministers That Hold Plea Before Them Against

The Points Of The Charters,  It Shall Be Undone,  And Holden For

Naught."   25 Edward I.,  Ch. 1 And 2. (1297.)

 

Blackstone Also Says:

 

"It Is Agreed By All Our Historians That The Great Charter Of King

John Was,  For The Most Part,  Compiled From The Ancient Customs Of

The Realm,  Or The Laws Of Edward The Confessor; By Which They

Usually Mean The Old Common Law Which Was Established Under

Our Saxon Princes."   Blackstone's Introduction To The Charters.

See Blackstone's Law Tracts,  289.

 

Crabbe Says:

 

"It Is Admitted,  On All Hands,  That It (Magna Carta) Contains Nothing

But What Was Confirmatory Of The Common Law,  And The

Ancient Usages Of The Realm,  And Is,  Properly Speaking,  Only An

Enlargement Of The Charter Of Henry I.,  And His Successors."  

Crabbe's History Of The English Law,  P. 127.

 

That The Coronation Oath Of The Kings Subsequent To Magna Carta 

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 5 Pg 86

Was,  In Substance,  If Not In Form,  "To Maintain This Law Of The

Land,  Or Common Law," Is Shown By A Statute Of Edward Third, 

Commencing As Follows:

 

"Edward,  By The Grace Of God,  Ect.,  Ect.,  To The Sheriff Of

Stafford,  Greeting: Because That By Divers Complaints Made

To Us,  We Have Perceived That The Law Of The Land,  Which We

By Oath Are Bound To Maintain," Ect.   St. 20 Edward Iii. (1346.)

 

The Following Extract From Lord Somers' Tract On Grand Juries

Shows That The Coronation Oath Continued The Same As Late As

1616,  (Four Hundred Years After Magna Carta.) He Says:

 

"King James,  In His Speech To The Judges,  In The Star Chamber, 

Anno 1616,  Told Them,  'That He Had,  After Many Years,  Resolved

To Renew His Oath,  Made At His Coronation,  Concerning Justice, 

And The Promise Therein Contained For Maintaining The Law Of

The Land.' And,  In The Next Page Save One,  Says,  'I Was Sworn To

Maintain The Law Of The Land,  And Therefore Had Been Perjured

If I Had Broken It. God Is My Judge,  I Never Intended It.'

"Somers On Grand Juries,  P. 82.

 

In 1688,  The Coronation Oath Was Changed By Act Of Parliament, 

And The King Was Made To Swear:

 

"To Govern The People Of This Kingdom Of England,  And The

Dominions Thereto Belonging,  According To The Statutes In

Parliament Agreed On,  And The Laws And Customs Of The

Same."   St. 1 William And Mary,  Ch. 6. (1688.)

 

The Effect And Legality Of This Oath Will Hereafter Be

Considered. For The Present It Is Sufficient To Show,  As Has

Been Already Sufficiently Done,  That From The Saxon Times

Until At Least As Lately As 1616,  The Coronation Oath Has

Been,  In Substance,  To Maintain The Law Of The Land,  Or

The Common Law,  Meaning Thereby The Ancient Saxon

Customs,  As Embodied In The Laws Of Alfred,  Of Edward

The Confessor,  And Finally In Magna Carta.

 

It May Here Be Repeated That This Oath Plainly Proves That

The Statutes Of The King Were Of No Authority Over Juries,  If

Inconsistent With Their Ideas Of Right; Because It Was One

Part Of The Common Law That Juries Should Try All Causes

According To Their Own Consciences,  Any Legislation Of The

King To The Contrary Notwithstanding.[33]

 

[1] Hale Says:"The Trial By Jury Of Twelve Men Was The Usual

Trial Among The Normans,  In Most Suits; Especially In Assizes,  Et

Juris Utrum."   1 Hale's History Of The Common Law,  219

 

This Was In Normandy,  Before The Conquest Of England By The

Normans. See Ditto,  P. 218.

 

Crabbe Says:"It Cannot Be Denied That The Practice Of Submitting

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 5 Pg 87

Causes To The Decision Of Twelve Men Was Universal Among All The

Northern Tribes (Of Europe) From The Very Remotest Antiquity." 

Crabbe's History Of The English Law,  P. 32.

 

[2] "The People,  Who In Every General Council Or Assembly Could

Oppose And Dethrone Their Sovereigns,  Were In Little Dread Of

Their Encroachments On Their Liberties; And Kings,  Who Found

Sufficient Employment In Keeping Possession Of Their Crowns,

Would Not Likely Attack The More Important Privileges Of Their

Subjects."

 

[3] This Office Was Afterwards Committed To Sheriffs. But Even

While The Court Was Held By The Lord,  "The Lord Was Not Judge,

But The Pares (Peers) Only."   Gilbert On The Court Of Exchequer,

61-2.

 

[4] The Opinion Expressed In The Text,  That The Witan Had No

Legislative Authority,  Is Corroborated By The Following

Authorities:

 

"From The Fact That The New Laws Passed By The King And The Witan

Were Laid Before The Shire-Mote,  (County Court,) We Should Be

Almost Justified In The Inference That A Second Sanction Was

Necessary Before They Could Have The Effect Of Law In That

Particular County."   Durham's Middle Ages,  Sec. 2,  B. 2,  Ch. L.

57 Lardner's Cab. Cyc.,  53.

 

The "Second Sanction" Required To Give The Legislation Of The

King And Witan The Effect Of Law,  Was Undoubtedly,  I Think,  As A

General Thing,  The Sanction Of A Jury. I Know Of No Evidence

Whatever That Laws Were Ever Submitted To Popular Vote In The

County Courts,  As This Author Seems To Suppose Possible. Another

Mode,  Sometimes Resorted To For Obtaining The Sanction Of The

People To The Laws Of The Witan,  Was,  It Seems,  To Persuade The

People Themselves To Swear To Observe Them. Mackintoshsays:

 

"The Preambles Of The Laws (Of The Witan) Speak Of The Infinite

Number Of Liegemen Who Attended,  As Only Applauding The

Measures Of The Assembly. But This Applause Was Neither So

Unimportant To The Success Of The Measures,  Nor So Precisely

Distinguished From A Share In Legislation,  As Those Who Read History

With A Modern Eye Might Imagine. It Appears That Under Athelstan

Expedients Were Resorted To,  To Obtain A Consent To The Law From

Great Bodies Of The People In Their Districts,  Which Their Numbers

Rendered Impossible In A National Assembly. That Monarch Appears

To Have Sent Commissioners To Hold Shire-Gemotes Or County

Meetings,  Where They Proclaimed The Laws Made By The King And

His Counsellors,  Which,  Being Acknowledged And Sworn To At These

Folk-Motes (Meetings Of The People) Became,  By Their Assent,

Completely Binding On The Whole Nation."   Mackintosh's Hist. Of

England,  Ch. 2. 45 Lardner's Cab. Cc.,  75.

 

[5] Page 31.

 

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 5 Pg 88

[6] Hallam Says,  "It Was,  However,  To The County Court That An

English Freeman Chiefly Looked For The Maintenance Of His Civil

Rights."   2 Middle Ages,  392.

 

Also,  "This (The County Court) Was The Great Constitutional

Judicature In All Ques- Tions Of Civil Right."   Ditto,  395.

Also,  "The Liberties Of These Anglo-Saxon Thanes Were Chiefly

Secured,  Next To Their Swords And Their Free Spirits,  By The

Inestimable Right Of Deciding Civil And Criminal Suits In Their

Own County Courts."   Ditto,  899.

 

[7] "Alfred May,  In One Sense,  Be Called The Founder Of These

Laws,  (The Saxon,) For Until His Time They Were An Unwrittencode,

But He Expressly Says,  'That I,  Alfred,  Collected The Good Laws Of

Our Forefathers Into One Code,  And Also I Wrote Them Down'

-- Which Is A Decisive Fact In The History Of Our Laws Well

Worth Noting."   Introduction To Gilbert's History Of The Common

Pleas,  P. 2,  Note.

 

Kelham Says,  "Let Us Consult Our Own Lawyers And Historians,  And

They Will Tell As That Alfred,  Edgar,  And Edward The Confessor,

Were The Great Compilers And Restorers Of The English Laws." 

Kelham's Preliminary Discourse To The Laws Of William The

Conqueror,  P. 12. Appendix To Kelham's Dictionary Of The Norman

Language.

 

"He (Alfred) Also,  Like Another Theodosius,  Collected The Various

Customs That He Found Dispersed In The Kingdom,  And Reduced And

Digested Them Into One Uniform System,  Or Code Of Laws,  In His

Som-Bec,  Or Liber Judicialis (Judicial Book). This He Compiled

For The Use Of The Court Baron,  Hundred And County Court,  The

Court-Leet And Sheriff's Toarn,  Tribunals Which He Established

For The Trial Of All Causes,  Civil And Criminal,  In The Very

Districts Wherein The Complaints Arose."   4 Blackstone,  411.

 

Alfred Himself Says,  "Hence I,  King Alfred,  Gathered These

Together,  And Commanded Many Of Those To Be Written Down Which

Our Forefathers Observed   Those Which I Liked   And Those Which

I Did Not Like,  By The Advice Of My Witan,  I Threw Aside. For I

Durst Not Venture To Set Down In Writing Over Many Of My Own,

Since I Knew Not What Among Them Would Please Those That Should

Come After Us. But Those Which I Met With Either Of The Days Of

Me,  My Kinsman,  Or Of Offa,  King Of Mercia,  Or Of Aethelbert,  Who

Was The First Of The English Who Received Baptism   Thse Which

Appeared To Me The Justest   I Have Here Collected,  And Abandoned

The Others. Then I,  Alfred,  King Of The West Saxons,  Showed These

To All My Witan,  And They Then Said That They Were All Willing To

Observe Them."   Laws Of Alfred,  Translated By R. Price,  Prefixed

To Mackintosh's History Of England,  Vol. L. 45 Lardner's Cab. Cyc.

 

"King Edward * * Projected And Begun What His Grandson,  King

Edward The Confessor,  Afterwards Completed,  Viz.,  One Uniform

Digest Or Body Of Laws To Be Observed Throughout The Whole

Kingdom,  Being Probably No More Than A Revival Of King Alfred's

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 5 Pg 89

Code,  With Some Improvements Suggested By Necessity And

Experience,  Particularly The Incorporating Some Of The British,

Or,  Rather,  Mercian Customs,  And Also Such Of The Danish

(Customs) As Were Reasonable And Approved,  Into The West Saxon

Lage,  Which Was Still The Ground-Work Of The Whole. And This

Appears To Be The Best Supported And Most Plausible Conjecture,

(For Certainty Is Not To Be Expected,) Of The Rise And Original

Of That Admirable System Of Maxims And Unwritten Customs Which

Is Now Known By The Name Of The Common Law,  As Extending Its

Authority Universally Over All The Realm,  And Which Is Doubtless

Of Saxon Parentage."   4 Blackstone,  412.

 

"By The Lex Terrae And Lex Regni Is Understood The Laws Of

Edward The Confessor,  Confirmed And Enlarged As They Were By William

The Conqueror; And This Constitution Or Code Of Laws Is What Even To

This Day Are Called 'The Common Law Of The Land.'"   Introduction

To Gilbert's History Of The Common Pleas,  P. 22,  Note.

 

 

 

 

 

[8] Not The Conqueror Of The English People,  (As The Friends Of

Liberty Maintain,) But Only Of Harold The Usurper.   See Hale's

History Of The Common,  Law,  Ch. 5.

 

[9] For All These Codes See Wilkins' Laws Of The Anglo-Saxons.

 

"Being Regulations Adapted To Existing Institutions,  The

Anglo-Saxon Statutes Are Concise And Technical,  Alluding To The

Law Which Was Then Living And In Vigor,  Rather Than Defining It.

The Same Clauses And Chapters Are Often Repeated Word,  For Word,

In The Statutes Of Subsequent Kings,  Showing That Enactments

Which Bear The Appearance Of Novelty Are Merely Declaratory.

Consequently The Appearance Of A Law,  Seemingly For The First

Time,  Is By No Means To Be Considered As A Proof That The Matter

Which It Contains Is New; Nor Can We Trace The Progress Of The

Anglo-Saxon Institutions With Any Degree Of Certainty,  By

Following The Dates Of The Statutes In Which We Find Them First

Noticed. All Arguments Founded On The Apparent Chronology Of The

Subjects Included In The Laws,  Are Liable To Great Fallacies.

Furthermore,  A Considerable Portion Of The Anglo-Saxon Law Was

Never Recorded In Writing. There Can Be No Doubt But That The

Rules Of Inheritance Were Well Established And,  Defined; Yet We

Have Not A Single Law,  And Hardly A Single Document From Which

The Course Of The Descent Of Land Can Be Inferred. * * Positive

Proof Cannot Be Obtained Of The Commencement Of Any Institution,

Because The First Written Law Relating To It May Possibly Be

Merely Confirmatory Or Declaratory; Neither Can The Non-Existence

Of Any Institution Be Inferred From The Absence Of Direct

Evidence. Written Laws Were Modified And Controlled By Customs

Of Which No Trace Can Be Discovered Until After The Lapse Of

Centuries,  Although Those Usages Must Have Been In Constant Vigor

During The Long Interval Of Silence."   1 Palgrave's Rise And

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 5 Pg 90

Progress Of The English Commonwealth,  58-9.

 

[10] Rapin Says,  "The Customs Now Practised In England Are,  For

The Most Part,  The Same As The Anglo-Saxons Brought With Them

From Germany."   Rapin's Dissertation On The Government Of The

Anglo-Saxons,  Vol. 2,  Oct Ed.,  P. 138. See Kelham's Discourse

Before Named.

 

[11] Hallam Says,  "The County Of Sussex Contains Sixty-Five

('Hundreds'); That Of Dorset Forty-Three; While Yorkshire Has

Only Twenty-Six; And Lancashire But Six."   2 Middle Ages,  391.

 

[12] Excepting Also Matters Pertaining To The Collection Of The

Revenue,  Which Were Determined In The King's Court Of Exchequer.

But Even In This Court It Was The Law "That None Be Amerced But

By His Peers."   Mirror Of Justices,  49.

 

[13] "For The English Laws,  Although Not Written,  May,  As It

Should Seem,  And That Without Any Absurdity,  Be Termed Laws,

(Since This Itself Is Law   That Which Pleases The Prince Has The

Force Of Law,) I Mean Those Laws Which It Is Evident Were

Promuulgated By The Advice Of The Nobles And The Authority Of The

Prince,  Concerning Doubts To Be Settled In Their Assembly. For If

From The Mere Want Of Writing Only,  They Should Not Be Considered

Laws,  Then,  Unquestionably,  Writing Would Seem To Confer More

Authority Upon Laws Themselves,  Than Either The Equity Of The

Persons Constituting,  Or The Reason Of Those Framing Them."  

Glanville's Preface,  P. 38. (Glanville Was Chief Justice Of Henry

Ii.,  1180.) 2 Turner's History Of The Anglo-Saxons,  280.

 

[14] Mackintosh's History Of England,  Ch. 3. Lardner's Cabinet

Cyclopedia,  286.

 

[15] If The Laws Of The King Were Received As Authoritative By

The Juries,  What Occasion Was There For His Appointing Special

Commissioners For The Trial Of Offences,  Without The Intervention

Of A Jury,  As He Frequently Did,  In Manifest And Acknowledged

Violation Of Magna Carta,  And "The Law Of The Land?" These

Appointments Were Undoubtedly Made For No Other Reason Than That

The Juries Were Not Sufficiently Subservient,  But Judged

According To Their Own Notions Of Right,  Instead Of The Will Of

The King   Whether The Latter Were Expressed In His Statutes,  Or

By His Judges.

 

[16] Of Course,  Mr. Reeve Means To Be Understood That,  In The

Hundred Court,  And Court-Leet,  The Jurors Were The Judges,  As He

Declares Them To Have Been In The County Court; Otherwise The

"Bailiff" Or "Steward" Must Have Been Judge.

 

[17] The Jurors Were Sometimes Called " Assessors," Because They

Assessed,  Or Determined The Amount Of Fines And Amercements To

Be Imposed.

 

[18] "The Barons Of The Hundred" Were The Freeholders. Hallam

Says: "The Word Baro,  Originally Meaning Only A Man,  Was Of Very

Large Significance,  And Is Not Unfrequently Applied To Common

Freeholders,  As In The Phrase Court-Baron."   3 Middle Ages,

14-15.

 

Blackstone Says: "The Court-Baron *  * Is A Court Of Common Law,

And It Is The Court Of The Barons,  By Which Name The Freeholders

Were Sometimes Anciently Called; For That It Is Held Before The

Freeholders Who Owe Suit And Service To The Manor."   3

Blackstone,  33.

 

[19] The Ancient Jury Courts Kept No Records,  Because Those Who

Composed The Courts Could Neither Make Nor Read Records. Their

Decisions Were Preserved By The Memories Of The Jurors And Other

Persons Present.

 

[20] Stuart Says:

 

"The Courts,  Or Civil Arrangements,  Which Were

Modelled In Germany,  Preserved The Independence Of The People;

Aud Having Followed The Saxons Into England,  And Continuing Their

Importance,  They Supported The Envied Liberty We Boast Of.

 

"As A Chieftain Led Out His Retainers To The Field,  And Governed

Them During War; So In Peace He Summoned Them Together,  And

Exerted A Civil Jurisdiction. He Was At Once Their Captain And

Their Judge. They Constituted His Court; And Having Inquired With

Him Into The Guilt Of Those Of Their Order Whom Justice Had

Accused,  They Assisted Him To Enforce His Decrees.

 

"This Court (The Court-Baron) Was Imported Into England; But The

Innovation Which Conquest Introduced Into The Fashion Of The

Times Altered Somewhat Its Appearance.

 

"The Head Or Lord Of The Manor Called Forth His Attendants To His

Hall. * * He Inquired Into The Breaches Of Custom,  And Of

Justice,  Which Were Committed Within The Precincts Of His

Territory,  And With His Followers,  Who Sat With Him As Judges,  He

Determined In All Matters Of Debt,  And Of Trespass To A Certain

Amount. He Possessed A Similar Jurisdiction With The Chieftain In

Germany,  And His Tenants Enjoyed An Equal Authority With The

German Retainers.

 

"But A Mode Of Administration Which Intrusted So Much Power To

The Great Could Not Long Be Exercised Without Blame Or Injustice.

The German,  Guided By The Candor Of His Mind,  And Entering Into

All His Engagements With The Greatest Ardor,  Perceived Not,  At

First,  That The Chieftain To Whom He Submitted His Disputes Might

Be Swayed,  In The Judgments He Pronounced,  By Partiality,

Prejudice,  Or Interest; And That The Influence He Maintained With

His Followers Was Too Strong To Be Restrained By Justice.

Experience Instructed Him Of His Error",  He Acknowledged The

Necessity Of Appealing From His Lord; And The Court Of The

Hundred Was Erected.

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 5 Pg 91

 

"This Establishment Was Formed Both In Germany And England,  By

The Inhabitants Of A Certain Division,  Who Extened Their

Jurisdiction Over The Territory They Occupied. [21] They Bound

Themselves Under A Penalty To Assemble At Stated Times; And

Having Elected The Wisest To Preside Over Them,  They Judged,  Not

Only All Civil And Criminal Matters,  But Of Those Also Which

Regarded Religion And The Priesthood. The Judicial Power Thus

Invested In The People Was Extensive; They Were Able To Preserve

Their Rights,  And Attended This Court In Arms.

 

[21] "It Was The Freemen In Germany,  And The Possessors Of Land

In England,  Who Were Suitors (Jurors) In The Hundred Court. These

Ranks Of Men Were The Same. The Alteration Which Had Happened In

Relation To Property Had Invested The German Freemen With Land Or

Territory."

 

"As The Communication,  However,  And Intercourse,  Of The

Individuals Of A German Community Began To Be Wider,  And More

General,  As Their Dealings Enlarged,  And As Disputes Arose Among

The Members Of Different Hundreds,  The Insufficiency Of These

Courts For The Preservation Of Order Was Gradually Perceived. The

Shyre Mote,  Therefore,  Or County Court,  Was Instituted; And It

Formed The Chief Source Of Justice Both In Germany And England.

 

"The Powers,  Accordingly,  Which Had Been Enjoyed By The Court Of

The Hundred,  Were Considerably Impaired. It Decided No Longer

Concerning Capital Offences; It Decided Not Concerning Matters Of

Liberty,  And The Property Of Estates,  Or Of Slaves; Its

Judgments,  In Every Case,  Became Subject To Review; And It Lost

Entirely The Decision Of Causes,  When It Delayed Too Long To

Consider Them.

 

"Every Subject Of Claim Or Contention Was Brought,  In The First

Instance,  Or By Appeal,  To The County Court; And The Earl,  Or

Eorldorman,  Who Presided There,  Was Active To Put The Laws In

Execution. He Repressed The Disorders Which Fell Out Within The

Circuit Of His Authority; And The Least Remission In Hi Duty,  Or

The Least Fraud He Committed,  Was Complained Of And Punished. He

Was Elected From Among The Great,  And Was Above The Temptation

Of

A Bribe; But,  To Encourage His Activity,  He Was Presented With A

Share Of The Territory He Governed,  Or Was Entitled To A

Proportion Of The Fines And Profits Of Justice. Every Man,  In His

District,  Was Bound To Inform Him Concerning Criminals,  And To

Assist Him To Bring Them To Trial; And,  As In Rude And Violent

Times The Poor And Helpless Were Ready To Be Oppressed By The

Strong,  He Was Instructed Particularly To Defend Them.

 

"His Court Was Ambulatory,  And Assembled Only Twice A Year,

Unless The Distribution Of Justice Required That Its Meetings

Should Be Oftener. Every Freeholder In The County Was Obliged To

Attend It; And Should He Refuse This Service,  His Possessions

Were Seized,  And He Was Forced To Find Surety For His Appearance.

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 5 Pg 92

The Neighboring Earls Held Not Their Courts On The Same Day; And,

What Seems Very Singular,  No Judge Was Allowed,  After Meals,  To

Exercise His Office.

 

"The Druids Also,  Or Priests,  In Germany,  As We Had Formerly

Occasion To Remark,  And The Clergy In England,  Exercised A

Jurisdiction In The Hundred And County Courts. They Instructed

The People In Religious Duties,  And In Matters Regarding The

Priesthood; And The Princes,  Earls,  Or Eorldormen,  Related To

Them The Laws And Customs Of The Community. These Judges Were

Mutually A Check To Each Other; But It Was Expected That They

Should Agree In Their Judgments,  And Should Willingly Unite Their

Efforts For The Public Interest. [22]

 

"The Meeting (The County Court) Was Opened With A Discourse By

The Bishop,  Explaining,  Out Of The Scriptures And Ecclesiastical

Canons,  Their Several Duties As Good Christians And Members Of

The Church. After This,  The Alderman,  Or One Of His Assessors,

Made A Discourse On The Laws Of The Land,  And The Duties Of Good

Subjects And Good Citizens. When These Preliminaries Were Over,

They Proceede To Try And Determine,  First The Causes Of The

Church,  Next The Pleas Of The Crown,  And Last Of All The

Controversies Of Private Parties."   8 Henry's History Of Great

Britain,  348.

 

This View Is Corroborated By Tyrrell's Introduction To The

History Of England; P. 83-84,  And By Spence's Origin Of The Laws

And Political Institutions Of Modern Europe,  P. 447,  And The Note

On The Same Page. Also By A Law Of Canute To This Effect,  In

Every County Let There Be Twice A Year An Assembly,  Whereat The

Bishop And The Earl Shall Be Present,  The One To Instruct The

People In Divine,  The Other In Human,  Laws.   Wilkins,  P. 136.

 

"But The Prince Or Earl Performed Not,  At All Times,  In Person,

The Obligations Of His Office. The Enjoyment Of Ease And Of

Pleasure,  To Which In Germany He Had Delivered Himself Over,

When Disengaged From War,  And The Mean Idea He Conceived

Of The Drudgery Of Civil Affairs,  Made Him Often Delegate To An

Inferior Person The Distribution Of Justice In His District. The

Same Sentiments Were Experienced By The Saxon Nobility;

And The Service Which They Owed By Their Tenures,  And The High

Employments They Sustained,  Called Them Often From The

Management Of Their Counties. The Progress,  Too,  Of Commerce, 

Giving An Intricacy To Cases,  And Swelling The Civil Code,  Added

To The Difficulty Of Their Office,  And Made Them Averse To Its Duties.

Sheriffs,  Therefore,  Or Deputies,  Were Frequently Appointed To

Transact Their Business; And Though These Were At First Under

Some Subordination To The Earls,  They Grew At Length To Be

Entirely Independent Of Them. The Connection Of Jurisdiction And

Territory Ceasing To Prevail,  And The Civil Being Separated From

The Ecclesiastical Power,  They Became The Sole And Proper

Officers For The Direction Of Justice In The Counties.

 

"The Hundred,  However,  And County Courts Were Not Equal Of

Themselves For The Purposes Of Jurisdiction And Order. It Was

Necessary That A Court Should Be Erected,  Of Supreme Authority,

Where The Disputes Of The Great Should Be Decided,  Where The

Disagreeing Sentiments Of Judges Should Be Reconciled,  And Where

Protection Should Be Given To The People Against Their Fraud And

Injustice.

 

"The Princes Accordingly,  Or Chief Nobility,  In The German

Communities,  Assembled Together To Judge Of Such Matters. The

Saxon Nobles Continued This Prerogative; And The King,  Or,  In His

Absence,  The Chief Justiciary,  Watched Over Their Deliberations.

But It Was Not On Every Trivial Occasion That This Court

Interested Itself. In Smaller Concerns,  Justice Was Refused

During Three Sessions Of The Hundred,  And Claimed Without Effect,

At Four Courts Of The County,  Before There Could Lie An Appeal To

It.

 

"So Gradually Were These Arrangements Established,  And So

Naturally Did The Varying Circumstances In The Situation Of The

Germans And Anglo-Saxons Direct Those Successive Improvements

Which The Preservation Of Order,  And The Advantage Of Society,

Called Them To Adopt. The Admission Of The People Into The Courts

Of Justice Preserved,  Among The Former,  That Equality Of Ranks

For Which They Were Remarkable; And It Helped To Overturn,  Among

The Latter,  Those Envious Distinctions Which The Feudal System

Tended To Introduce,  And Prevented That Venality In Judges,  And

Those Arbitrary Proceedings,  Which The Growing Attachment To

Interest,  And The Influence Of The Crown,  Might Otherwise Have

Occasioned."   Stuart On The Constitution Of England,  P. 222 To

245.

 

"In The Anglo-Saxon Period,  Accordingly,  Twelve Only Were

Elected; And These,  Together With The Judge,  Or Presiding Officer

Of The District,  Being Sworn To Regard Justice,  And The Voice Of

Reason,  Or Conscience,  All Causes Were Submitted To Them." 

Ditto,  P. 260.

 

"Before The Orders Of Men Were Very Nicely Disinguished,  The

Jurors Were Elected From The Same Rank. When,  However,  A Regular

Subordination Of Orders Was Established,  And When A Knowledge Of

Property Had Inspired The Necessitous With Envy,  And The Rich

With Contempt,  Every Man Was Tried By His Equals. The Same Spirit

Of Liberty Which Gave Rise To This Regulation Attended Its Progress.

Nor Could Monarchs Assume A More Arbitrary Method Of Proceeding.

'I Will Not' (Said The Earl Of Cornwall To His  Sovereign)  'Render  Up 

My   Castles,   Nor   Depart  The  Kingdom,   But   By  Judgment Of  My

Peers.' Of  This Institution,   So Wisely  Calculated For  The Preservation 

Of Liberty,   All Our,  Historians Have Pronounced The Eulogium." --

Ditto,  P. 262-3.                                      

 

Blackstone Says:

 

"The Policy Of Our Ancient Constitution,  As Regulated And 

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 5 Pg 93

Established By The Great Alfred,  Was To Bring Justice Home To

Every Man's Door,  By Constituting As Many Courts Of Judicature

As There Are Manors And Towns In The Kingdom; Wherein Injuries

Were Redressed In An Easy And Expeditious Manner,  By The

Suffrage Of Neighbors And Friends.  These Little Courts,  However, 

Communicated With Others Of A Larger Jurisdiction,  And Those

With Others Of A Still Greater Power; Ascending Gradually From

The Lowest To The Supreme Courts,  Which Were Respectively

Constituted To Correct The Errors Of The Inferior Ones,  And To

Determine Such Causes As,  By Reason Of Their Weight And

Difficulty,  Demanded A More Solemn Discussion. The Course

Of Justice Flowing In Large Streams From The King,  As The

Fountain,  To His Superior Courts Of Record; And Being Then

Subdivided Into Smaller Channels,  Till The Whole And Every Part

Of The Kingdom Were Plentifully Watered And Refreshed. An

Institution That Seems Highly Agreeable To The Dictates Of

Natural Reason,  As Well As Of More Enlightened Policy.            

                                       

"These Inferior Courts,  At Least The Name And Form Of Them,  Still

Cntinue In Our Legal Constitution; But As The Superior Courts Of

Record Have,  In Practice,  Obtained A Concurrent Original

Jurisdiction,  And As There Is,  Besides,  A Power Of Removing

Plaints Or Actions Thither From All The Inferior Jurisdictions;

Upon These Accounts (Among Others) It Has Happened That These

Petty Tribunals Have Fallen Into Decay,  And Almost Into Oblivion;

Whether For The Better Or The Worse May Be Matter Of Some

Speculation,  When We Consider,  On The One Hand,  The Increase Of

Expense And Delay,  And,  On The Other,  The More Able And Impartial

Decisions That Follow From This Change Of Jurisdiction.          

                                                               

"The Order I Shall Observe In Discoursing On These Several

Courts,  Constituted For The Redress Of Civil Injuries,  (For With

Those Of A Jurisdiction Merely Criminal  I Shall Not At Present

Concern Myself,  [23]) Will Be By Beginning With The Lowest,  And

Those Whose Jurisdiction,  Though Public And Generally Dispersed

Through The Kingdom,  Is Yet (With Regard To Each Particular

Court) Confined To Very Narrow Limits; And So Ascending Gradually

To Those Of The Most Extensive And Transcendent Power." -- 3

Blackstone,  30 To 32.                                            

                                          

"The Court-Baron Is A Court Incident To Every Manor In The

Kingdom,  To Beholden By The Steward Within The Said Manor.  This

Court-Baron Is Of Two Natures; The One Is A Customary Court,  Of

Which We Formerly Spoke,  Appertaining Entirely To The

Copy-Holders,  In Which Their Estates Are Transferred By Surrender

And Admittance,  And Other Matters Transacted Relative To Their

Tenures Only. The Other,  Of Which We Now Speak,  Is A Court Of

Common Law,  And It Is A Court Of The Barons,  By Which Name The

Freeholders Were Sometimes Anciently Called; For That It Is Held

By The Freeholders Who Owe Suit And Service To Th Manor,  The

Steward Being Rather The Registrar Than The Judge.  These Courts,

Though In Their Nature Distinct,  Are Frequently Confounded

Together. The Court We Are Now Considering,  Viz.,  The Freeholders

Court,  Was Composed Of The Lord's Tenants,  Who Were The Pares 

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 5 Pg 94

(Equals) Of Each Other,  And Were Bound By Their Feudal Tenure To

Assist Their Lord In The Dispensation Of Domestic Justice. This

Was Formerly Held Every Three Weeks; And Its Most Important

Business Is To Determine,  By Writ Of Right,  All Controversies

Relating To The Right Of Lands Within The Manor. It May Also Hold

Plea Of Any Personal Actions,  Of Debt,  Trespass In The Case,  Or

The Like,  Where The Debt Or Damages Do Not Amount To Forty

Shillings; Which Is The Same Sum,  Or Three Marks,  That Bounded

The Jurisdiction Of The Ancient Gothic Courts In Their Lowest

Instance,  Or Fierding Courts,  So Called Because Four Were

Institute Within Every Superior District Or Hundred."   8

Blackstone,  38,  34.

 

"A Hundred Court Is Only A Larger Court-Baron,  Being Held For All

The Inhabitants Of A Particular Hundred,  Instead Of A Manor. The

Free Suitors Are Here Also The Judges,  And The Steward The

Registrar,  As In The Case Of A Court-Baron. It Is Likewise No

Court Of Record,  Resembling The Former At All Points,  Except That

In Point Of Territory It Is Of Greater Jurisdiction. This Is Said

By Sir Edward Coke To Have Been Derived Out Of The County Court

For The Ease Of The People,  That They Might Have Justice Done To

Them At Their Own Doors,  Without Any Charge Or Loss Of Time; But

Its Institution Was Probably Coeval With That Of Hundreds

Themselves,  Which Were Formerly Observed To Have Been

Introduced,  Though Not Invented,  By Alfred,  Being Derived From

The Polity Of The Ancient Germans. The Centeni,  We May Remember, 

Were The Principal Inhabitants Of A District Composed Of Different

Villages,  Oriinally In Number A Hundred,  But Afterward Only Called

By That Name,  And Who Probably Gave The Same Denomination

To The District Out Of Which They Were Chosen. Caesar Speaks

Positively Of The Judicial Power Exercised In Their Hundred

Courts And Courts-Baron. 'Princeps Regiorum Atque Pagorum' (Which

We May Fairly Construe The Lords Of Hundreds And Manors) 'Inter

Suos Jus Dicunt,  Controversias Que Minuunt.' (The Chiefs Of The

Country And The Villages Declare The Law Among Them,  And Abate

Controversies.) And Tacitus,  Who Had Examined Their Constitution

Still More Attentively,  Informs Us Not Only Of The Authority Of

The Lords,  But That Of The Centeni,  The Hundreders,  Or Jury,  Who

Were Taken Out Of The Common Freeholders,  And Had Themselves A

Share In The Determination. ' Eliguntur In Conciliis Et

Principes,  Qui Jura Per Pagos Vicosque Reddunt,  Centenii

Singulis,  Ex Plebe Comites Comcilium Simul Et Auctoritas Adsunt.

(The Princes Are Chosen In The Assemblies,  Who Administer The

Laws Throughout The Towns And Villages,  And With Each One Are

Associated An Hundred Companions,  Taken From The People,  For

Purposes Both Of Counsel And Authority.) This Hundred Court Was

Denominated Haereda In The Gothic Constitution. But This Court,

As Causes Are Equally Liable To Removal From Hence As From The

Common Court-Baron,  And By The Same Writs,  And May Also Be

Reviewed By Writ Of False Judgment,  Is Therefore Fallen Into

Equal Disuse With Regard To The Trial Of Actions." 8 Blackstone,  34,

85.

 

"The County Court Is A Court Incident To The Jurisdiction Of The

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 5 Pg 95

Sheriff. It Is Not A Court Of Record,  But May Hold Pleas Of Debt,

Or Damages,  Under The Value Of Forty Shillings; Over Some Of

Which Causes These Inferior Courts Have,  By The Express Words Of

The Statute Of Gloucester,  (6 Edward I.,  Eh. 8,) A Jurisdicton

Totally Exclusive Of The King's Superior Courts. *  * The County

Court May Also Hold Plea Of Many Real Actions,  And Of All

Personal Actions To Any Amount,  By Virtue Of A Special Writ,

Called A Justicies,  Which Is A Writ Empowering The Sheriff,  For

The Sake Of Despatch,  To Do The Samee Justice In His County Court

As Might Otherwise Be Had At Westminster. The Freeholders Of The

County Court Are The Real Judges In This Court,  And The Sheriff

Is The Ministerial Ofhcer. * * In Modern Times,  As Proceedings

Are Removable From Hence Into The King's Superior Courts,  By Writ

Of Pone Or Recordari,  In The Same Manner As From Hundred Courts

And Courts-Baron,  And As The Same Writ Of False Judgment May Be

Had In Nature Of A Writ Of Error,  This Has Occasioned The Same

Disuse Of Bringing Actions Therein."   3 Blackstone,  36,  37.

 

"Upon The Whole,  We Cannot But Admire The Wise Economy And

Admirable Provision Of Our Ancestors In Settling The Distribution

Of Justice In A Method So Well Calculated For Cheapness,

Expedition,  And Ease. By The Constitution Which They Established,

All Trivial Debts,  And Injuries Of Small Consequence,  Were To Be

Recovered Or Redressed In Every Man's Own County,  Hundred,  Or

Perhaps Parish."   3 Blackstone,  59.

 

[22] It Would Be Wholly Erroneous,  I Think,  To Infer From This

Statement Of Stuart,  That Either The "Priests,  Princes,  Earls,  Or

Eorldormen" Exercised Any Authority Over The Jury In The Trial Of

Causes,  In The Way Of Dictating The Law To Them. Henry's Account

Of This Matter Doubtless Gives A Much More Accurate

Representation Of The Truth. He Says That Anciently

 

[23] There Was No Distinction Between The Civil And Criminal

Courts,  As To The Rights Or Powers Of Juries.                     

 

[24] This Quaint And Curious Book; (Smith's Commonwealth

Of England) Describes The Minutiae Of Trials,  Giving In Detail

The Mode Of Impaneling The Jury And Then The Conduct Of The

 Lawyers,  Witnesses,  And Court I Give The Following Extracts, 

Tending To Show That The Judges Impose No Law Upon The Juries, 

In Either Civil Or Criminal Cases But Only Require Them To

Determine The Causes According To Their Consciences.

 

In Civil Causes He Says:

 

"When It Is Thought That It Is Enough Pleaded Before Them, 

And The Witnesses Have Said What They Can,  One Of The Judges, 

With A Brief And Pithy Recapitulation,  Reciteth To The Twelve

In Sum The Arguments Of The Sergeants Of Either Side,  That

Which The Witnesses Have Declared,  And The Chief Points Of The

Evidence Showed In Writing,  And Once Again Putteth Them In

Mind Of The Issue,  And Sometime Giveth It Them In Writing,

Delivering To Them The Evidence Which Is Showed On Either Part,  

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 5 Pg 96

If Any Be,  (Evidence Here Is Called Writings Of Contracts,

Authentical After The Manner Of England,  That Is To Say,  Written, 

Sealed,  And Delivered,) And Biddeth Them Go Together."   P. 74.

 

This Is The Whole Account Given Of The Charge To The Jury.

 

In Criminal Eases,  After The Witnesses Have Been Heard,  And

The Prisoner Has Said What He Pleases In His Defence,  The Book

Proceeds:

 

"When The Judge Hath Heard Them Say Enough,  He Asketh If

They Can Say Any More. If They Say No,  Then He Turneth His Speech

To The Inquest. 'Good Men,  (Saith He,) Ye Of The Inquest,  Ye Have

Heard What These Men Say Against The Prisoner. You Have Also

Heard What The Prisoner Can Say For Himself. Have An Eye To

Your Oath,  And To Your Duty,  And Do That Which God Shall Put

In Your Minds To The Discharge Of Your Consciences,  And Mark

Well What Is Said.' "  P. 92.

 

This Is The Whole Account Given Of The Charge In A Criminal Ease.

 

The Following Statement Goes To Confirm The Same Idea,  That

Jurors In England Have Formerly Understood It To Be Their Right And

Duty To Judge Only According To Their Consciences,  And Not To

Submit To Any Dictation From The Court,  Either As To Law Or Fact.

 

"If Having Pregnant Evidence,  Nevertheless,  The Twelve Do

Acquit The Malefactor Which They Will Do Sometime,  Especially If

They Perceive Either One Of The Justices Or Of The Judges,  Or Some

Other Man,  To Pursue Too Much And Too Maliciously The Death Of The

Prisoner,  * * The Prisoner Escapeth; But The Twelve (Are) Not Only

Rebuked By The Judges,  But Also Threatened Of Punishment; And

Many Times Commanded To Appear In The Star-Chamber,  Or Before The

Privy Council For The Matter. But This Threatening Chanceth Oftener

Than The Execution Thereof; And The Twelve Answer With Most

Gentle Words,  They Did It According To Their Consciences,  And

Pray The Judges To Be Good Unto Them,  They Did As They Thought

Right,  And As They Accorded All,  And So It Passeth Away For The

Most Part."   P. 100.

 

The Account Given Of The Trial Of A Peer Of  The Realm Corroborates

The Same Point:

 

"If Any Duke,  Marquis,  Or Any Other Of The Degrees Of A Baron, 

Or Above,  Lord Of The Parliament,  Be Appeached Of Treason,  Or Any

Other Capital Crime,  He Is Judged By His Peers And Equals; That, 

Is,  The Yeomanry Doth Not Go Upon Him,  But An Inquest Of The Lords

Of Parliament,  And They Give Their Voice Not One For All,  But Each

Severally As They Do In Parliament Being (Beginning) At The

Youngest Lord. And For Judge One Lord Sitteth,  Who Is Constable Of

England For That Day. The Judgment Once Given,  He Breaketh His

Staff,  And Abdicateth His Office. In The Rest There Is No Difference

From That Above Written," (That Is,  In The Case Of A Freeman.) P. 98.

 

Chapter 3 (Additional Proofs Of The Rights And Duties Of Jurors) Section 5 Pg 97

[25] "The Present  Form Of The Jurors' Oath Is  That They Shall 'Give A

True Verdict According To The Evidence.' At What Time This Form Was

Introduced Is Uncertain; But For Several Centuries After The Conquest, 

The Jurors,  Both In Civil And Criminal Cases,   Were Sworn Merely To

Speak  The Truth. (Glanville,  Lib. 2,  Cap. 17; Bracton,  Lib. 3,  Cap. 22; Lib. 4, 

P. 287,  291; Britton,  P. 135.) Hence Their Decision Was Accurately

Termed Veredictum,  Or Verdict,  That Is,  ' A Thing Truly Said'; Whereas

The Phrase 'True Verdict' In The Modern Oath Is Not An Accurate

Expression."   Political Dictionary,  Word Jury.

 

[26] Of Course,  There Can Be No Legal Trial By Jury,  In Either Civil Or

Criminal Cases,  Where The Jury Are Sworn To Try The Cases "According

To Law."

 

[27] Coke,  As Late As 1588,  Admits That Amercements Must Be Fixed By The

Peers (8 Coke's Rep. 88,  2 Inst. 27); But He Attempts,  Wholly Without

Success,  As It Seems To Me,  To Show A Difference Between Fines And

Amercements. The Statutes Are Very Numerous,  Running Through The

Three Or Four Hundred Years Immediately Succeeding Magna Carta,

In Which Fines,  Ransoms,  And Amercements Are Spoken Of As If They

Were The Common Punishments Of Offences,  And As If They All Meant The

Same Thing. If,  However,  Any Technical Difference Could Be Made

Out Between Them,  There Is Clearly None In Principle; And The Word

Amercement,  As Used In Magna Carta,  Must Be Taken In Its Most

Comprehensive Sense.

 

[28] "Common Right" Was The Common Law. 1 Coke's

Inst. 142 A. 2 Do. 55,  6.

 

[29] The Oath Of The Justices Is In These Words:"Ye Shall

Swear,  That Well And Lawfully Ye Shall Serve Our Lord The

King And His People,  In The Office Of Justice,  And That

Lawfully Ye Shall Counsel The King In His Business,  And That

Ye Shall Not Counsel Nor Assent To Anything Which May

Turn Him In Damage Or Disherison In Any Manner,  Way,  Or

Color. And That Ye Shall Not Know The Damage Or

Disherison Of Him,  Whereof Ye Shall Not Cause Him To Be

Warned By Yourself,  Or By Other; And That Ye Shall Do

Equal Law And Execution Of Right To All His Subjects,  Rich

And Poor,  Without Having Regard To Any Person. And That

Ye Take Not By Yourself,  Or By Other,  Privily Nor Apertly, 

Gift Nor Reward Of Gold Nor Silver,  Nor Of Any Other

Thing That May Turn To Your Profit,  Unless It Be Meat Or

Drink,  And That Of Small Value,  Of Any Man That Shall

Have Any Plea Or Process Hanging Before You,  As Long

As The Same Process Shall Be So Hanging,  Nor After For

The Same Cause. And That Ye Take No Fee,  As Long As Ye

Shall Be Justice,  Nor Robe Of Any Man Great Or Small,  But

Of The King Himself. And That Ye Give None Advice Or

Counsel To No Man Great Or Small,  In No Case Where The King

Is Party. And In Case That Any,  Of What Estate Or Condition

They Be,  Come Before You In Your Sessions With Force

And Arms,  Or Otherwise Against The Peace,  Or Against The

Form Of The Statute Thereof Made,  To Disturb Execution

Of The Common Law," [Mark The Term,  "Common Law,")

"Or To Menace The People That They May Not Pursue The

Law,  That Ye Shalt Cause Their Bodies To Be Arrested And

Put In  Prison; And In Case They Be Such That Ye Cannot

Arrest Them,  That Ye Certify The King Of Their Names,  And

Of Their Misprision,  Hastily,  So That He May Thereof

Ordain A Convenable Remedy. And That Ye By Yourself,

Nor By Other,  Privily Nor Apertly,  Maintain Any Plea Or

Quarrel Hanging In The King's Court,  Or Elsewhere In The

Country. And That Ye Deny No Man Common Right By

The King's Letters,  Nor None Other Man's,  Nor For None

Other Cause,  And In Case Any Letters Come To You

Contrary To The Law,'" (That Is,  The "Common Law

" Before Mentioned,) "That Ye Do Nothing By Such

Letters,  But Certify The King Thereof,  And Proceed To

Execute The Law," (The "Common Law" Before Mentioned,)

"Notwithstanding The Same Letters. And That Ye Shall

Do And Procure The Profit Of The King And Of His Crown, 

With All Things Where Ye May Reasonably Do The

Same.  And In Case Ye Be From Henceforth Found In

Default In Any Of The Points Aforesaid,  Ye Shall Be At The

King's Will Of Body,  Lands,  And Goods,  Thereof To Be

Done As Shall Please Him,  As God You Help And All

Saints."   18 Edward Iii.,  St. 4. (1344.)

 

[30] That The Terms "Law" And "Right," As Used

In This Statute,  Mean The Common Law,  Is Shown

By The Preamble,  Which Declares The Motive Of

The Statute To Be That "The Law Of The Land, 

(The Common Law,) Which We (The King) By Our

Oath Are Bound To Maintain," May Be The Better

Kept,  &.

 

[31] The Following Is A Copy Of The Original:

 

"Forma Juramenti Regis Anglicae In Coronacione Sua:

 

(Archiepiscopus Cantuariae,  Ad Quo De Jure Et Consuetudine

Ecclesiae Cantuariae,  Antiqua Et Approbata,  Pertinet

Reges Angliae Inungere Et Coronare,  Die Coronacionis

Regis,  Anteque Rex Coronetur,  Faciet Regi Interrogationes

Subscriptas.)

 

Si Leges Et Consuetudines Ab Antiquis Justis Et Deo

Devotis Regibus Plebi Anglicano Concessas,  Cum

Sacramenti Confirmacione Eidem Plebi Concedere

Et Servare (Volueris:) Et Praesertim Leges Et

Consuetudines Et Libertates A Glorioso Rege Edwardo

Clero Populoque Concessas ?

 

(Et Respondeat Rex,) Concedo Et Servare Volo,  Et

Sacramento Confirmare.

 

Servabis Ecclesiae Dei,  Cleroque,  Et Populo,  Pacem

Ex Integro Et Concordiam In Deo Secundum Vires Tuas ?

 

(Et Respondeat Rex,) Servabo.

 

Facies Fieri In Omnibus Judieiis Tuis Equam Et Rectam

Justioiam,  Et Discreeionem,  In Misericordia Et Veritate, 

Secundum Vires  Tuas?

 

(Et Respondeat Rex,) Faciam.

 

Concedis Justas,  Leges Et Consuetudines Esse Tenendas, 

Et Promittis Per Te Eas Esse Protegendas,  Et Ad Honorem

Dei Corroborandas,  Quas Vulgus Elegit,  Secundum Vires

Tuas ?

 

(Et Respondeat Rex,) Concedo Et Promitto."

 

[32] It Would Appear,  From The Text,  That The Charter Of Liberties

And The Charter Of The Forest Were Sometimes Called "Laws Of The

Land."

 

[33] As The Ancient Coronation Oath,  Given In The Text,

 Has Come Down From The Saxontimes,  The Following

Remarks Of Palgrave Will Be Pertinent,  In Connection

With The Oath,  As Illustrating The Fact That,  In Those Times,

No Special Authority Attached To The Laws Of The King:

 

"The Imperial Witenagemot Was Not A Legislative

Assembly,  In The Strict Sense Of The Term,  For The Whole

Anglo-Saxon Empire. Promulgating His Edicts Amidst

His Peers And Prelates,  The King Uses The Language Of

Command; But The Theoretical Prerogative Was Modified

By Usage,  And The Practice Of The Constitution Required

That The Law Should Be Accepted By The Legislatures

(Courts) Of The Several Kingdoms. * * The 'Basileus'

Speaks In The Tone Of Prerogative: Edgar Does Not

Merely Recommend,  He Commands That The Law Shall Be

Adopted By All The People,  Whether English,   Danes,  Or

Britons,  In Every Part Of His Empire. Let This Statute Be

Observed,  He Continues,  By Earl Oslac,  And All The Host

Who Dwell Under His Government,  And Let It Be Transmitted

By Writ To The Ealdormen Of The Other Subordinate States.

And Yet,  In Defiance Of This Positive Iujunction,  The

Laws Of Edgar Were Not Accepted In Mercia Until The Reign

Of Canute The Dane. It Might Be Said That The Course

So Adopted May Have Been An Exception To The General Rule;

But In The Scanty And Imperfect Annals Of Anglo-Saxon

Legislation,  We Shall Be Able To Find So Many Examples

Of Similar Proceedings,  That This Mode Of Enactment

Must Be Considered As Dictated By The Constitution Of

The Empire. Edward Was The Supreme Lord Of The

Northumbrians,  But More Than A Century Elapsed Before

They Obeyed His Decrees.  The Laws Of The Glorious

Athelstane Had No Effect In Kent,  (County,) The

Dependent Appanage Of His Crown,  Until Sanctioned

By The Witan Of The Shire (County Court). And The Power Of

Canute Himself,  The 'King Of All England,' Does Not

Seem To Have Compelled The Northumbrians To

Receive His Code,  Until The Reign Of The Confessor, 

When Such Acceptance Became A Part Of The Compact

Upon The Accession Of A New Earl.

 

Legislation Constituted But A Small Portion  Of The

Ordinary Business Transacted By The Imperial

Witenagemot. The Wisdom Of The Assembly Was

Shown In Avoiding Unnecessary Change. Consisting

Principally Of Traditionary Usages And Ancestorial Customs,

The Law Was Upheld By Opinion. The People Considered

Their Jurisprudence As A Part Of Their  Inheritance.

Their Privileges And Their Duties Were Closely Conjoined;

Most Frequently,  The Statutes Themselves Were Only

Affirmances Of Ancient Customs,  Or Declaratory Enactments.

 

In The Anglo-Saxon Commonwealth,  Therefore,  The

Legislative Functions Of The Witenagemot Were Of Far

Less Importance Than The Other Branches Of Its Authority.

* * The Members Of The Witenagemot Were The ' Pares Curiae '

(Peers Of Court) Of The Kingdom. How Far,  On These Occasions, 

Their Opinion Or Their Equity Controlled The Power Of The Crown,

Cannot Be Ascertained. But The Form Of Inserting Their Names

In The 'Testing Clause' Was Retained Under The

Anglo-Norman Reigns; And The Sovereign,  Who Submitted

His Charter To The Judgment Of The Proceres,  Professed To

Be Guided By The Opinion Which They Gave. As The 'Pares'

Of The Empire,  The Witenagemot Decided' The Disputes

Between The Great Vassals Of The Crown. * * The Jurisdiction

Exercised In The Parliament Of Edward I.,  When The Barony

Of A Lord-Marcher Became The Subject Of Litigation,  Is

Entirely Analogous To The Proceedings Thus Adopted By The Great

Council Of Edward,  The Son Of Alfred,  The Anglo-Saxon King.

 

In This Assembly,  The King,  The Prelates,  The Dukes,  The

Ealdormen,  And The Optimates Passed Judgment Upon All Great

Offenders.* *

 

The Sovereign Could Not Compel The Obedience Of The Different

Nations Composing The Anglo-Saxon Empire. Hence,  It

Became More Necessary For Him To Conciliate Their

Opinions,  If He Solicited Any Service From A Vassal Prince Or

A Vassal State Beyond The Ordinary Terms Of The Compact;

Still More So,  When He Needed The Support Of A Free Burgh Or

City. And We May View The Assembly (The Witenagemot)

As Partaking Of The Character Of A Political Congress,  In

Which The Liegemen Of The Crown,  Or The Communities

Protected By The ' Basileus,' (Sovereign,) Were Asked Or

Persuaded To Relieve The Exigences Of The State,  Or To Consider

Those Measures Which Might Be Required For The Common Weal.

The Sovereign Was Compelled To Parley With His Dependents,

 

It May Be Doubted Whether Any One Member Of The Empire Had

Power To Legislate For Any Other Member. The Regulus Of Cumbria

Was Unaffected By The Vote Of The Earl Of East Angliae,  If

He Chose To Stand Out Against It. These Dignitaries

Constituted A Congress,  In Which The Sovereign Could

Treat More Conveniently And Effectually With His Vassals

Than By Separate Negotiations. * * But The Determinations

Of The Witan Bound Those Only Who Were Present,  Or Who

Concurred In The Proposition; And A Vassal Denying His Assent

To The Grant,  Might Assert That The Engagement Which He

Had Contracted With His Superior Did Not Involve Any

Pecuniary Subsidy,  But Only Rendered Him Liable To Perform

Service In The Field."   1 Palgrave's Rise And Progress Of The

English Commonwealth,  637 To 642.

 

 

Chapter 4 (The Rights And Duties Of Juries In Civil Suits) Pg 98

The Evidence Already Given In The Preceding Chapters Proves That

The Rights And Duties Of Jurors,  In Civil Suits,  Were Anciently

The Same As In Criminal Ones; That The Laws Of The King Were Of

No Obligation Upon The Consciences Of The Jurors,  Any Further

Than The Laws Were Seen By Them To Be Just; That Very Few Laws

Were Enacted Applicable To Civil Suits; That When A New Law Was

Enacted,  The Nature Of It Could Have Been Known To The Jurors

Only By Report,  And Was Very Likely Not To Be Known To Them At

All; That Nearly All The Law Involved In Civil Suits Was

Unwritten;  That There Was Usually  No One In Attendance Upon

Juries Who Could Possibly Enlighten Them,  Unless It Were

Sheriffs,  Stewards,  And Bailiffs,  Who Were Unquestionably Too

Ignorant And Untrustworthy To Instruct Them Authoritatively; That

The Jurors Must Therefore Necessarily Have Judged For Themselves

Of The Whole Case; And That,  As A General Rule,  They Could Judge

Of It By No Law But The Law Of Nature,  Or The. Principles Of

Justice As They Existed In Their Own Minds.

 

The Ancient Oath Of Jurors In Civil Suits,  Viz.,  That "They Would

Make Known The Truth According To Their Consciences," Implies

That The Jurors Were Above The Authority Of All Legislation. The

Modern Oath,  In England,  Viz.,  That They "Will Well And Truly Try

The Issue Between The Parties,  And A True Verdict Give,  According

To The Evidence," Implies The Same Thing. If The Laws Of The King

Had Been Binding Upon A Jury,  They Would Have Been Sworn To Try

The Cases According To Law,  Or According To The Laws.

 

The Ancient Writs,  In Civil Suits,  As Given In Glanville,  (Within

The Half Century Before Magna Carta,) To Wit,  "Summon Twelve Free

And Legal Men,  (Or Sometimes Twelve Knights,) To Be In Court,

Prepared Upon Their Oaths To Declare Whether A Or B Have The

Greater Right To The Land In Question," Indicate That The Jurors

Judged Of The Whole Matter On Their Consciences Only.

 

The Language Of Magna Carta,  Already Discussed,  Establishes

The Same Point; For,  Although Some Of The Words,  Such As

"Outlawed," And "Exiled," Would Apply Only To Criminal Cases,

Nearly The Whole Chapter Applies As Well To Civil As To Criminal

Suits. For Example,  How Could The Payment Of A Debt Ever Be

Enforced Against An Unwilling Debtor,  If He Could Neither Be

"Arrested,  Imprisoned,  Nor Deprived Of His Freehold," And If The

King Could Neither "Proceed Against Him,  Nor Send Any One Against

Him,  By Force Or Arms" ?  Yet Magna Carta As Much Forbids That

Any Of These Things Shall Be Done Against A Debtor,  As Against A

Criminal,  Except According To,  Or In Execution Of,  " A Judgment

Of His Peers,  Or The Law Of The Land,"   A Provision Which,  It

Has Been Shown,  Gave The Jury The Free And Absolute Right To Give

Or Withhold "Judgment" According To Their Consciences,

Irrespective Of All Legislation.

 

The Following Provisions,  In The Magna Carta Of John,  Illustrate

The Custom Of Referring The Most Important Matters Of A Civil

Nature,  Even Where The King Was A Party,  To The Determination Of

The Peers,  Or Of Twelve Men,  Acting By No Rules But Their Own

Consciences. These Examples At Least Show That There Is Nothing

Improbable Or Unnatural In The Idea That Juries Should Try All

Civil Suits According To Their Own Judgments,  Independently Of

All Laws Of The King.

 

Chap. 65. "If We Have Disseized Or Dispossessed The Welsh Of Any

Lands,  Liberties,  Or Other Things,  Without The Legal Judgment Of

Their Peers,  They Shall Be Immediately Restored To Them. And If

Any Dispute Arises Upon This Head,  The Matter Shall Be Determined

In The Marches,  [1] By The Judgment Of Their Peers," &C;.

 

Chap. 68. " We Shall Treat With Alexander,  King Of Scots,

Concerning The Restoring Of His Sisters,  And Hostages,  And Rights

And Liberties,  In The Same Form And Manner As We Shall Do To The

Rest Of Our Barons Of England; Unless By The Engagements,  Which

His Father William,  Late King Of Scots,  Hath Entered Into With

Us,  It Ought To Be Otherwise; And This Shall Be Left To The

Determination Of His Peers In Our Court."

 

Chap. 56. "All Evil Customs Concerning Forests,  Warrens,  And

Foresters,  Warreners,  Sheriffs,  And Their Officers,  Rivers And

Their Keepers,  Shall Forthwith Be Inquired Into In Each County,

By Twelve Knights Of The Same Shire,  Chosen By The Most

Creditable Persons In The Same County,  And Upon Oath; And Within

Forty Days After The Said Inquest,  Be Utterly Abolished,  So As

Never To Be Restored."

 

There Is Substantially The Same Reason Why A Jury Ought To Judge

Of The Justice Of Laws,  And Hold All Unjust Laws Invalid,  In

Civil Suits,  As In Criminal Ones. That Reason Is The Necessity Of

Guarding Against The Tyranny Of The Government. Nearly The Same

Oppressions Can Be Practised In Civil Suits As In Criminal Ones.

For Example,  Individuals May Be Deprived,  Of Their Liberty,  And

Robbed Of Their Property,  By Judgments Rendered In Civil Suits,

As Well As In Criminal Ones. If The Laws Of The King Were

Imperative Upon A Jury In Civil Suits,  The King Might Enact Laws

Giving One Man's Property To Another,  Or Confiscating It To The

King Himself,  And Authorizing Civil Suits To Obtain Possession Of

It. Thus A Man Might Be Robbed Of His Property At The Arbitrary

Pleasure Of The King. In Fact,  All The Property Of The Kingdom

Would Be Placed,  At The Arbitrary Disposal Of The King,  Through

The Judgments Of Juries In Civil Suits,  If The Laws Of The King

Were Imperative Upon A Jury In Such Suits. [2]

 

Furthemore,  It Would Be Absurd And Inconsistent To Make

A Jury Paramount To Legislation In Criminal Suits,  And

Subordinate To It In Civil Suits; Because An Individual,  By

Resisting The Execution Of A Civil Judgment,  Founded Upon An

Unjust Law,  Could Give Rise To A Criminal Suit,  In Which The Jury

Would Be Bound To Hold The Same Law Invalid. So That,  If An

Unjust Law Were Binding Upon A Jury In Civil Suits,  A Defendant,

By Resisting The Execution Of The Judgment,  Could,  In Effect,

Convert The Civil Action Into A Criminal One,  In Which The Jury

Would Be Paramount To The Same Legislation,  To Which,  In The

Civil Suit,  They Were Subordinate. In Other Words,  In The

Criminal Suit,  The Jury Would Be Obliged To Justify The Defendant

In Resisting A Law,  Which,  In The Civil Suit,  They Had Said He

Was Bound To Submit To.

 

To Make This Point Plain To The Most Common Mind   Suppose A

Law Be Enacted That The Property Of A Shall Be Given To B. B

Brings A Civil Action To Obtain Possession Of It. If The Jury,  In This

Civil Suit,  Are Bound To Hold The Law Obligatory,  They Render A

Judgment In Favor Of B,  That He Be Put In Possession Of The

Property; Thereby Declaring That A Is Bound To Submit To A Law

Depriving Him Of His Property. But When The Execution Of That

Judgment Comes To Be Attempted   That Is,  When The Sheriff Comes

To Take The Property For The Purpose Of Delivering It To B   A

Acting,  As He Has A Natural Right To Do,  In Defence Of His

Property,  Resists And Kills The Sheriff. He Is Thereupon Indicted

For Murder. On This Trial His Plea Is,  That In Killing The

Sheriff,  He Was Simply Exercising His Natural Right Of Defending

His Property Against An Unjust Law. The Jury,  Not Being Bound,  In

A Criminal Case,  By The Authority Of An Unjust Law,  Judge The Act

On Its Merits,  And Acquit The Defendant   Thus Declaring That He

Was Not Bound To Submit To The Same Law Which The Jury,  In The

Civil Suit,  Had,  By Their Judgment,  Declared That He Was Bound To

Submit To. Here Is A Contradiction Between The Two Judgments. In

The Civil Suit,  The Law Is Declared To Be Obligatory Upon A; In

The Criminal Suit,  The Same Law Is Declared To Be Of No

Obligation.

 

It Would Be A Solecism And Absurdity In Government To Allow

Such Consequences As These. Besides,  It Would Be Practically

Impossible To Maintain Government On Such Principles; For No

Government Could Enforce Its Civil Judgments,  Unless It Could

Support Them By Criminal Ones,  In Case Of Resistance. A Jury Must

Therefore Be Paramount To Legislation In Both Civil And Criminal

Cases,  Or In Neither. If They Are Paramount In Neither,  They Are

No Protection To Liberty. If They Are Paramount In Both,  Then All

Legislation Goes Only For What It May Chance To Be Worth In The

Estimation Of A Jury.

 

Another Reason Why Magna Carta Makes The Discretion And

Consciences Of Juries Paramount To All Legislation In Civilsuits,  Is,

That If Legislation Were Binding Upon A Jury,  The Jurors  (By Reason

Of Their Being Unable To Read,  As Jurors In Those Days Were,  And

Also By Reason Of Many Of The Statutes Being Unwritten,  Or At Least

Not So Many Copies Written As That Juries Could Be Supplied With

Them)   Would Have Been Necessitated At Least In Those Courts In

Which The King's Justices Sat   To Take The Word Of Those Justices

As To What The Laws Of The King Really Were. In Other Words,  They

Would Have Been Necessitated To Take The Law From The Court,  As

Jurors Do Now.

 

Now There Were Two Reasons Why,  As We May Rationally Suppose,

The People Did Not Wish Juries To Take Their Law From The King's

Judges. One Was,  That,  At That Day,  The People Probably Had Sense

Enough To See,  (What We,  At This Day,  Have Not Sense Enough To

See,  Although We Have The Evidence Of It Every Day Before Our

Eyes,) That Those Judges,  Being Dependent Upon The Legislative

Power,  (The King,) Being Appointed By It,  Paid By It,  And

Removable By It At Pleasure,  Would Be Mere Tools Of That Power,

And Would Hold All Its Legislation Obligatory,  Whether It Were

Just Or Unjust. This Was One Reason,  Doubtless,  Why Magna Carta

Made Juries,  In Civil Suits,  Paramount To All Instructions Of The

King's Judges. The Reason Was Precisely The Same As That For

Making Them Paramount To All Instructions Of Judges In Criminal

Suits,  Viz.,  That The People Did Not Choose To Subject Their

Rights Of Property,  And All Other Rights Involved In Civil Suits,

To The Operation Of Such Laws As The King Might Please To Enact.

It Was Seen That To Allow The King's Judges To Dictate The Law To

The Jury Would Be Equivalent To Making The Legislation Of The

King Imperative Upon The Jury.

 

Another Reason Why The People Did Not Wish Juries,  In Civil

Suits,  To Take Their Law From The King's Judges,  Doubtless Was,

That,  Knowing The Dependence Of The Judges Upon The King,  And

Knowing That The King Would,  Of Course,  Tolerate No Judges Who

Were Not Subservient To His Will,  They Necessarily Inferred; That

The King's Judges Would Be As Corrupt,  In The Administration Of

Justice,  As Was The King Himself,  Or As He Wished Them To Be. And

How Corrupt That Was,  May Be Inferred From The Following

Historical Facts.

 

Hume Says:

 

"It Appears That The Ancient Kings Of England Put Themselves

Entirely Upon The Footing Of The Barbarous Eastern Princes,  Whom

No Man Must Approach Without A Present,  Who Sell All Their Good

Offices,  And Who Intrude Themselves Into Every Business That They

May Have A Pretence For Extorting Money. Even Justice Was

Avowedly Bought And Sold; The King's Court Itself,  Though The

Supreme Judicature Of The Kingdom,  Was Open To None That Brought

Not Presents To The King; The Bribes Given For Expedition,  Delay,

Suspension,  And Doubtless For The Perversion Of Justice,  Were

Entered In The Public Registers Of The Royal Revenue,  And Remain

As Monuments Of The Perpetual Iniquity And Tyranny Of The Times.

The Barons Of The Exchequer,  For Instance,  The First Nobility Of

The Kingdom,  Were Not Ashamed To Insert,  As An Article In Their

Records,  That The County Of Norfolk Paid A Sum That They Might Be

Fairly Dealt With; The Borough Of Yarmouth,  That The King's

Charters,  Which They Have For Their Liberties,  Might Not Be

Violated; Richard,  Son Of Gilbert,  For The King's Helping Him To

Recover His Debt From The Jews; * * Serio,  Son Of Terlavaston,

That He Might Be Permitted To Make His Defence,  In Case He Were

Accused Of A Certain Homicide; Walter De Burton,  For Free Law,  If

Accused Of Wounding Another; Robert De Essart,  For Having An

Inquest To Find Whether Roger,  The Butcher,  And Wace And

Humphrey,  Accused Him Of Robbery And Theft Out Of Envy And

Ill-Will,  Or Not; William Buhurst,  For Having An Inquest To Find

Whether He Were Accused Of The Death Of One Godwin,  Out Of

Ill-Will,  Or For Just Cause. I Have Selected These Few Instances

From A Great Number Of The Like Kind,  Which Madox Had Selected

From A Still Greater Number,  Preserved In The Ancient Rolls Of

The Exchequer.

 

Sometimes A Party Litigant Offered The King A Certain Portion, 

A Half,  A Third,  A Fourth,  Payable Out Of The Debts Which He,  As

The Executor Of Justice,  Should Assist In Recovering. Theophania

De Westland Agreed To Pay The Half Of Two Hundred And Twelve

Marks,  That She Might Recover That Sum Against James De

Fughleston; Solomon,  The Jew,  Engaged To Pay One Mark

Out Of Every Seven That He Should Recover Against Hugh De La

Hose; Nicholas Morrel Promised To Pay Sixty Pounds,  That The Earl

Of Flanders Might Be Distrained To Pay Him Three Hundred And

Forty-Three Pounds,  Which The Earl Had Taken From Him; And These

Sixty Pounds Were To Be Paid Out Of The First Money That Nicholas

Should Recover From The Earl."   Hume,  Appendix 2.

 

"In The Reign Of Henry Ii,,  The Best And Most Just Of These (The

Norman) Princes,  * *Peter,  Of Blois,  A Judicious And Even Elegant

Writer,  Of That Age,  Gives A Pathetic Description Of The Venality

Of Justice,  And The Oppressions Of The Poor,  * * And He Scruples

Not To Complain To The King Himself Of These Abuses. We May Judge

What The Case Would Be Under The Government Of Worse Princes." 

Hume,  Appendix 2.

 

Carte Says:

 

"The Crown Exercised In Those Days An Exorbitant And

Inconvenient Power,  Ordering The Justices Of The King's Court,  In

Suits About Lands,  To Turn Out,  Put,  And Keep In Possession,

Which Of The Litigants They Pleased; To Send Contradictory

Orders; And Take Large Sums Of Money From Each; To Respite

Proceedings; To Direct Sentences; And The Judges,  Acting By Their

Commission,  Conceived Themselves Bound To Observe Such Orders,

To The Great Delay,  Interruption,  And Preventing Of Justice; At

Least,  This Was John's Practice,"   Carte's History Of England,

Vol. 1,  P. 832.

 

Hallam Says:

 

"But Of All The Abuses That Deformed The Anglo-Saxon Government,

None Was So Flagitious As The Sale Of Judicial Redress,  The King,

We Are Often Told,  Is The Fountain Of Justice; But In Those Ages

It Was One Which Gold Alone Could Unseal. Men Fined (Paid Fines)

To Have Right Done Them; To Sue In A Certain Court; To Implead A

Certain Person; To Have Restitution Of Land Which They Had

Recovered At Law. From The Sale Of That Justice Which Every

Citizen Has A Right To Demand,  It Was An Easy Transition To

Withhold Or Deny It. Fines Were Received For The King's Help

Against The Adverse Suitor; That Is,  For Perversion Of Justice,

Or For Delay. Sometimes They Were Paid By Opposite Parties,  And,

Of Course,  For Opposite Ends."   2 Middle Ages,  438.

 

In Allusion To The Provision Of Magna Carta On This Subject,

Hallam Says:

 

"A Law Which Enacts That Justice Shall Neither Be Sold,  Denied,

Nor Delayed,  Stamps With Infamy That Government Under Which It

Had Become Necessary."   2 Middle Ages,  451.

 

Lingard,  Speaking Of The Times Of Henry Ii.,  (Say 1184,) Says:

 

"It Was Universally Understood That Money Possessed Greater

Influence Than Justice In The Royal Courts,  And Instances Are On

Record,  In Which One Party Has Made The King A Present To

Accelerate,  And The Other By A More Valuable Offer Has Succeeded

In Retarding A Decision. * * But Besides The Fines Paid To The

Sovereigns,  The Judges Often Exacted Presents For Themselves,  And

Loud Complaints Existed Against Their Venality And Injustice." 

8 Lingard,  231.

 

In The Narrative Of "The Costs And Charges Which I,  Richard De

Anesty,  Bestowed In Recovering The Land Of William,  My Uncle,"

(Some Fifty Years Before Magna Carta,) Are The Following Items:

 

"To Ralph,  The King's Physician,  I Gave Thirty-Six Marks And One

Half; To The King An Hundred Marks; And To The Queen One Mark Of

Gold." The Result Is Thus Stated. "At Last,  Thanks To Our Lord

The King,  And By Judgment Of His Court,  My Uncle's Land Was

Adjudged To Me."   2 Palgrave's Rise And Progress Of The English

Commonwealth,  P. 9 And 24.

 

Palgrave Also Says:

 

"The Precious Ore Was Cast Into The Scales Of Justice,  Even When

Held By The Most Conscientious Of Our Anglo-Saxon Kings. A Single

Case Will Exemplify The Practices Which Prevailed. Alfric,  The

Heir Of 'Aylwin,  The Black,' Seeks To Set Aside The Death-Bed

Bequest,  By Which His Kinsman Bestowed Four Rich And Fertile

Manors Upon St. Benedict. Alfric,  The Claimant,  Was Supported By

Extensive And Powerful Connexions; And Abbot Alfwine,  The

Defendant,  Was Well Aware That There Would Be Danger In The

Discussion Of The Dispute In Public,  Or Before The Folkmoot,

(People's Meeting,  Or County Court); Or,  In Other Words,  That The

Thanes Of The Shire Would Do Their Best To Give A Judgment In

Favor Of Their Compeer. The Plea Being Removed Into The Royal

Court,  The Abbot Acted With That Prudence Which So Often Calls

Forth The Praises Of The Monastic Scribe. He Gladly Emptied

Twenty Marks Of Gold Into The Sleeve Of The Confessor,  (Edward,)

And Five Marks Of Gold Presented To Edith,  The Fair,  Encouraged

Her To Aid The Bishop,  And To Exercise Her Gentle Influence In

His Favor. Alfric,  With Equal Wisdom,  Withdrew From Prosecuting

The Hopeless Cause,  In Which His Opponent Might Possess An

Advocate In The Royal Judge,  And A Friend In The King's Consort.

Both Parties. Therefore,  Found It Desirable To Come To An

Agreement."   1 Palgrave's Rise And Progress,  &C;.,  P. 650.

 

But Magna Carta Has Another Provision For The Trial Of Civil

Suits,  That Obviously Had Its Origin In The Corruption Of The

King's Judges. The Provision Is,  That Four Knights,  To Be Chosen

In Every County,  By The People Of The County,  Shall Sit With The

King's Judges,  In The Common Pleas,  In Jury Trials,  (Assizes,) On

The Trial Of Three Certain Kinds Of Suits,  That Were Among The

Most Important That Were Tried At All. The Reason For This

Provision Undoubtedly Was,  That The Corruption And Subserviency

Of The King's Judges Were So Well Known,  That The People Would

Not Even Trust Them To Sit Alone In A Jury Trial Of Any

Considerable Importance. The Provision Is This:

 

Chap. 22,  (Of John's Charter.) "Common Pleas Shall Not Follow Our

Court,  But Shall Be Holden In Some Certain Place. Trials Upon The

Writ Of Novel Disseisin,  And Of Mort D'ancester,  And Of Darrein

Presentment,  Shall Be Taken But In Their Proper Counties,  And

After This Manner: We,  Or,  If We Should Be Out Of Our Realm,  Our

Chief Justiciary,  Shall Send Two Jnsticiaries Through Every

County Four Times A Year; [3] Who,  With Four Knights Chosen Out

Of Every Shire,  By The People,  Shall Hold The Assizes (Juries) In

The County,  On The Day And At The Place Appointed."

 

It Would Be Very Unreasonable To Suppose That The King's Judges

Were Allowed To Dictate The Law To The Juries,  When The People

Would Not Even Suffer Them To Sit Alone In Jury Trials,  But

Themselves Chose Four Men To Sit With Them,  To Keep Them Honest.

[4]

 

This Practice Of Sending The King's Judges Into The Counties

Chapter 4 (The Rights And Duties Of Juries In Civil Suits) Pg 99

To Preside At Jury Trials,  Was Introduced By The Norman Kings

Under The Saxons It Was Not So. No Officer Of The King Was

Allowed To Preside At A Jury Trial; But Only Magistrates Chosen

By The People.[5]

 

But The Following Chapter Of John's Charter,  Which Immediately

Succeeds The One Just Quoted,  And Refers To The Same Suits,

Affords Very Strong,  Not To Say Conclusive,  Proof,  That Juries

Judged Of The Law In Civil Suits   That Is,  Made The Law,  So Far

As Their Deciding According To Their Own Notions Of Justice Could

Make The Law.

 

Chap. 23. "And If,  On The County Day,  The Aforesaid Assizes

Cannot Be Taken,  So Many Knights And Freeholders Shall Remain,  Of

Those Who Shall Have Been Present On Said Day,  As That The

Judgments May Be Rendered By Them,  Whether The Business Be More

Or Less."

 

The Meaning Of This Chapter Is,  That So Many Of The Civil

Suits,  As Could Not Be Tried On The Day When The King's Justices

Were Present,  Should Be Tried Afterwards,  By The Four Knights

Before Mentioned,  And The Freeholders,  That Is,  The Jury. It Must

Be Admitted,  Of Course,  That The Juries,  In These Cases,  Judged

The Matters Of Law,  As Well As Fact,  Unless It Be Presumed That

The Knights Dictated The Law To The Jury Na Thing Of Which There

Is No Evidence At All.

 

As A Final Proof On This Point,  There Is A Statute Enacted

Seventy Years After Magna Carta,  Which,  Although It Is Contrary

To The Common Law,  And Therefore Void,  Is Nevertheless Good

Evidence,  Inasmuch As It Contains An Acknowledgment,  On The Part

Of The King Himself,  That Juries Had A Right To Judge Of The

Whole Matter,  Law And Fact,  In Civil Suits. The Provision Is

This:

 

"It Is Ordained,  That The Justices Assigned To Take The Assizes,

Shall Not Compel The Jurors To Say Precisely Whether It Be

Disseisin,  Or Not,  So That They Do Show The Truth Of The Deed,

And Seek Aid Of The Justices. But If They Will,  Of Their Own

Accord,  Say That It Is Disseisin,  Or Not,  Their Verdict Shall Be

Admitted At Their Own Peril."   13 Edward I.,  St. 1,  Ch. 3,  Sec.

2. (1285.)

 

The Question Of "Disseisin,  Or Not," Was A Question Of Law,  As

Well As Fact. This Statute,  Therefore,  Admits That The Law,  As

Well As The Fact,  Was In The Hands Of The Jury. The Statute Is

Nevertheless Void,  Because The King Had No Authority To Give

Jurors A Dispensation From The Obligation Imposed Upon Them By

Their Oaths And The "Law Of The Land," That They Should "Make

Known The Truth According Their (Own) Consciences." This They

Were Bound To Do,  And There Was No Power In The King To Absolve

Them From The Duty. And The Attempt Of The King Thus To Absolve

Them,  And Authorize Them To Throw The Case Into The Hands Of The

Judges For Decision,  Was Simply An Illegal And Unconstitutional

Chapter 4 (The Rights And Duties Of Juries In Civil Suits) Pg 100

Attempt To Overturn The "Law Of The Land," Which He Was Sworn To

Maintain,  And Gather Power Into His Own Hands,  Through His

Judges. He Had Just As Much Constitutional Power To Enact That

The Jurors Should Not Be Compelled To Declare The Facts,  But That

They Might Leave Them To Be Determined By The King's Judges,  As

He Had To Enact That They Should Not Be Compelled To Declare The

Law,  But Might Leave It To Be Decided By The King's Judges. 122

It Was As Much The Legal Duty Of The Jury To Decide The Law As To

Decide The Fact; And No Law Of The King Could Affect Their

Obligation To Do Either. And This Statute Is Only One Example Of

The Numberless Contrivances And Usurpations Which Have Been

Resorted To,  For The Purpose Of Destroying The Original And

Genuine Trial By Jury.

 

[1] Marches,  The Limits,  Or Boundaries,  Between England And

Wales.

 

[2] That The Kings Would Have Had No Scruples To Enact Laws For

The Special Purpose Of Plundering The People,  By Means Of The

Judgments Of Juries,  If They Could Have Got Juries To Acknowledge

The Authority Of Their Laws,  Is Evident From The Audacity With

Which They Plundered Them,  Without Any Judgments Of Juries To

Authorize Them.

 

It Is Not Necessary To Occupy Space Here To Give Details As To

These Robberies; But Only Some Evidence Of The General Fact.

 

Hallam Says,  That "For The First Three Reigns (Of The Norman

Kings) * * The Intolerable Exactions Of Tribute,  The Rapine Of

Purveyance,  The Iniquity Of Royal Courts,  Are Continually In The

Mouths Of The Historians. ' God Sees The Wretched People,' Says

The Saxon Chronicler,  'Most Unjustly Oppressed; First They Are

Despoiled Of Their Possessions,  And Then Butchered.' This Was A

Grievous Year (1124). Whoever Had Any Property,  Lost It By Heavy

Taxes And Unjust Decrees."   2 Middle Ages,  435-6.

 

"In The Succeeding Reign Of John,  All The Rapacious Exactions

Usual To These Norman Kings Were Not Only Redoubled,  But Mingled

With Outrages Of Tyranny Still More Intolerable.

 

"In 1207 John Took A Seventh Of The Movables Of Lay And Spiritual

Persons,  All Murmuring,  But None Daring To Speak Against It." 

Ditto,  446.

 

In Hume's Account Of The Extortions Of Those Times,  The Following

Paragraph Occurs:

 

"But The Most Barefaced Acts Of Tyranny And Oppression Were

Practised Against The Jews,  Who Were Entirely Out Of The

Protection Of The Law,  And Were Abandoned To The Immeasurable

Rapacity Of The King And His Ministers. Besides Many Other

Indignities,  To Which They Were Continually Exposed,  It Appears

That They Were Once All Thrown Into Prison,  And The Sum Of 66,000

Marks Exacted For Their Liberty. At Another Time,  Isaac,  The Jew,

Chapter 4 (The Rights And Duties Of Juries In Civil Suits) Pg 101

Paid Alone 5100 Marks",  Brun,  3000 Marks; Jurnet,  2000; Bennet,

500. At Another,  Licorica,  Widow Of David,  The Jew Of Oxford,  Was

Required To Pay 6000 Marks."   Hume's Hist Eng.,  Appendix 2.

 

Further Accounts Of The Extortions And Oppressions Of The Kings

May Be Found In Hume's History,  Appendix 2,  And In Hallam's

Middle Ages,  Vol. 2,  P. 435 To 446.

 

By Magna Carta John Bound Himself To Make Restitution For Some

Of The Spoliations He Had Committed Upon Individuals "Without The

Legal Judgment Of Their Peers."   See Magna Carta Of John,  Ch.

60,  61,  65 And 66.

 

One Of The Great Charges,  On Account Of Which The Nation Rose

Against John,  Was,  That He Plundered Individuals Of Their

Property,  "Without Legal Judgment Of Their Peers." Now It Was

Evidently Very Weak And Short Sighted In John To Expose Himself

To Such Charges,  If His Laws Were Really Obligatory Upon The

Peers; Because,  In That Case,  He Could Have Enacted Any Laws That

Were Necessary For His Purpose,  And Then,  By Civil Suits,  Have

Brought The Cases Before Juries For Their "Judgment," And Thus

Have Accomplished All His Robberies In A Perfectly Legal Manner.

 

There Would Evidently Have Been No Sense In These Complaints,

That He Deprived Men Of Their Property "Without Legal Judgment Of

Their Peers," If His Laws Had Been Binding Upon The Peers;

Because He Could Then Have Made The Same Spoliations As Well With

The Judgment Of The Peers As Without It. Taking The Judgment Of

The Peers In The Matter,  Would Have Been Only A Ridiculous And

Useless Formality,  If They Were To Exercise No Discretion Or

Conscience Of Their Own,  Independently Of The Laws Of The King.

 

It May Here Be Mentioned,  In Passing,  That The Same Would Be True

In Criminal Mature,  If The King's Laws Were Obligatory Upon

Juries.

 

As An Illustration Of What Tyranny The Kings Would Sometimes

Practise,  Hume Says:

 

"It Appears From The Great Charter Itself,  That Not Only John,  A

Tyrannical Prince,  And Richard,  A Violent One,  But Their Father

Henry,  Under Whose Reign The Prevalence Of Gross Abuses Is The

Least To Be Suspected,  Were Accustomed,  From Their Sole

Authority,  Without Process Of Law,  To Imprison,  Banish,  And

Attaint The Freemen Of Their Kingdom."   Hume,  Appendix 2.

 

The Provision,  Also,  In The 64th Chapter Of Magna Carta,  That "

All Unjust And Illegal Fines,  And All Amercements,  Imposed

Unjustly,  And Contrary To The Law Of The Land,  Shall Be Entirely

Forgiven," &C;.; And The Provision,  In Chapter 61,  That The King

"Will Cause Full Justice To Be Administered" In Regard To "All

Those Things,  Of Which Any Person Has,  Without Legal Judgment Of

His Peers,  Been Dispossessed Or Deprived,  Either By King Henry,

Our Father.,  Or Our Brother,  King Richard," Indicate The

Chapter 4 (The Rights And Duties Of Juries In Civil Suits) Pg 102

Tyrannical Practices That Prevailed.

 

We Are Told Also That John Himself "Had Dispossessed Several

Great Men Without Any Judgment Of Their Peers,  Condemned Others

To Cruel Deaths,  * * Insomuch That His Tyrannical Will Stood

Instead Of A Law."   Echard's History Of England,  106.

Now All These Things Were Very Unnecessary And Foolish,  If His

Laws Were Binding Upon Juries; Because,  In That Ease,  He Could

Have Procured The Conviction Of These Men In A Legal Manner,  And

Thus Have Saved The Necessity Of Such Usurpation. In Short,  If

The Laws Of The King Had Been Binding Upon Juries,  There Is No

Robbery,  Vengeance,  Or Oppression,  Which He Could Not Have

Accomplished Through The Judgments Of Juries. This Consideration

Is Sufficient,  Of Itself,  To Prove That The Laws Of The King Were

Of No Authority Over A Jury,  In Either Civil Or Criminal Cases,

Unless The Juries Regarded The Laws As Just In Themselves.

 

[3] By The Magna Carta Of Henry Iii.,  This Is Changed To Once A

Year.

 

[4] From The Provision Of Magna Carta,  Cited In The Text,  It Must

Be Inferred That There Can Be No Legal Trial By Jury,  In Civil

Eases,  If Only The King's Justices Preside; That,  To Make The

Trial Legal,  There Must Be Other Persons,  Chosen By The People,

To Sit With Them; The Object Being To Prevent The Jury's Being

Deceived By The Justices. I Think We Must Also Infer That The

King's Justices Could Sit Only In The Three Actions Specially

Mentioned. We Cannot Go Beyond The Letter Of Magria Carta,  In

Making Innovations Upon The Common Law,  Which Required All

Presiding Officers In Jury Trials To Be Elected By The People.

 

[5] ["The Earls,  Sheriffs,  And Head-Boroughs Were Annually

Elected In The Full Folcmote,  (People's Meeting)." Introduction

To Gilbert's History Of The Common Pleas,  P. 2,  Note.

 

"It Was The Especial Province Of The Earldomen Or Earl To Attend

The Shyre-Meeting,  (The County Court,) Twice A Year,  And There

Officiate As The County Judge In Expounding The Secular Laws,  As

Appears By The Fifth Of Edgar's Laws."   Same,  P. 2,  Note.

 

"Every Ward Had Its Proper Alderman,  Who Was Chosen,  And Not

Imposed By The Prince."   Same,  P. 4,  Text.

 

"As The Aldermen,  Or Earls,  Were Always Chosen" (By The People)

"From Among The Greatest Thanes,  Who In Those Times Were

Generally More Addicted To Arms Than To Letters,  They Were But

Ill-Qualified For The Administration Of Justice,  And Performing

The Civil Duties Of Their Office."   3 Henry's History Of Great

Britain,  343.

 

"But None Of These Thanes Were Annually Elected In The Full

Folcmote,  (People's Meeting,) As The Earls,  Sheriffs,  And

Head-Boroughs Were; Nor Did King Alfred (As This Author Suggests)

Deprive The People Of The Election Of Those Last Mentioned

Chapter 4 (The Rights And Duties Of Juries In Civil Suits) Pg 103

Magistrates And Nobles,  Much Less Did He Appoint Them Himself." 

Introd. To Gilbert's Hist. Com. Pleas,  P. 2,  Note.

 

"The Sheriff Was Usually Not Appointed By The Lord,  But Elected

By The Freeholders Of The District."   Political Dictionary,  Word

Sheriff.

 

"Among The Most Remarkable Of The Saxon Laws We May Reckon

* * The Election Of Their Magistrates By The People,  Originally Even

That Of Their Kings,  Till Dear-Bought  Experience Evinced The

Convenience And Necessity Of Establishing An Hereditary

Succession To The Crown. But That (The Election) Of All

Subordinate Magistrates,  Their Military Officers Or Heretochs,

Their Sheriffs,  Their Conservators Of The Peace,  Their Coroners,

Their Portreeves,  (Since Changed Into Mayors And Bailiffs,) And

Even Their Tithing-Men And Borsholders At The Last,  Continued,

Some,  Till The Norman Conquest,  Others For Two Centuries After,

And Some Remain To This Day."   4 Blackstone,  418.

 

"The Election Of Sheriffs Was Left To The People,  According To

Ancient Usage."   St. West. 1,  C. 27.   Crabbe's History Of

English Law,  181.

 

 

 

Chapter 5 (Objections Answered) Pg 104

The Following Objections Will Be Made To The Doctrines And The

Evidence Presented In The Preceding Chapters.

 

1. That It Is A Maxim Of The Law,  That The Judges Respond To The

Question Of Law,  And Juries Only To The Question Of Fact.

The Answer To This Objection Is,  That,  Since Magna Carta,  Judges

Have Had More Than Six Centuries In Which To Invent And

Promulgate Pretended Maxims To Suit Themselves; And This Is One

Of Them. Instead Of Expressing The Law,  It Expresses Nothing But The

Ambitious And Lawless Will Of The Judges Themselves,  And Of Those

Whose Instruments They Are.[1]

 

2. It Will Be Asked,  Of What Use Are The Justices,  If The Jurors

Judge Both Of Law And Fact?

 

The Answer Is,  That They Are Of Use,  1. To Assist And Enlighten

The Jurors,  If They Can,  By Their Advice And Information; Such

Advice And Information To Be Received Only For What They May

Chance To Be Worth In The Estimation Of The Jurors.  2. To Do

Anything That May Be Necessary In Regard,  To Granting Appeals And

New Trials.

 

3. It Is Said That It Would Be Absurd That Twelve Ignorant Men

Should Have Power To Judge Of The Law,  While Justices Learned In

Chapter 5 (Objections Answered) Pg 105

The Law Should Be Compelledto Sit By And See The Law Decided

Erroneously.

 

One Answer To This Objection Is,  That The Powers Of Juries Are Not

Granted To Them On The Supposition That They Know The Law Better

Than The Justices; But On The Ground That The Justices Are

Untrustworthy,  That They Are Exposed To Bribes,  Are Themselves

Fond Of Power And Authority,  And Are Also The Dependent And

Subservient Creatures Of The Legislature; And That To Allow Them

To Dictate The Law,  Would Not Only Expose The Rights Of Parties To

Be Sold For Money,  But Would Be Equivalent To Surrendering All The

Property,  Liberty,  And Rights Of The People,  Unreservedly Into The

Hands Of Arbitrary Power,  (The Legislature,) To Be Disposed Of At

Its Pleasure. The Powers Of Juries,  Therefore,  Not Only Place A

Curb Upon The Powers Of Legislators And Judges,  But Imply Also An

Imputation Upon Their Integrity And Trustworthiness: And These Are

The Reasons Why Legislators And Judges Have Formerly Entertained

The Intensest Hatred Of Juries,  And,  So Fast As They Could Do It

Without Alarming The People For Their Liberties,  Have,  By

Indirection,  Denied,  Undermined,  And Practically Destroyed Their

Power. And It Is Only Since All The Real Power Of Juries Has Been

Destroyed,  And They Have Become Mere Tools In The Hands Of

Legislators And Judges,  That They Have Become Favorites With Them.

 

Legislators And Judges Are Necessarily Exposed To All The

Temptations Of Money,  Fame,  And Power,  To Induce Them To

Disregard Justice Between Parties,  And Sell The Rights,  And Violate The

Liberties Of The People. Jurors,  On The Other Hand,  Are Exposed To

None Of These Temptations. They Are Not Liable To Bribery,  For

They Are Unknown To The Parties Until They Come Into The Jury-Box.

They Can Rarely Gain Either Fame,  Power,  Or Money,  By Giving

Erroneous Decisions. Their Offices Are Temporary,  And They Know

That When They Shall Have Executed Them,  They Must Return To The

People,  To Hold All Their Own Rights In Life Subject To The

Liability Of Such Judgments,  By Their Successors,  As They

Themselves Have Given An Example For. The Laws Of Human Nature

Do Not Permit The Supposition That Twelve Men,  Taken By Lot From The

Mass Of The People,  And Acting Under Such Circumstances,  Will All

Prove Dishonest. It Is A Supposable Case That They May Not Be

Sufficiently Enlightened To Know And Do Their Whole Duty,  In All

Cases Whatsoever; But That They Should All Prove Dishonest,  Is Not

Within The Range Of Probability. A Jury,  Therefore,  Insures To Us  

What No Other Court Does   That First And Indispensable Requisite

In A Judicial Tribunal,  Integrity.

 

4. It Is Alleged That If Juries Are Allowed To Judge Of The Law,

They Decide The Law Absolutely; That Their Decision Must

Necessarily Stand,  Be It Right Or Wrong; And That This Power Of

Absolute Decision Would Be Dangerous In Their Hands,  By Reason Of

Their Ignorance Of The Law.

 

One Answer Is,  That This Power,  Which Juries Have Of Judging Of

The Law,  Is Not A Power Of Absolute Decision In All Cases.  For

Example,  It Is A Power To Declare Imperatively That A Man's

Property,  Liberty,  Or Life,  Shall Not Be Taken From Him; But It Is

Not A Power To Declare Imperatively That They Shall Be Taken From

Him.

 

Magna Carta Does Not Provide That The Judgments Of The Peers Shall

Be Executed; But Only That No Other Than Their Judgments Shall

Ever Be Executed,  So Far As To Take A Party's Goods,  Rights,  Or

Person,  Thereon.

 

A Judgment Of The Peers May Be Reviewed,  And Invalidated,  And A

New Trial Granted. So That Practically A Jury Has No Absolute

Power To Take A Party's Goods,  Rights,  Or Person. They Have Only

An Absolute Veto Upon Their Being Taken By The Government. The

Government Is Not Bound To Do Everything That A Jury May Adjudge.

It Is Only Prohibited From Doing Anything   (That Is,  From Taking

A Party's Goods,  Rights,  Or Person)   Unless A Jury Have First

Adjudged It To Be Done.

 

But It Will,  Perhaps,  Be Said,  That If An Erroneous Judgment Of

One Jury Should Be Reaffirmed By Another,  On A New Trial,  It Must

Then Be Executed. But Magna Carta Does Not Command Even This 

Although It Might,  Perhaps,  Have Been Reasonably Safe For It To

Have Done So   For If Two Juries Unanimously Affirm The Same

Thing,  After All The Light And Aid That Judges And Lawyers Can

Afford Them,  That Fact Probably Furnishes As Strong A Presumption

In Favor Of The Correctness Of Their Opinion,  As Can Ordinarily Be

Obtained In Favor Of A Judgment,  By Any Measures Of A Practical

Character For The Administration Of Justice. Still,  There Is

Nothing In Magna Carta That Compels The Execution Of Even A

Second Judgment Of A Jury. The Only Injunction Of Magna Carta

Upon The Government,  As To What It Shall Do,  On This Point,  Is That It

Shall "Do Justice And Right," Without Sale,  Denial,  Or Delay. But

This Leaves The Government All Power Of Determining What Is

Justice And Right,  Except That It Shall Not Consider Anything As

Justice And Right   So Far As To Carry It Into Execution Against

The Goods,  Rights,  Or Person Of A Party   Unless It Be Something

Which A Jury Have Sanctioned.

 

If The Government Had No Alternative But To Execute All Judgments

Of A Jury Indiscriminately,  The Power Of Juries Would

Unquestionably Be Dangerous; For There Is No Doubt That They May

Sometimes Give Hasty And Erroneous Judgments. But When It Is

Considered That Their Judgments Can Be Reviewed,  And New Trials

Granted,  This Danger Is,  For All Practical Purposes,  Obviated.

 

If It Be Said That Juries May Successively Give Erroneous

Judgments,  And That New Trials Cannot Be Granted Indefinitely,  The

Answer Is,  That So Far As Magna Carta Is Concerned,  There Is

Nothing To Prevent The Granting Of New Trials Indefinitely,  If The

Judgments Of Juries Are Contrary To "Justice And Right." So That

Magna Carta Does Not Require Any Judgment Whatever To Be

Executed So Far As To Take A Party's Goods,  Rights,  Or Person,  Thereon 

Unless It Be Concurred In By Both Court And Jury.

 

Chapter 5 (Objections Answered) Pg 106

Nevertheless,  We May,  For The Sake Of The Argument,  Suppose The

Existence Of A Practical,  If Not Legal,  Necessity,  For Executing

Some Judgment Or Other,  In Cases Where Juries Persist In

Disagreeing With The Courts. In Such Cases,  The Principle Of Magna

Carta Unquestionably Is,  That The Uniform Judgments Of

Successivejuries Shall Prevail Over The Opinion Of The Court. And

The Reason Of This Principle Is Obvious,  Viz.,  That It Is The Will Of The

Country,  And Not The Will Of The Court,  Or The Government,  That

Must Determine What Laws Shall Be Established And Enforced; That

The Concurrent Judgments Of Successive Juries,  Given In Opposition

To All The Reasoning Which Judges And Lawyers Can Offer To The

Contrary,  Must Necessarily Be Presumed To Be A Truer Exposition Of

The Will Of The Country,  Than Are The Opinions Of The Judges.

 

But It May Be Said That,  Unless Jurors Submit To The Control Of

The Court,  In Matters Of Law,  They May Disagree Amongthemselves,

And Never Come To Any Judgment; And Thus Justice Fail To Be Done.

 

Such A Case Is Perhaps Possible; But,  If Possible,  It Can Occur

But Rarely; Because,  Although One Jury May Disagree,  A Succession

Of Juries Are Not Likely To Disagree   That Is,  On Matters Of

Natural Law,  Or Abstract Justice. [2] If Such A Thing Should

Occur,  It Would Almost Certainly Be Owing To The Attempt Of The

Court To Mislead Them. It Is Hardly Possible That Any Other Cause

Should Be Adequate To Produce Such An Effect; Because Justice

Comes Very Near To Being A Self-Evident Principle. The Mind

Perceives It Almost Intuitively. If,  In Addition To This,  The

Court Be Uniformly On The Side Of Justice,  It Is Not A Reasonable

Supposition That A Succession Of Juries Should Disagree About It.

If,  Therefore,  A Succession Of Juries Do Disagree On The Law Of

Any Case,  The Presumption Is,  Not That Justice Fails Of Being

Done,  But That Injustice Is Prevented   That Injustice,  Which

Would Be Done,  If The Opinion Of The Court Were Suffered To

Control The Jury.

 

For The Sake Of The Argument,  However,  It May Be Admitted To Be

Possible That Justice Should Sometimes Fail Of Being Done Through

The Disagreements Of Jurors,  Notwithstanding All The Light Which

Judges And Lawyers Can Throw Upon The Question In Issue. If It Be

Asked What Provision The Trial By Jury Makes For Such Cases,  The

Answer Is,  It Makes None; And Justice Must Fail Of Being Done,

From The Want Of Its Being Made Sufficiently Intelligible.

 

Under The Trial By Jury,  Justice Can Never Be Done   That Is,  By A

Judgment That Shall Take A Party's Goods,  Rights,  Or Person 

Until That Justice Can Be Made Intelligible Or Perceptible To The

Minds Of All The Jurors; Or,  At Least,  Until It Obtain The

Voluntary Assent Of All   An Assent,  Which Ought Not To Be Given

Until The Justice Itself Shall Have Become Perceptible To All.

 

The Principles Of The Trial By Jury,  Then,  Are These:

 

1. That,  In Criminal Cases,  The Accused Is Presumed Innocent.

Chapter 5 (Objections Answered) Pg 107

 

2. That,  In Civil Cases,  Possession Is Presumptive Proof Of

Property; Or,  In Other Words,  Every Man Is Presumed To Be The

Rightful Proprietor Of Whatever He Has In His Possession.

 

3. That These Presumptions Shall Be Overcome,  In A Court Of

Justice,  Only By Evidence,  The Sufficiency Of Which,  And By Law,

The Justice Of Which,  Are Satisfactory To The Under- Standing And

Consciences Of All The Jurors.

 

These Are The Bases On Which The Trial By Jury Places The

Property,  Liberty,  And Rights Of Every Individual.

 

But Some One Will Say,  If These Are The Principles Of The Trial By

Jury,  Then It Is Plain That Justice Must Often Fail To Be Done.

Admitting,  For The Sake Of The Argument,  That This May Be True,

The Compensation For It Is,  That Positive Injustice Will Also

Often Fail To Be Done; Whereas Otherwise It Would Be Done

Frequently. The Very Precautions Used To Prevent Injustice Being

Done,  May Often Have The Effect To Prevent Justice Being Done. Bu

Are We,  Therefore,  To Take No Precautions Against Injustice? By No

Means,  All Will Agree. The Question Then Arises   Does The Trial

By Jury,  As Here Explained,  Involve Such Extreme And Unnecessary

Precautions Against Injustice,  As To Interpose Unnecessary

Obstacles To The Doing Of Justice? Men Of Different Minds May Very

Likely Answer This Question Differently,  According As They Have

More Or Less Confidence In The Wisdom And Justice Of Legislators,

The Integrity And Independence Of Judges,  And The Intelligence Of

Jurors. This Much,  However,  May Be Said In Favor Of These

Precautions,  Viz.,  That The History Of The Past,  As Well As Our

Constant Present Experience,  Prove How Much Injustice May,  And

Certainly Will,  Be Done,  Systematically And Continually,  For The

Want Of These Precautions   That Is,  While The Law Is Authoritatively

Made And Expounded By Legislators And Judges. On The Other Hand, 

We Have No Such Evidence Of How Much Justice May Fail To Be Done, 

By Reason Of These Precautions   That Is,  By Reason Of The Law Being

Left To The Judgments And Consciences Of Jurors. We Can Determine

The Former Point   That Is,  How Much Positive Injustice Is Done

Under The First Of These Two Systems Because The System Is In Full

Operation; But We Cannot Determine How Much Justice Would

Fail To Be Done Under The Latter System,  Because We Have,  In

Modern Times,  Had No Experience Of The Use Of The Precautions

Themselves. In Ancient Times,  When These Precautions Were

Nominally In Force,  Such Was The Tyranny Of Kings,  And Such The

Poverty,  Ignorance,  And The Inability Of Concert And Resistance, 

On The Part Of The People,  That The System Had No Full Or Fair

Operation. It,  Nevertheless,  Under All These Disadvantages, 

Impressed Itself Upon The Understandings,  And Imbedded Itself

In The Hearts,  Of The People,  So As No Other System Of Civil Liberty

Has Ever Done.

 

But This View Of The Two Systems Compares Only The Injustice Done,

And The Justice Omitted To Be Done,  In The Individual Cases Adjudged, 

Without Looking Beyond Them. And Some Persons Might,  On

Chapter 5 (Objections Answered) Pg 108

First Thought,  Argue That,  If Justice Failed Of Being Done Under

The One System,  Oftener Than Positive Injustice Were Done Under

The Other,  The Balance Was In Favor Of The Latter System. But Such

A Weighing Of The Two Systems Against Each Other Gives No True

Idea Of Their Comparative Merits Or Demerits; For,  Possibly,  In

This View Alone,  The Balance Would Not Be Very Great In Favor Of

Either. To Compare,  Or Rather To Contrast,  The Two,  We Must

Consider That,  Under The Jury System,  The Failures To Do Justice

Would Be Only Rare And Exceptional Cases; And Would Be Owing

Either To The Intrinsic Difficulty Of The Questions,  Or To The

Fact That The Parties Had. Transacted Their Business In A Manner

Unintelligible To The Jury,  And The Effects Would Be Confined To

The Individual Or Individuals Interested In The Particular Suits.

No Permanent Law Would Be Established Thereby Destructive Of The

Rights Of The People In Other Like Cases. And The People At Large

Would Continue To Enjoy All Their Natural Rights As Before. But

Under The Other System,  Whenever An Unjust Law Is Enacted By The

Legislature,  And The Judge Imposes It Upon The Jury As

Authoritative,  And They Give A Judgment In Accordance Therewith,

The Authority Of The Law Is Thereby Established,  And The Whole

People Are Thus Brought Under The Yoke Of That Law; Because They

Then Understand That The Law Will Be Enforced Against Them In

Future,  If They Presume To Exercise Their Rights,  Or Refuse To

Comply With The Exactions Of The Law. In This Manner All Unjust

Laws Are Established,  And Made Operative Against The Rights Of The

People.

 

The Difference,  Then,  Between The Two Systems Is This: Under The

One System,  A Jury,  At Distant Intervals,  Would (Not Enforce Any

Positive Injustice,  But Only) Fail Of Enforcing Justice,  In A Dark

And Difficult Case,  Or In Consequence Of The Parties Not Having

Transacted Their Business In A Manner Intelligible To A Jury; And

The Plaintiff Would Thus Fail Of Obtaining What Was Rightfully Due

Him. And There The Matter Would End,  For Evil,  Though Not For

Good; For Thenceforth Parties,  Warned,  Of The Danger Of Losing

Their Rights,  Would Be Careful To Transact Their Business In A

More Clear And Intelligible Manner. Under The Other System   The

System Of Legislative And Judicial Authority   Positive Injustice

Is Not Only Done In Every Suit Arising Under Unjust Laws,   That

Is,  Men's Property,  Liberty,  Or Lives Are Not Only Unjustly Taken

On Those Particular Judgments,   But The Rights Of The Whole People

Are Struck Down By The Authority Of The Laws Thus Enforced,  And A

Wide-Sweeping Tyranny At Once Put In Operation.

 

But There Is Another Ample And Conclusive Answer To The Argument

That Justice Would Often Fail To Be Done,  If Jurors Were Allowed

To Be Governed By Their Own Consciences,  Instead Of The Direction

Of The Justices,  In Matters Of Law. That Answer Is This:

 

Legitimate Government Can Be Formed Only By The Voluntary

Association Of All Who Contribute To Its Support. As A Voluntary

Association,  It Can Have For Its Objects Only Those Things In

Which The Members Of The Association Are All Agreed. If,

Therefore,  There Be Any Justice,  In Regard To Which All The

Chapter 5 (Objections Answered) Pg 109

Parties To The Government Are Not Agreed,  The Objects Of The

Association Do Not Extend To It. [3]

 

If Any Of The Members Wish More Than This,   If They Claim To Have

Acquired A More Extended Knowledge Of Justice Than Is Common To

All,  And Wish To Have Their Pretended Discoveries Carried Into

Effect,  In Reference To Themselves,    They Must Either Form A

Separate Association For That Purpose,  Or Be Content To Wait Until

They Can Make Their Views Intelligible To The People At Large.

They Cannot Claim Or Expect That The Whole People Shall Practise

The Folly Of Taking On Trust Their Pretended Superior Knowledge,

And Of Committing Blindly Into Their Hands All Their Own

Interests,  Liberties,  And Rights,  To Be Disposed Of On Principles,

The Justness Of Which The People Themselves Cannot Comprehend.

 

A Government Of The Whole,  Therefore,  Must Necessarily Confine

Itself To The Administration Of Such Principles Of Law As All The

People,  Who Contribute To The Support Of The Government,  Can

Comprehend And See The Justice Of. And It Can Be Confined Within

Those Limits Only By Allowing The Jurors,  Who Represent All The

Parties To The Compact,  To Judge Of The Law,  And The Justice Of

The Law,  In All Cases Whatsoever. And If Any Justice Be Left

Undone,  Under These Circumstances,  It Is A Justice For Which The

Nature Of The Association Does Not Provide,  Which The Association

Does Not Undertake To Do,  And Which,  As An Association,  It Is

Under No Obligation To Do.

 

The People At Large,  The Unlearned And Common People,  Have

Certainly An Indisputable Right To Associate For The Establishment

And Maintenance Of Such A Government As They Themselves See The

Justice Of,  And Feel The Need Of,  For The Promotion Of Their Own

Interests,  And The Safety Of Their Own Rights,  Without At The Same

Time Surrendering All Their Property,  Liberty,  And Rights Into The

Hands Of Men,  Who,  Under The Pretence Of A Superior And

Incomprehensible Knowledge Of Justice,  May Dispose Of Such

Property,  Liberties,  And Rights,  In A Manner To Suit Their Own

Selfish And Dishonest Purposes.

 

If A Government Were To Be Established And Supported Solely By

That Portion Of The People Who Lay Claim To Superior Knowledge,

There Would Be Some Consistency In Their Saying That The Common

People Should Not Be Received As Jurors,  With Power To Judge Of

The Justice Of The Laws. But So Long As The Whole People (Or All

The Male Adults) Are Presumed To Be Voluntary Parties To The

Government,  And Voluntary Contributors To It Support,  There Is No

Consistency In Refusing To Any One Of Them More Than To Another

The Right To Sit As Juror,  With Full Power To Decide For Himself

Whether Any Law That Is Proposed To Be Enforced In Any Particular

Case,  Be Within The Objects Of The Association.

 

The Conclusion,  Therefore,  Is,  That,  In A Government Formed By

Voluntary Association,  Or On The Theory Of Voluntary Association,

And Voluntary Support,  (As All The North American Governments

Are,) No Law Can Rightfully Be Enforced By The Association In Its

Chapter 5 (Objections Answered) Pg 110

Corporate Capacity,  Against The Goods,  Rights,  Or Person Of Any

Individual,  Except It Be Such As All The Members Of The

Association Agree That It May Enforce. To Enforce Any Other Law,

To The Extent Of Taking A Man's Goods,  Rights,  Or Person,  Would Be

Making Some Of The Parties To The Association Accomplices In What

They Regard As Acts Of Injustice. It Would Also Be Making Them

Consent To What They Regard As The Destruction Of Their Own

Rights. These Are Things Which No Legitimate System Or Theory Of

Government Can Require Of Any Of The Parties To It.

 

The Mode Adopted,  By The Trial By Jury,  For Ascertaining Whether

All The Parties To The Government Do Approve Of A Particular Law,

Is To Take Twelve Men At Random From The Whole People,  And Accept

Their Unanimous Decision As Representing The Opinions Of The

Whole. Even This Mode Is Not Theoretically Accurate; For

Theoretical Accuracy Would Require That Every Man,  Who Was A

Party To The Government,  Should Individually Give His Consent To The

Enforcement Of Every Law In Every Separate Case. But Such A Thing

Would Be Impossible In Practice. The Consent Of Twelve Men Is

Therefore Taken Instead; With-The Privilege Of Appeal,  And (In

Case Of Error Found By The Appeal Court) A New Trial,  To Guard

Against Possible Mistakes. This System,  It Is Assumed,  Will

Ascertain The Sense Of The Whole People   "The Country"   With

Sufficient Accuracy For All Practical Purposes,  And With As Much

Accuracy As Is Practicable Without Too Great Inconvenience And

Expense.

 

5. Another Objection That Will Perhaps Be Made To Allowing Jurors

To Judge Of The Law,  And The Justice Of The Law,  Is,  That The Law

Would Be Uncertain.

 

If,  By This Objection,  It Be Meant That The Law Would Be Uncertain

To The Minds Of The People At Large,  So That They Would Not Know

What The Juries Would Sanction And What Condemn,  And Would Not

Therefore Know Practically What Their Own Rights And Liberties

Were Under The Law,  The Objection Is Thoroughly Baseless And

False. No System Of Law That Was Ever Devised Could Be So Entirely

Intelligible And Certain To The Minds Of The People At Large As

This. Compared With It,  The Complicated Systems Of Law That Are

Compounded Of The Law Of Nature,  Of Constitutional Grants,  Of

Innumerable And Incessantly Changing Legislative Enactments,  And

Of Countless And Contradictory Judicial Decisions,  With No Uniform

Principle Of Reason Or Justice Running Through Them,  Are Among The

Blindest Of All The Mazes In Which Unsophisticated Minds Were Ever

Bewildered And Lost. The Uncertainty Of The Law Under These

Systems Has Become A Proverb. So Great Is This Uncertainty,  That

Nearly All Men,  Learned As Well As Unlearned,  Shun The Law As

Their Enemy,  Instead Of Resorting To It For Protection. They

Usually Go Into Courts Of Justice,  So Called,  Only As Men Go Into

Battle   When There Is No Alternative Left For Them. And Even Then

They Go Into Them As Men Go Into Dark Labyrinths And Caverns 

With No Knowledge Of Their Own,  But Trusting Wholly To Their

Guides. Yet,  Less Fortunate Than Other Adventurers,  They Can Have

Little Confidence Even In Their Guides,  For The Reason That The

Chapter 5 (Objections Answered) Pg 111

Guides Themselves Know Little Of The Mazes They Are Threading.

They Know The Mode And Place Of Entrance; But What They Will

Meet With On Their Way,  And What Will Be The Time,  Mode,  Place, 

Or Condition Of Their Exit; Whether They Will Emerge Into A Prison,

Or Not; Whether Wholly Naked And Destitute,  Or Not; Whether With

Their Reputations Left To Them,  Or Not; And Whether In Time Or

Eternity; Experienced And Honest Guides Rarely Venture To Predict.

Was There Ever Such Fatuity As That Of A Nation Of Men Madly Bent

On Building Up Such Labyrinhs As These,  For No Other Purpose Than

That Of Exposing All Their Rights Of Reputation,  Property,  Liberty, 

And Life,  To The Hazards Of Being Lost In Them,  Instead Of Being

Content To Live In The Light Of The Open Day Of Their Own

Understandings?

 

What Honest,  Unsophisticated Man Ever Found Himself Involved

In A Lawsuit,  That He Did Not Desire,  Of All Things,  That His Cause

Might Be Judged Of On Principles Of Natural Justice,  As Those

Principles Were Understood By Plain Men Like Himself? He Would

Then Feel That He Could Foresee The Result. These Plain Men Are

The Men Who Pay The Taxes,  And Support The Government. Why

Should They Not Have Such An Administration Of Justice As They

Desire,  And Can Understand?

 

If The Jurors Were To Judge Of The Law,  And The Justice Of The

Law,  There Would Be Something Like Certainty In The Administration

Of Justice,  And In The Popular Knowledge Of The Law,  And Men

Would Govern Themselves Accordingly. There Would Be Something

Like Certainty,  Because Every Man Has Himself Something Like

Definite And Clear Opinions,  And Also Knows Something Of The

Opinions Of His Neighbors,  On Matters Of Justice. And He Would

Know That No Statute,  Unless It Were So Clearly Just As To Command

The Unanimous Assent Of Twelve Men,  Who Should Be Taken At Random

From The Whole Community,  Could Be Enforced So As To Take From Him

His Reputation,  Property,  Liberty,  Or Life. What Greater Certainty Can

Men Require Or Need,  As To The Laws Under Which They Are To Live?

If A Statute Were Enacted By A Legislature,  A Man,  In Order To Know

What Was Its True Interpretation,  Whether It Were Constitutional,  And

Whether It Would Be Enforced,  Would Not Be Under The Necessity Of

Waiting For Years Until Some Suit Had Arisen And Been Carried Through

All The Stages Of Judicial Proceeding,  To A Final Decision. He Would

Need Only To Use His Own Reason As To Its Meaning And Its Justice, 

And Then Talk With His Neighbors On The Same Points. Unless He

Found Them Nearly Unanimous In Their Interpretation And Approbation

Of It,  He Would Conclude That Juries Would Not Unite In Enforcing It, 

And That It Would Consequently Be A Dead Letter. And He Would Be

Safe In Coming To This Conclusion.

 

There Would Be Something Like Certainty In The Administration Of

Justice,  And In The Popular Knowledge Of The Law,  For The Further

Reason That There Would Be Little Legislation,  And Men's Rights

Would Be Left To Stand Almost Solely Upon The Law Of Nature,  Or

What Was Once Called In England "The Common Law," (Before So

Much Legislation And Usurpation Had Become Incorporated Into The

Common Law,) In Other Words,  Upon The Principles Of Natural Justice.

Chapter 5 (Objections Answered) Pg 112

Of The Certainty Of This Law Of Nature,  Or The Ancient English

Common Law,  I May Be Excused For Repeating Here What,  I Have

Said On Another Occasion.

 

"Natural Law,  So Far From Being Uncertain,  When Compared With

Statutory And Constitutional Law,  Is The Only Thing That Gives Any

Certainty At All To A Very Large Portion Of Our Statutory And

Constitutional Law. The Reason Is This. The Words In Which

Statutes And Constitutions Are Written Are Susceptible Of So Many

Different Meanings,    Meanings Widely Different From,  Often

Directly Opposite To,  Each Other,  In Their Bearing Upon Men's

Rights,    That,  Unless There Were Some Rule Of Interpretation For

Determining Which Of These Various And Opposite Meanings Are The

True Ones,  There Could Be No Certainty At All As To The Meaning Of

The Statutes And Constitutions Themselves. Judges Could Make

Almost Anything They Should Please Out Of Them. Hence The

Necessity Of A Rule Of Interpretation. And This Rule Is,  That The

Language Of Statutes And Constitutions Shall Be Construed,  As

Nearly As Possible,  Consistently With Natural Law.

 

The Rule Assumes,  What Is True,  That Natural Law Is A Thing

Certain In Itself; Also That It Is Capable Of Being Learned. It

Assumes,  Furthermore,  That It Actually Is Understood By The

Legislators And Judges Who Make And Interpret The Written Law.

Of Necessity,  Therefore,  It Assumes Further,  That They (The

Legislators And Judges) Are Incompetent To Make And Interpret The

Written Law,  Unless They Previously Understand The Natural Law

Applicable To The Same Subject. It Also Assumes That The People

Must Understand The Natural Law,  Before They Can Understated The

Written Law.

 

It Is A Principle Perfectly Familiar To Lawyers,  And One That Must

Be Perfectly Obvious To Every Other Man That Will Reflect A

Moment,  That,  As A General Rule,  No One Can Know What The Written

Law Is,  Until He Knows What It Ought To Be; That Men Are Liable To

Be Constantly Misled By The Various And Conflicting Senses Of The

Same Words,  Unless They Perceive The True Legal Sense In Which The

Words Ought To Be Taken. And This True Legal Sense Is The Sense

That Is Most Nearly Consistent With Natural Law Of Any That The

Words Can Be Made To Bear,  Consistently With The Laws Of Language,

And Appropriately To The Subjects To Which They Are Applied.

 

Though The Words Contain The Law,  The Words Themselves Are Not

The Law. Were The Words Themselves The Law,  Each Single Written

Law Would Be Liable To Embrace Many Different Laws,  To Wit,  As

Many Different Laws As There Were Different Senses,  And Different

Combinations Of Senses,  In Which Each And All The Words Were

Capable Of Being Taken.

 

Take,  For Example,  The Constitution Of The United States. By

Adopting One Or Another Sense Of The Single Word "Free,"  The

Whole Instrument Is Changed. Yet The Word Free Is Capable Of Some

Ten Or Twenty Different Senses. So That,  By Changing The Sense Of

That Single Word,  Some Ten Or Twenty Different Constitutions Could

Be Made Out Of The Same Written Instrument. But There Are,  We Will

Suppose,  A Thousand Other Words In The Constitution,  Each Of Which

Is Capable Of From Two To Ten Different Senses. So That,  By

Changing The Sense Of Only A Single Word At A Time,  Several

Thousands Of Different Constitutions Would Be Made. But This Is

Not All. Variations Could Also Be Made By Changing The Senses Of

Two Or More Words At A Time,  And These Variations Could Be Run

Through All The Changes And Combinations Of Senses That These

Thousand Words Are Capable Of. We See,  Then,  That It Is No More

Than A Literal Truth,  That Out Of That Single Instrument,  As It

Now Stands,  Without Altering The Location Of A Single Word,  Might

Be Formed,  By Construction And Interpretation,  More Different

Constitutions Than Figures Can Well Estimate.

 

But Each Written Law,  In Order To Be A Law,  Must Be Taken Only In

Some One Definite And Distinct Sense; And That Definite And

Distinct Sense Must Be Selected From The Almost Infinite Variety

Of Senses Which Its Words Are Capable Of. How Is This Selection To

Be Made? It Can Be Only By The Aid Of That Perception Of Natural

Law,  Or Natural Justice,  Which Men Naturally Possess.

Such,  Then,  Is The Comparative Certainty Of The Natural And The

Written Law. Nearly All The Certainty There Is In The Latter,  So

Far As It Relates To Principles,  Is Based Upon,  And Derived From,

The Still Greater Certainty Of The Former. In Fact,  Nearly All The

Uncertainty Of The Laws Under Which We Live,    Which Are A Mixture

Of Natural And Written Laws,    Arises From The Difficulty Of

Construing,  Or,  Rather,  From The Facility Of Misconstruing,  The

Written Law; While Natural Law Has Nearly Or Quite The Same

Certainty As Mathematics. On This Point,  Sir William Jones,  One Of

The Most Learned Judges That Have Ever Lived,  Learned In Asiatic

As Well As European Law,  Says,     And  The Fact Should Be Kept

Forever In Mind,  As One Of The Most Important Of All Truths:   "It

Is Pleasing To Remark,  The Similarity,  Or,  Rather,  The Identity Of

Those Conclusions Which Pure,  Unbiased Reason,  In All Ages; And

Nations,  Seldom Fails To Draw,  In Such Juridical Inquiries As Are

Not Fettered And Manacled By Positive Institutions." [4] In Short,

The Simple Fact That The Written Law Must Be Interpreted By The

Natural,  Is,  Of Itself,  A Sufficient Confession Of The Superior

Certainty Of The Latter.

 

The Written Law,  Then,  Even Where It Can Be Construed Consistently

With The Natural,  Introduces Labor And Obscurity,  Instead Of

Shutting Them Out. And This Must Always Be The Case,  Because

Words Do Not Create Ideas,  But Only Recall Them; And The Same

Word May Recall Many Different Ideas. For This Reason,  Nearly All

Abstract Principles Can Be Seen By The Single Mind More Clearly

Than They Can Be Expressed By Words To Another. This Is Owing To The

Imperfection Of Language,  And The Different Senses,  Meanings,  And

Shades Of Meaning,  Which Different Individuals Attach To The Same

Words,  In The Same Circumstances. [5]

 

Where The Written Law Cannot Be Construed Consistently With The

Natural,  There Is No Reason Why It Should Ever Be Enacted At All.

It May,  Indeed,  Be Sufficiently Plain And Certain To Be Easily

Chapter 5 (Objections Answered) Pg 113

Understood; But Its Certainty And Plainness Are But A Poor

Compensation For Its Injustice. Doubtless A Law Forbidding Men To

Drink Water,  On Pain Of Death,  Might Be Made So Intelligible As To

Cut Off All Discussion As To Its Meaning; But Would The

Intelligibleness Of Such A Law Be Any Equivalent For The Right To

Drink Water? 

 

The Principle Is The Same In Regard To All Unjust Laws. Few

Persons Could Reasonably Feel Compensated For The Arbitrary

Destruction Of Their Rights,  By Having The Order For Their

Destruction Made Known Beforehand,  In Terms So Distinct And

Unequivocal As To Admit Of Neither Mistake Nor Evasion. Yet This

Is All The Compensation That Such Laws Offer.

 

Whether,  Therefore,  Written Laws Correspond With,  Or Differ From,

The Natural,  They Are To Be Condemned. In The First Case,  They Are

Useless Repetitions,  Introducing Labor And Obscurity. In The

Latter Case,  They Are Positive Violations Of Men's Rights.

There Would Be Substantially The Same Reason In Enacting

Mathematics By Statute,  That There Is In Enacting Natural Law.

Whenever The Natural Law Is Sufficiently Certain To All Men's

Minds To Justify Its Being Enacted,  It Is Sufficiently Certain To

Need No Enactment. On The Other Hand,  Until It Be Thus Certain,

There Is Danger Of Doing Injustice By Enacting It; It Should,

Therefore,  Be Left Open To Be Discussed By Anybody Who May Be

Disposed To Question It,  And To Be Judged Of By The Proper

Tribunal,  The Judiciary. [6]

 

It Is Not Necessary That Legislators Should Enact Natural Law In

Order That It May Be Known To The People,  Because That Would Be

Presuming That The Legislators Already Understand It Better Than

The People,    A Fact Of Which I Am Not Aware That They Have Ever

Heretofore Given Any Very Satisfactory Evidence. The Same Sources

Of Knowledge On The Subject Are Open To The People That Are Open

To The Legislators,  And The People Must Be Presumed To Know It As

Well As They.

 

The Objections Made To Natural Law,  On The Ground Of Obscurity,

Are Wholly Unfounded. It Is True,  It Must Be Learned,  Like Any

Other Science; But It Is Equally True That It Is Very Easily

Learned. Although As Illimitable In Its Applications As The

Infinite Relations Of Men To Each Other,  It Is,  Nevertheless,  Made

Up Of Simple Elementary Principles,  Of The Truth And Justice Of

Which Every Ordinary Mind Has An Almost Intuitive Perception. It

Is The Science Of Justice,    And Almost All Men Have The Same

Perceptions Of What Constitutes Justice,  Or Of What Justice

Requires,  When They Understand Alike The Facts From Which Their

Inferences Are To Be Drawn. Men Living In Contact With Each Other,

And Having Intercourse Together,  Cannot Avoid Learning Natural

Law,  To A Very Great Extent,  Even If They Would. The Dealings Of

Men With Men,  Their Separate Possessions,  And Their Individual

Wants,  Are Continually Forcing Upon Their Minds The Questions,  

Is This Act Just? Or Is It Unjust? Is This Thing Mine? Or Is It

His? And These Are Questions Of Natural Law; Questions,  Which,  In

Chapter 5 (Objections Answered) Pg 114

Regard To The Great Mass Of Cases,  Are Answered Alike By The Human

Mind Everywhere.

 

Children Learn Many Principles Of Natural Law At A Very Early Age.

For Example: They Learn That When One Child Has Picked Up An

Apple Or A Flower,  It Is His,  And That His Associates Must Not Take It

From Him Against His Will. They Also Learn That If He Voluntarily

Exchange His Apple Or Flower With A Playmate,  For Some Other

Article Of Desire,  He Has Thereby Surrendered His Right To It,  And

Must Not Reclaim It. These Are Fundamental Principles Of Natural

Law,  Which Govern Most Of The Greatest Interests Of Individuals

And Society; Yet Children Learn Them Earlier Than They Learn That

Three And Three Are Six,  Or Five And Five,  Ten. Talk Of Enacting

Natural Law By Statute,  That It May Be Known! It Would Hardly Be

Extravagant To Say,  That,  In Nine Cases In Ten,  Men Learn It

Before They Have Learned The Language By Which We Describe It.

Nevertheless,  Numerous Treatises Are Written On It,  As On Other

Sciences. The Decisions Of Courts,  Containing Their Opinions Upon

The Almost Endless Variety Of Cases That Have Come Before Them,

Are Reported; And These Reports Are Condensed,  Codified,  And

Digested,  So As To Give,  In A Small Compass,  The Facts,  And The

Opinions Of The Courts As To The Law Resulting From Them. And

These Treatises,  Codes,  And Digests Are Open To Be Read Of All

Men. And A Man Has The Same Excuse For Being Ignorant Of

Arithmetic,  Or Any Other Science,  That He Has For Being Ignorant

Of Natural Law. He Can Learn It As Well,  If He Will,  Without Its

Being Enacted,  As He Could If It Were.

 

If Our Governments Would But Themselves Adhere To Natural Law,

There Would Be Little Occasion To Complain Of The Ignorance Of The

People In Regard To It. The Popular Ignorance Of Law Is

Attributable Mainly To The Innovations That Have Been Made Upon

Natural Law By Legislation; Whereby Our System Has Become An

Incongruous Mixture Of Natural And Statute Law,  With No Uniform

Principle Pervading It. To Learn Such A System,    If System It Can

Be Called,  And If Learned It Can Be,    Is A Matter Of Very Similar

Difficulty To What It Would Be To Learn A System Of Mathematics,

Which Should Consist Of The Mathematics Of Nature,  Interspersed

With Such Other Mathematics As Might Be Created By Legislation,  In

Violation Of All The Natural Principles Of Numbers And Quantities.

 

But Whether The Difficulties Of Learning Natural Law Be Greater Or

Less Than Here Represented,  They Exist In The Nature Of Things,

And Cannot Be Removed. Legislation,  Instead Of Removing,  Only

Increases Them; This It Does By Innovating Upon Natural Truths And

Principles,  And Introducing Jargon And Contradiction,  In The Place

Of Order,  Analogy,  Consistency,  And Uniformity.

 

Further Than This; Legislation Does Not Even Profess To Remove The

Obscurity Of Natural Law. That Is No Part Of Its Object. It Only

Professes To Substitute Something Arbitrary In The Place Of

Natural Law. Legislators Generally Have The Sense To See That

Legislation Will Not Make Natural Law Any Clearer Than It Is.

Neither Is It The Object Of Legislation To Establish The Authority

Chapter 5 (Objections Answered) Pg 115

Of Natural Law. Legislators Have The Sense To See That They Can

Add Nothing To The Authority Of Natural Law,  And That It Will

Stand On Its Own Authority,  Unless They Overturn It.

The Whole Object Of Legislation,  Excepting That Legislation Which

Merely Makes Regulations,  And Provides Instrumentalities For

Carrying Other Laws Into Effect,  Is To Overturn Natural Law,  And

Substitute For It The Arbitrary Will Of Power. In Other Words,  The

Whole Object Of It Is To Destroy Men's Rights. At Least,  Such Is

Its Only Effect; And Its Designs Must Be Inferred From Its Effect.

Taking All The Statutes In The Country,  There Probably Is Not One

In A Hundred,  Except The Auxiliary Ones Just Mentioned,    That

Does Not Violate Natural Law; That Does Not Invade Some Right Or

Other.

 

Yet The Advocates Of Arbitrary Legislation Are Continually

Practising The Fraud Of Pretending That Unless The Legislature

Make The Laws,  The Laws Will Not Be Known. The Whole Object Of

The Fraud Is To Secure To The Government The Authority Of Making

Lawsthat Never Ought To Be Known."

 

In Addition To The Authority Already Cited,  Of Sir William Jones,

As To The Certainty Of Natural Law,  And The Uniformity Of Men's

Opinions In Regard To It,  I May Add The Following:

 

"There Is That Great Simplicity And Plainness In The Common Law,

That Lord Coke Has Gone So Far As To Assert,  (And Lord Bacon

Nearly Seconds Him In Observing,) That  'He Never Knew Two

Questions Arise Merely Upon Common Law; But That They Were

Mostly Owing To Statutes Ill-Penned And Overladen With Provisos.' "  

3 Eunomus,  157   8.

 

If It Still Be Said That Juries Would Disagree,  As To What Was

Natural Justice,  And That One Jury Would Decide One Way,  And

Another Jury Another; The Answer Is,  That Such A Thing Is Hardly

Credible,  As That Twelve Men,  Taken At Random From The People At

Large,  Should Unanimously Decide A Question Of Natural Justice One

Way,  And That Twelve Other Men,  Selected In The Same Manner,

Should Unanimously Decide The Same Question The Other Way,

Unless They Were Misled By The Justices. If,  However,  Such Things

Should Sometimes Happen,  From Any Cause Whatever,  The Remedy

Is By Appeal,  And New Trial.

 

[1] Judges Do Not Even Live Up To That Part Of Their Own Maxim,

Which Requires Jurors To Try The Matter Of Fact. By Dictating To

Them The Laws Of Evidence,    That Is,  By Dictating What Evidence

They May Hear,  And What They May Not Hear,  And Also By Dictating

To Them Rules For Weighing Such Evidence As They Permit Them To

Hear,    They Of Necessity Dictate The Conclusion To Which They

Shall Arrive. And Thus The Court Really Tries The Question Of

Fact,  As Well As The Question Of Law,  In Every Cause. It Is

Clearly Impossible,  In The Nature Of Things,  For A Jury To Try,  A

Question Of Fact,  Without Trying Every Question Of Law On Which

The Fact Depends.

 

[2] Most Disagreements Of Juries Are On Matters Of Fact,  Which Are

Admitted To Be Within Their Province. We Have Little Or No

Evidence Of Their Disagreements On Matters Of Natural Justice. The

Disagreements Of Courts On Matters Of Law,  Afford Little Or No

Evidence That Juries Would Also Disagree On Matters Of Law   That

Is,  Of Justice,  Because The Disagreements Of Courts Are Generally

On Matters Of Legislation,  And Not On Those Principles Of Abstract

Justice,  By Which Juries Would Be Governed,  And In Regard To Which

The Minds Of Men Are Nearly Unanimous.

 

[3] This Is The Principle Of All Voluntary Associations

Whatsoever. No Voluntary Association Was Ever Formed,  And In The

Nature Of Things There Never Can Be One Formed,  For The

Accomplishment Of Any Objects Except Those In Which All The

Parties To The Association Are Agreed. Government,  Therefore,  Must

Be Kept Within These Limits,  Or It Is No Longer A Voluntary

Association Of All Who Contribute To Its Support,  But A Mere

Tyrant Established By A Part Over The Rest.

 

All,  Or Nearly All,  Voluntary Associations Give To A Majority,  Or

To Some Other Portion Of The Members Less Than The Whole,  The

Right To Use Some Limited Discretion As To Themeans To Be Used To

Accomplish The Ends In View; But The End Themselves To Be

Accomplished Are Always Precisely Defined,  And Are Such As Every

Member Necessarily Agrees To,  Else He Would Not Voluntarily Join

The Association.

 

Justice Is The Object Of Government,  And Those Who Support The

Government,  Must Be Agreed As To The Justice To Be Executed By It,

Or They Cannot Rightfully Unite In Maintaining The Government

Itself.

 

[4] Jones On Bailments,

 

[5] Kent,  Describing The Difficulty Of Construing The Written Law,

Says:

 

"Such Is The Imperfection Of Language,  And The Want Of Technical

Skill In The Makers Of The Law,  That Statutes Often Give Occasion

To The Most Perplexing And Distressing Doubts And Discussions,

Arising From The Ambiguity That Attends Them. It Requires Great

Experience,  As Well As The Command Of A Perspicuous Diction,  To

Frame A Law In Such Clear And Precise Terms,  As To Secure It From

Ambiguous Expressions,  And From All Doubts And Criticisms Upon Its

Meaning "   Kent,  460.

 

The Following Extract From A Speech Of Lord Brougham,  In The

House Of Lords,  Confesses The Same Difficulty:

 

There Was Another Subject,  Well Worthy Of The Consideration Of

Government During The Recess,  The Expediency,  Or Rather The

Absolute Necessity,  Of Some Arrangement For The Preparation Of

Bills,  Not Merely Private,  But Public Bills,  In Order That

Legislation Might Be Consistent And Systematic,  And That The

Chapter 5 (Objections Answered) Pg 116

Courts Might Not Have So Large A Portion Of Their Time Occupied In

Endeavoring To Construe Acts Of Parliament,  In Many Cases

Unconstruable,  And In Most Cases Difficult To Be Construed."   Law

Reporter,  1848,  P. 525.

 

[6] This Condemnation Of Written Laws Must,  Of Course,  Be

Understood As Applying Only To Cases Where Principles And Rights

Are Involved,  And Not As Condemning Any Governmental

Arrangements,  Or Instrumentalities,  That Are Consistent With Natural

Right,  And Which Must Be Agreed Upon For The Purpose Of Carrying

Natural Law Into Effect. These Things May Be Varied,  As Expediency

May Dictate,  So Only That They Be Allowed To Infringe No Principle Of

Justice. And They Must,  Of Course,  Be Written,  Because They Do Not

Exist As Fixed Principles,  Or Laws In Nature.

 

 

Chapter 6 (Juries Of The Present Day Illegal) Pg 117

It May Probably Be Safely Asserted That There Are,  At This Day,

No Legal Juries,  Either In England Or America. And If There Are

No Legal Juries,  There Is,  Of Course,  No Legal Trial,  Nor

"Judgment," By Jury.

 

In Saying That There Are Probably No Legal Juries,  I Mean That

There Are Probably No Juries Appointed In Conformity With The

Principles Of The Common Law.

 

The Term Jury Is A Technical One,  Derived From The Common Law;

And When The American Constitutions Provide For The Trial By

Jury,  They Provide For The Common Law Trial By Jury; And Not

Merely For Any Trial By Jury That The Government Itself May

Chance To Invent,  And Call By That Name. It Is The Thing,  And Not

Merely The Name,  That Is Guarantied. Any Legislation,  Therefore,

That Infringes Any Essential Principle Of The Common Law,  In The

Selection Of Jurors,  Is Unconstitutional; And The Juries Selected

In Accordance With Such Legislation Are,  Of Course,  Illegal,  And

Their Judgments Void.

 

It Will Also Be Shown,  In A Subsequent Chapter,  [1] That Since

Magna Carta,  The Legislative Power In England (Whether King Or

Parliament) Has Never Had Any Constitutional Authority To

Infringe,  By Legislation,  Any Essential Principle Of The Common

Law In The Selection Of Jurors. All Such Legislation Is As Much

Unconstitutional And Void,  As Though It Abolished The Trial By

Jury Altogether. In Reality It Does Abolish It.

 

What,  Then,  Are The Essential Principles Of The Common Law,

Controlling The Selection Of Jurors?

 

They Are Two.

 

Chapter 6 (Juries Of The Present Day Illegal) Pg 118

1. That All The Freemen,  Or Adult Male Members Of The State,

Shall Be Eligible As Jurors. [2]

 

Any Legislation Which Requires The Selection Of Jurors To Be Made

From A Less Number Of Freemen Than The Whole,  Makes The Jury

Selected An Illegal One.

 

If A Part Only Of The Freemen,  Or Members Of The State,  Are

Eligible As Jurors,  The Jury No Longer Represent "The Country,"

But Only A Part Of "The Country."

 

If The Selection Of Jurors Can Be Restricted To Any Less Number

Of Freemen Than The Whole,  It Can Be Restricted To A Very Small

Proportion Of The Whole; And Thus The Government Be Taken Out Of

The Hands Of " The Country," Or The Whole People,  And Be Thrown

Into The Hands Of A Few.

 

That,  At Common Law,  The Whole Body Of Freemen Were Eligible As

Jurors,  Is Sufficiently Proved,  Not Only By The Reason Of The

Thing,  But By The Following Evidence:

 

1. Everybody Must Be Presumed Eligible,  Until The Contrary

Be Shown. We Have No Evidence,  That I Am Aware Of,  Of A

Prior Date To Magna Carta,  To Disprove That All Freemen Were

Eligible As Jurors,  Unless It Be The Law Of Ethelred,  Which

Requires That They Be Elderly [3] Men. Since No Specific Age

Is Given,  It Is Probable,  I Think,  That This Statute Meant

Nothing More Than That They Be More Than Twenty-One Years

Old. If It Meant Anything More,  It Was Probably Contrary To

The Common Law,  And Therefore Void.

 

2. Since Magna Carta,  We Have Evidence Showing Quite

Conclusively That All Freemen,  Above The Age Of Twenty-One

Years,  Were Eligible As Jurors.

 

The Mirror Of Justices,  (Written Within A Century After

Magna Carta,) In The Section " Of Judges"   That Is,  Jurors 

Says:

 

"All Those Who Are Not Forbidden By Law May Be Judges

(Jurors).

 

To Women It Is Forbidden By Law That They Be Judges; And Thence It

Is,  That Feme Coverts Are Exempted To Do Suit In Inferior Courts.

On The Other Part,  A Villein Cannot Be A Judge,  By Reason Of The

Two Estates,  Which Are Repugnants; Persons Attainted Of False

Judgments Cannot Be Judges,  Nor Infants,  Nor Any Under The Age Of

Twenty-One Years,  Nor Infected Persons,  Nor Idiots,  Nor Madmen,

Nor Deaf,  Nor Dumb,  Nor Parties In The Pleas,  Nor Men

Excommunicated By The Bishop,  Nor Criminal Persons. * * And

Those Who Are Not Of The Christian Faith Cannot Be Judges,  Nor Those

Who Are Out Of The King's Allegiance."   Mirror Of Justices,  59   60.

 

In The Section " Of Inferior Courts," It Is Said:

 

"From The First Assemblies Came Consistories,  Which We Now Call

Courts,  And That In Divers Places,  And In Divers Manners: Whereof

The Sheriffs Held One Monthly,  Or Every Five Weeks According To

The Greatness Or Largeness Of The Shires. And These Courts Are

Called County Courts,  Where The Judgment Is By The Suitors,  If

There Be No Writ,  And Is By Warrant Of Jurisdiction Ordinary. The

Other Inferior Courts Are The Courts Of Every Lord Of The Fee,  To

The Likeness Of The Hundred Courts. There Are Other Inferior

Courts Which The Bailiffs Hold In Every Hundred,  From Three Weeks

To Three Weeks,  By The Suitors Of The Freeholders Of The Hundred.

All The Tenants Within The Fees Are Bounden To Do Their Suit

There,  And That Not For The Service Of Their Persons,  But For The

Service Of Their Fees. But Women,  Infants Within The Age Of

Twenty-One Years,  Deaf,  Dumb,  Idiots,  Those Who Are Indicted Or

Appealed Of Mortal Felony,  Before They Be Acquitted,  Diseased

Persons,  And Excommunicated Persons Are Exempted From Doing

Suit."  Mirror Of Justices,  50   51.

 

In The Section "Of The Sheriff's Turns," It Is Said:

 

"The Sheriff's By Ancient Ordinances Hold Several Meetings Twice

In The Year In Every Hundred; Where All The Freeholders Within The

Hundred Are Bound To Appear For The Service Of Their Fees." 

Mirror Of Justices,  50.

 

The Following Statute Was Passed By Edward I.,  Seventy Years After

Magna Carta:

 

"Forasmuch Also As Sheriffs,  Hundreders,  And Bailiffs Of

Liberties,  Have Used To Grieve Those Which Be Placed Under Them,

Putting In Assizes And Juries Men Diseased And Decrepit,  And

Having Continual Or Sudden Disease; And Men Also That Dwelled Not

In The Country At The Time Of The Summons; And Summon Also An

Unreasonable Number Of Jurors,  For To Extort Money From Some Of

Them,  For Letting Them Go In Peace,  And So The Assizes And Juries

Pass Many Times By Poor Men,  And The Rich Abide At Home By

Reason Of Their Bribes; It Is Ordained That From Henceforth In One

Assize No More Shall Be Summoned Than Four And Twenty; And

Old Men Above Three Score And Ten Years,  Being Continually Sick, 

Or Being Diseased At The Time Of The Summons,  Or Not Dwelling In

That Country,  Shall Not Be Put In Juries Of Petit Assizes."   St. 13

Edward I.,  Ch. 38. (1285.)

 

Although This Command To The Sheriff's And Other Officers,  Not To

Summon,  As Jurors,  Those Who,  From Age And Disease,  Were

Physically Incapable Of Performing The Duties,  May Not,  Of Itself,

Afford Any Absolute Or Legal Implication,  By Which We Can

Determine Precisely Who Were,  And Who Were Not,  Eligible As Jurors

At Common Law,  Yet The Exceptions Here Made Nevertheless Carry A

Seeming Confession With Them That,  At Common Law,  All Male

Adults Were Eligible As Jurors.

 

But The Main Principle Of The Feudal System Itself,  Shows That All

Chapter 6 (Juries Of The Present Day Illegal) Pg 119

The Full And Free Adult Male Members Of The State   That Is,  All

Who Were Free Born,  And Had Not Lost Their Civil Rights By Crime,

Or Otherwise   Must,  At Common Law,  Have Been Eligible As Jurors.

What Was That Principle? It Was,  That The State Rested For Support

Upon The Land,  And Not Upon Taxation Levied Upon The People

Personally. The Lands Of The Country Were Considered The Property

Of The State,  And Were Made To Support The State In This Way: A

Portion Of Them Was Set Apart To The King,  The Rents Of Which Went

To Pay His Personal And Official Expenditures,  Not Including The

Maintenance Of Armies,  Or The Administration Of Justice. War And

The Administration Of Justice Were Provided For In The Following

Manner. The Freemen,  Or The Free-Born Adult Male Members Of The

State   Who Had Not Forfeited Their Political Rights   Were

Entitled To Land Of Right,  (Until All The Land Was Taken Up,) On

Condition Of Their Rendering Certain Military And Civil Services,

To The State. The Military Services Consisted In Serving

Personally As Soldiers,  Or Contributing An Equivalent In Horses,

Provisions,  Or Other Military Supplies. The Civil Services

Consisted,  Among Other Things,  In Serving As Jurors (And,  It Would

Appear,  As Witnesses) In The Courts Of Justice. For These Services

They Received No Compensation Other Than The Use Of Their Lands.

In This Way The State Was Sustained; And The King Had No Power To

Levy Additional Burdens Or Taxes Upon The People. The Persons

Holding Lands On These Terms Were Called Freeholders   In Later

Times Freemen   Meaning Free And Full Members Of The State.

 

Now,  As The Principle Of The System Was That The Freeholders Held

Their Lands Of The State,  On The Condition Of Rendering These

Military And Civil Services As Rents For Their Lands,  The

Principle Implies That All The Freeholders Were Liable To These

Rents,  And Were Therefore Eligible As Jurors. Indeed,  I Do Not

Know That It Has Ever Been Doubted That,  At Common Law,  All The

Freeholders Were Eligible As Jurors. If All Had Not Been Eligible,

We Unquestionably Should Have Had Abundant Evidence Of The

Exceptions. And If Anybody,  At This Day,  Allege Any Exceptions,

The Burden Will Be On Him To Prove Them. The Presumption Clearly

Is That All Were Eligible.

 

The First Invasion Which I Find Made,  By The English Statutes,

Upon This Common Law Principle,  Was Made In I285,  Seventy Years

After Magna Carta. It Was Then Enacted As Follows:

 

"Nor Shall,  Any Be Put In Assizes Or Juries,  Though They Ought To

Be Taken In Their Own Shire,  That Hold A Tenement Of Less Than The

Value Of Twenty Shillings Yearly. And If Such Assizes And Juries

Be Taken Out Of The Shire,  No One Shall Be Placed In Them Who

Holds A Tenement Of Less Value Than Forty Shillings Yearly At The

Least,  Except Such As Be Witnesses In Deeds Or Other Writings,

Whose Presence Is Necessary,  So That They Be Able To Travel." 

St. 13 .Edward I.,  Ch. 38. (1285.)

 

The Next Invasion Of The Common Law,  In This Particular,  Was Made

In 1414,  About Two Hundred Years After Magna Carta,  When It Was

Enacted:

Chapter 6 (Juries Of The Present Day Illegal) Pg 120

 

"That No Person Shall Be Admitted To Pass In Any Inquest Upon

Trial Of The Death Of A Man,  Nor In Any Inquest Betwixt Party And

Party In Plea Real,  Nor In Plea Personal,  Whereof The Debt Or The

Damage Declared Amount To Forty Marks,  If The Same Person Have

Not Lands Or Tenements Of The Yearly Value Of Forty Shillings Above

All Charges Of The Same."   2 Henry V.,  St. 2,  Ch. 3. (1414.)

 

Other Statutes On This Subject Of The Property Qualifications Of

Jurors,  Are Given In The Note. [4]

 

From These Statutes It Will Be Seen That,  Since 1285,  Seventy

Years After Magna Carta,  The Common Law Right Of All Free British

Subjects To Eligibility As Jurors Has Been Abolished,  And  The

Qualifications Of Jurors Have Been Made A Subject Of Arbitrary

Legislation. In Other Words,  The Government Has Usurped The

Authority Of Selecting The Jurors That Were To Sit In Judgment

Upon Its Own Acts. This Is Destroying The Vital Principle Of The

Trial By Jury Itself,  Which Is That The Legislation Of The Government

Shall Be Subjected To The Judgment Of A Tribunal,  Taken

Indiscriminately From The Whole People,  Without Any Choice By The

Government,  And Over Which The Government Can Exercise No

Control. If The Government Can Select The Jurors,  It Will,  Of Course,

Select Those Whom It Supposes Will Be Favorable To Its Enactments.

And An Exclusion Of Any Of The Freemen From Eligibility Is A

Selection Of Those Not Excluded.

 

It Will Be Seen,  From The Statutes Cited,  That The Most Absolute

Authority Over The Jury Box   That Is,  Over The Right Of The

People To Sit In Juries   Has Been Usurped By The Government; That

The Qualifications Of Jurors Have Been Repeatedly Changed,  And

Made To Vary From A Freehold Of Ten Shillings Yearly,  To One Of

"Twenty Pounds By The Year At Least Above Reprises." They Have

Also Been Made Different,  In The Counties Of Southampton,  Surrey,

And Sussex,  From What They Were In The Other Counties; Different

In Wales From What They Were In England; And Different In The City

Of London,  And In The County Of Middlesex,  From What They Were In

Any Other Part Of The Kingdom.

 

But This Is Not All. The Government Has Not Only Assumed

Arbitrarily To Classify The People,  On The Basis Of Property,  But

It Has Even Assumed To Give To Some Of Its Judges Entire And

Absolute Personal Discretion In The Selection Of The Jurors To Be

Impaneled In Criminal Cases,  As The Following Statutes Show.

 

"Be It Also Ordained And Enacted By The Same Authority,  That All

Panels Hereafter To Be Returned,  Which Be Not At The Suit Of Any

Party,  That Shall Be Made And Put In Afore Any Justice Of Gaol

Delivery Or Justices Of Peace In Their Open Sessions To Inquire

For The King,  Shall Hereafter Be Reformed By Additions And Taking

Out Of Names Of Persons By Discretion Of The Same Justices Before

Whom Such Panel Shall Be Returned; And The Same Justices Shall

Hereafter Command The Sheriff,  Or His Ministers In His Absence,  To

Put Other Persons In The Same Panel By Their Discretions; And That

Chapter 6 (Juries Of The Present Day Illegal) Pg 121

Panel So Hereafter To Be Made,  To Be Goodand Lawful.  This Act To

Endure Only To The Next Parliament "   11 Henry Vii.,  Ch. 24,  Sec.

6. (1495.)

 

This Act Was Continued In Force By 1 Henry Viii,  Ch. 11,  (1509,)

To The End Of The Then Next Parliament.

 

It Was Reenacted,  And Made Perpetual,  By 3 Henry Viii.,  Ch. 12.

(1511.)

 

These Acts Gave Unlimited Authority To The King's' Justices To

Pack Juries At Their Discretion; And Abolished The Last Vestige Of

The Common Law Right Of The People To Sit As Jurors,  And Judge Of

Their Own Liberties,  In The Courts To Which The Acts Applied.

 

Yet,  As Matters Of Law,  These Statutes Were No More Clear

Violations Of The Common Law,  The Fundamental And Paramount

"Law Of The Land," Than Were Those Statutes Which Affixed The

Property Qualifications Before Named; Because,  If The King,  Or The

Government,  Can Select The Jurors On The Ground Of Property,  It

Can Select Them On Any Other Ground Whatever.

 

Any Infringement Or Restriction Of The Common Law Right Of The

Whole Body Of The Freemen Of The Kingdom To Eligibility As Jurors,

Was Legally An Abolition Of The Trial By Jury Itself. The Juries

No Longer Represented "The Country," But Only A Part Of The

Country; That Part,  Too,  On Whose Favor The Government Chose To

Rely For The Maintenance Of Its Power,  And Which It Therefore Saw

Fit To Select As Being The Most Reliable Instruments For Its

Purposes Of Oppression Towards The Rest. And The Selection Was

Made On The Same Principle,  On Which Tyrannical Governments

Generally Select Their Supporters,  Viz.,  That Of Conciliating

Those Who Would Be Most Dangerous As Enemies,  And Most

Powerful As Friends That Is,  The Wealthy. [6]

 

These Restrictions,  Or Indeed Any One Of Them,  Of The Right Of

Eligibility As Jurors,  Was,  In Principle,  A Complete Abolition Of

The English Constitution; Or,  At Least,  Of Its Most Vital And

Valuable Part. It Was,  In Principle,  An Assertion Of A Right,  On

The Part Of The Government,  To Select The Individuals Who Were To

Determine The Authority Of Its Own Laws,  And The Extent Of Its Own

Powers. It Was,  Therefore,  In Effect,  The Assertion Of A Right,  On

The Part Of The Government Itself,  To Determine Its Own Powers,

And The Authority Of Its Own Legislation,  Over The People; And A

Denial Of All Right,  On The Part Of The People,  To Judge Of Or

Determine Their Own Liberties Against The Government. It Was,

Therefore,  In Reality,  A Declaration Of Entire Absolutism On The

Part Of The Government. It Was An Act As Purely Despotic,  In

Principle,  As Would Have Been The Express Abolition Of All Juries

Whatsoever. By "The Law Of The Land," Which The Kings Were Sworn

To Maintain,  Every Free Adult Male British Subject Was Eligible To

The Jury Box,  With Full Power To Exercise His Own Judgment As To

The Authority And Obligation Of Every Statute Of The King,  Which

Might Come Before Him. But The Principle Of These Statutes (Fixing

Chapter 6 (Juries Of The Present Day Illegal) Pg 122

The Qualifications Of Jurors) Is,  That Nobody Is To Sit In

Judgment Upon The Acts Or Legislation Of The King,  Or The

Government,  Except Those Whom The Government Itself Shall Select

For That Purpose. A More Complete Subversion Of The Essential

Principles Of The English Constitution Could Not Be Devised.

 

The Juries Of England Are Illegal For Another Reason,  Viz.,  That

The Statutes Cited Require The Jurors (Except In London And A Few

Other Places) To Be Freeholders. All The Other Free British

Subjects Are Excluded; Whereas,  At Common Law,  All Such Subjects

Are Eligible To Sit In Juries,  Whether They Be Freeholders Or Not.

 

It Is True,  The Ancient Common Law Required The Jurors To Be

Freeholders; But The Term Freeholder No Longer Expresses The Same

Idea That It Did In The Ancient Common Law; Because No Land Is Now

Holden In England On The Same Principle,  Or By The Same Tenure,  As

That On Which All The Land Was Held In The Early Times Of The

Common Law.

 

As Has Heretofore Been Mentioned,  In The Early Times Of The

Common Law The Land Was Considered The Property Of The State;

And Was All Holden By The Tenants,  So Called,  (That Is,  Holders,)

On The Condition Of Their Rendering Certain Military And Civil Services

To The State,  (Or To The King As The Representative Of The State,)

Under The Name Of Rents. Those Who Held Lands On These Terms

Were Called Free Tenants,  That Is,  Free Holders   Meaning Free Persons,

Or Members Of The State,  Holding Lands   To Distinguish Them From

Villeins,  Or Serfs,  Who Were Not Members Of The State,  But Held

Their Lands By A More Servile Tenure,  And Also To Distinguish Them

From Persons Of Foreign Birth,  Outlaws,  And All Other Persons,  Who

Were Not Members Of The State.

 

Every Freeborn Adult Male Englishman (Who Had Not Lost His Civil

Right" By Crime Or Otherwise) Was Entitled To Land Of Right; That

Is,  By Virtue Of His Civil Freedom,  Or Membership Of The Body

Politic. Every Member Of The State Was Therefore A Freeholder; And

Every Freeholder Was A Member Of The State. And The Members Of

The State Were Therefore Called Freeholders. But What Is Material To

Be Observed,  Is,  That A Man's Right To Land Was An Incident To His

Civil Freedom; Not His Civil Freedom An Incident To His Right To

Land. He Was A Freeholder Because He Was A Freeborn Member Of

The State; And Not A Freeborn Member Of The State Because He Was A

Freeholder; For This Last Would Be An Absurdity.

 

As The Tenures Of Lands Changed,  The Term Freeholder Lost Its

Original Significance,  And No Longer Described A Man Who Held Land

Of The State By Virtue Of His Civil Freedom,  But Only One Who Held

It In Fee-Simple   That Is,  Free Of Any Liability To Military Or

Civil Services. But The Government,  In Fixing The Qualifications

Of Jurors,  Has Adhered To The Term Freeholder After That Term Has

Ceased To Express The Thing Originally Designated By It.

 

The Principle,  Then,  Of The Common Law,  Was,  That Every Freeman,

Or Freeborn Male Englishman,  Of Adult Age,  &C;.,  Was Eligible To

Chapter 6 (Juries Of The Present Day Illegal) Pg 123

Sit In Juries,  By Virtue Of His Civil Freedom,  Or His Being A

Member Of The State,  Or Body Politic. Rut The Principle Of The

Present English Statutes Is,  That A Man Shall Have A Right To Sit

In Juries Because He Owns Lands In Fee-Simple. At The Common Law

A Man Was Born To The Right To Sit In Juries. By The Present

Statutes He Buys That Right When He Buys His Land. And Thus This,

The Greatest Of All The Political Rights Of An Englishman,  Has

Become A Mere Article Of Merchandise; A Thing That Is Bought And

Sold In The Market For What It Will Bring.

 

Of Course,  There Can Be No Legality In Such Juries As These; But

Only In Juries To Which Every Free Or Natural Born Adult Male

Englishman Is Eligible.

 

The Second Essential Principle Of The Common Law,  Controlling The

Selection Of Jurors,  Is,  That When The Selection Of The Actual

Jurors Comes To Be Made,  (From The Whole Body Of Male Adults,)

That Selection Shall Be Made In Some Mode That Excludes The

Possibility Of Choice On The Part Of The Government.

 

Of Course,  This Principle Forbids The Selection To Be Made By Any

Officer Of The Government.

 

There Seem To Have Been At Least Three Modes Of Selecting The

Jurors,  At The Common Law. 1. By Lot. [7] 2. Two Knights,  Or Other

Freeholders,  Were Appointed,  (Probably By The Sheriff,) To Select

The Jurors. 3. By The Sheriff,  Bailiff,  Or Other Person,  Who Held

The Court,  Or Rather Acted As Its Ministerial Officer. Probably

The Latter Mode May Have Been The Most Common,  Although There

May Be Some Doubt On This Point.

 

At The Common Law The Sheriff's,  Bailiffs,  And Other Officers Were

Chosen By The People,  Instead Of Being Appointed By The King. (4

Blackstone,  413. Introduction To Gilbert's History Of The Common

Pleas,  P. 2; Note,  And P. 4.) This Has Been Shown In A Former

Chapter. [8] At Common Law,  Therefore,  Jurors Selected By These

Officers Were Legally Selected,  So Far As The Principle Now Under

Discussion Is Concerned; That Is,  They Were Not Selected By Any

Officer Who Was Dependent On The Government.

 

But In The Year 1315,  One Hundred Years After Magna Carta,  The

Choice Of Sheriff's Was Taken From The People,  And It Was Enacted:

 

"That The Sheriffs Shall Henceforth Be Assigned By The Chancellor,

Treasurer,  Barons Of The Exchequer,  And By The Justices. And In

The Absence Of The Chancellor,  By The Treasurer,  Barons And

Justices."   9 Edward Ii.,  St. 2. (1315.)

 

These Officers,  Who Appointed The Sheriffs,  Were Themselves

Appointed By The King,  And Held Their Offices During His Pleasure.

Their Appointment Of Sheriffs Was,  Therefore,  Equivalent To An

Appointment By The King Himself. And The Sheriffs,  Thus Appointed,

Held Their Offices Only During The Pleasure Of The King,  And Were

Of Course Mere Tools Of The King; And Their Selection Of Jurors

Chapter 6 (Juries Of The Present Day Illegal) Pg 124

Was Really A Selection By The King Himself. In This Manner The

King Usurped The Selection Of The Jurors Who Were To Sit In

Judgment Upon His Own Laws.

 

Here,  Then,  Was Another Usurpation,  By Which The Common Law Trial

By Jury Was Destroyed,  So Far As Related To The County Courts,  In

Which The Sheriff's Presided,  And Which Were The Most Important

Courts Of The Kingdom. From This Cause Alone,  If There Were No

Other,  There Has Not Been A Legal Jury In A County Court In

England,  For More Than Five Hundred Years.

 

In Nearly Or Quite All The States Of The United States The Juries

Are Illegal,  For One Or The Other Of The Same Reasons That Make

The Juries In England Illegal.

 

In Order That The Juries In The United States May Be Legal   That

Is,  In Accordance With The Principles Of The Common Law It Is

Necessary That Every Adult Male Member Of The State Should Have

His Name In The Jury Box,  Or Be Eligible As A Juror. Yet This Is

The Case In Hardly A Single State.

 

In New Jersey,  Maryland,  North Carolina,  Tennessee,  And

Mississippi,  The Jurors Are Required To Be Freeholders. But This

Requirement Is Illegal,  For The Reason That The Term Freeholder,

In This Country,  Has No Meaning Analogous To The Meaning It Had In

The Ancient Common Law.

 

In Arkansas,  Missouri,  Indiana,  And Alabama,  Jurors Are Required

To Be "Freeholders Or Householders." Each Of These Requirements Is

Illegal.

 

In Florida,  They Are Required To Be "Householders."

 

In Connecticut,  Maine,  Ohio,  And Georgia,  Jurors Are Required To

Have The Qualifications Of "Electors."

 

In Virginia,  They Are Required To Have A Property Qualification Of

One Hundred Dollars.

 

In Maine,  Massachusetts,  Vermont,  Connecticut,  New York,  Ohio,

Indiana,  Michigan,  And Wisconsin,  Certain Civil Authorities Of The

Towns,  Cities,  And Counties Are Authorized To Select,  Once In One,

Two,  Or Three Years,  A Certain Number Of The People   A Small

Number Compared With The Whole   From Whom Jurors Are To Be

Taken

When Wanted; Thus Disfranchising All Except,  The Few Thus

Selected.

 

In Maine And Vermont,  The Inhabitants,  By Vote In Town Meeting,

Have A Veto Upon The Jurors Selected By The Authorities Of The

Town.

 

In Massachusetts,  The Inhabitants,  By Vote In Town Meeting,  Can

Strike Out Any Names Inserted By The Authorities,  And Insert

Chapter 6 (Juries Of The Present Day Illegal) Pg 125

Others; Thus Making Jurors Elective By The People,  And,  Of Course,

Representatives Only Of A Majority Of The People.

 

In Illinois,  The Jurors Are Selected,  For Each Term Of Court,  By

The County Commissioners.

 

In North Carolina,  "The Courts Of Pleas And Quarter Sessions Shall

Select The Names Of Such Persons Only As Are Freeholders,  And As

Are Well Qualified To Act As Jurors,  &C;.; Thus Giving The Courts

Power To Pack The Juries."   (Revised Statutes,  147.)

 

In Arkansas,  Too,  "It Shall Be The Duty Of The County Court Of

Each County * To Make Out And Cause To Be Delivered To The Sheriff

A List Of Not Less Than Sixteen,  Nor More Than Twenty-Three

Persons,  Qualified To Serve As Grand Jurors;" And The Sheriff Is

To Summon Such Persons To Serve As Grand Jurors.

 

In Tennessee,  Also,  The Jurors Are To Be Selected By The County

Courts.

 

In Georgia,  The Jurors Are To Be Selected By "The Justices Of The

Inferior Courts Of Each County,  Together With The Sheriff And

Clerk,  Or A Majority Of Them."

 

In Alabama,  "The Sheriff; Judge Of The County Court,  And Clerks Of

The Circuit And County Courts," Or "A Majority Of" Them,  Select

The Jurors.

 

In Virginia,  The Jurors Are Selected By The Sheriffs; But The

Sheriff's Are Appointed By The Governor Of The State,  And That Is

Enough To Make The Juries Illegal. Probably The Same Objection

Lies Against The Legality Of The Juries In Some Other States.

 

How Jurors Are Appointed,  And What Are Their Qualifications,  In

New Hampshire,  Rhode Island,  Pennsylvania,  Delaware,  South

Carolina,  Kentucky,  Iowa,  Texas,  And California,  I Know Not.

There

Is Little Doubt That There Is Some Valid Objection To Them,  Of The

Kinds Already Suggested,  In All These States.

 

In Regard To Jurors In The Courts Of The United States,  It Is

Enacted,  By Act Of Congress:

 

"That Jurors To Serve In The Courts Of The United States,  In Each

State Respectively,  Shall Have The Like Qualifications And Be

Entitled To The Like Exemptions,  As Jurors Of The Highest Court Of

Law Of Such State Now Have And Are Entitled To,  And Shall

Hereafter,  From Time To Time,  Have And Be Entitled To,  And Shall

Be Designated By Ballot,  Lot,  Or Otherwise,  According To The Mode

Of Forming Such Juries Now Practised And Hereafter To Be Practised

Therein,  In So Far As Such Mode May Be Practicable By The Courts

Of The United States,  Or The Officers Thereof; And For This

Purpose,  The Said Courts Shall Have Power To Make All Necessary

Rules And Regulations For Conforming The Designation And

Chapter 6 (Juries Of The Present Day Illegal) Pg 126

Empanelling Of Jurors,  In Substance,  To The Laws And Usages Now In

Force In Such State; And,  Further,  Shall Have Power,  By Role Or

Order,  From Time To Time,  To Conform The Same To Any Change In

These Respects Which May Be Hereafter Adopted By The Legislatures

Of The Respective States For The State Courts."   St. 1840,  Ch.

47,  Statutes At Large,  Vol. 5,  P. 394.

 

In This Corrupt And Lawless Manner,  Congress,  Instead Of Taking

Care To Preserve The Trial By Jury,  So Far As They Might,  By

Providing For The Appointment Of Legal Juries   Incomparably The

Most Important Of All Our Judicial Tribunals,  And The Only Ones On

Which The Least Reliance Can Be Placed For The Preservation Of

Liberty   Have Given The Selection Of Them Over Entirely To The

Control Of An Indefinite Number Of State Legislatures,  And Thus

Authorized Each State Legislature To Adapt The Juries Of The

United States To The Maintenance Of Any And Every System Of

Tyranny That May Prevail In Such State.

 

Congress Have As Much Constitutional Right To Give Over All The

Functions Of The United States Government Into The Hand Of The

State Legislatures,  To Be Exercised Within Each State In Such

Manner As The Legislature Of Such State Shall Please To Exercise

Them,  As They Have To Thus Give Up To These Legislatures The

Selection Of Juries For The Courts Of The United States.

 

There Has,  Probably,  Never Been A Legal Jury,  Nor A Legal Trial By

Jury,  In A Single Court Of The United States,  Since The Adoption

Of The Constitution.

 

These Facts Show How Much Reliance Can Be Placed In Written

Constitutions,  To Control The Action Of The Government,  And

Preserve The Liberties Of The People.

 

If The Real Trial By Jury Had Been Preserved In The Courts Of The

United States   That Is,  If We Had Had Legal Juries,  And The

Jurors Had Known Their Rights   It Is Hardly Probable That One

Tenth Of The Past Legislation Of Congress Would Ever Have Been

Enacted,  Or,  At Least,  That,  If Enacted,  It Could Have Been

Enforced.

 

Probably The Best Mode Of Appointing Jurors Would Be This: Let The

Names Of All The Adult [Male] [9] Members Of The State,  In Each

Township,  Be Kept In A Jury Box,  By The Officers Of The Township;

And When A Court Is To Be Held For A County Or Other District,  Let

The Officers Of A Sufficient Number Of Townships Be Required

(Without Seeing The Names) To Draw Out A Name From Their Boxes

Respectively,  To Be Returned To The Court As A Juror. This Mode Of

Appointment Would Guard Against Collusion And Selection; And

Juries So Appointed Would Be Likely To Be A Fair Epitome Of "The

Country."

 

[1]On The English Constitution.

 

[2] Although All The Freemen Are Legally Eligible As Jurors,  Any

Chapter 6 (Juries Of The Present Day Illegal) Pg 127

One May Nevertheless Be Challenged And Set Aside,  At The Trial,

For Any Special Personal Disqualification; Such As Mental Or

Physical Inability To Perform The Duties; Having Been Convicted,

Or Being Under Charge,  Of Crime; Interest,  Bias,  &C;. But It Is

Clear That The Common Law Allows None Of These Points To Be

Determined By The Court,  But Only By "Triers."

 

[3] What Was The Precise Meaning Of The Saxon Word,  Which I Have

Here Called Elderly,  I Do Not Know. In The Latin Translations It

Is Rendered By Seniores,  Which May Perhaps Mean Simply Those

Who Have Attained Their Majority.

 

[4] In 1485 It Was Enacted,  By A Statute Entitled " Of What Credit

And Estate Those Jurors Must Be Which Shall Be Impaneled In The

Sheriff's Turn."

 

"That No Bailiff Nor Other Officer From Henceforth Return Or

Impanel Any Such Person In Any Shire Of England,  To Be Taken Or

Put In Or Upon Any Inquiry In Any Of The Said Turns,  But Such As

Be Of Good Name And Fame,  And Having Lands And Tenements Of

Freehold Within The Same Shires,  To The Yearly Value Of Twenty

Shillings At The Least,  Or Else Lands And Tenements Holden By

Custom Of Manor,  Commonly Called Copy-Hold,  Within The Said

Shires,  To The Yearly Value Of Twenty-Six Shillings Eight Pence

Over All Charges At The Least."   1 Richard Iii.,  Ch. 4. (1483 )

 

In 1486 It Was Enacted,  " That The Justices Of The Peace Of Every

Shire Of This Realm For The Time Being May Take,  By Their

Discretion,  An Inquest,  Whereof Every Man Shall Have Lands And

Tenements To The Yearly Value Of Forty Shillings At The Least,  To

Inquire Of The Concealments Of Others," &C;.,  &C;.   3 Henry Vii,

Ch. 1. (1486.)

 

A Statute Passed In 1494,  In Regard To Jurors In The City Of

London,  Enacts:

 

"That No Person Nor Persons Hereafter Be Impaneled,  Summoned,

Or Sworn In Any Jury Or Inquest In Courts Within The Same City,  (Of

London,) Except He Be Of Lands,  Tenements,  Or Goods And Chattels,

To The Value Of Forty Marks; [5] And That No Person Or Persons

Hereafter Be Impaneled,  Summoned,  Nor Sworn In Any Jury Or

Inquest In Any Court Within The Said City,  For Lands Or Tenements,  Or

Action Personal,  Wherein The Debt Or Damage Amounteth To The Sum

Of Forty Marks,  Or Above,  Except He Be In Lands Tenements,  Goods,

Or Chattels,  To The Value Of One Hundred Marks."   11 Henry Vii.

Ch. 21. (1494.)

 

The Statute 4 Henry Viii,  Ch. 3,  Sec. 4,  (1512) Requires Jurors In

London To Have "Goods To The Value Of One Hundred Marks."

 

In 1494 It Was Enacted That "It Shall Be Lawful To Every Sheriff

Of The Counties Of Southampton,  Surrey.,  And Sussex,  To Impanel

And Summons Twenty-Four Lawful Men Of Such,  Inhabiting Within

The Precinct Of His Or Their Turns,  As Owe Suit,  To The Same Turn,

Chapter 6 (Juries Of The Present Day Illegal) Pg 128

Whereof Every One Hath Lands Or Freehold To The Yearly Value Of

Ten Shillings,  Or Copyhold Lands To The Yearly Value Of Thirteen

Shillings Four Pence,  Above All Charges Within Any Of The Said

Counties,  Or Men Of Less Livelihood,  If There Be Not So Many

There,  Not Withstanding The Statute Of 1 Richard Iii.,  Ch. 4. To

Endure To The Next Parliament."   11 Henry Vii.,  Ch. 24. (1494.)

This Statute Was Continued In Force By 19 Henry Vii.,  Ch. 16

(1503.)

 

In 1531 It Was Enacted,  "That Every Person Or Person Being The

King's Natural Subject Born,  Which Either By The Name Of Citizen,

Or Of A Freeman,  Or Any Other Name,  Doth Enjoy And Use The

Liberties And Privileges Of Any City,  Borough,  Or Town Corporate,

Where He Dwelleth And Maketh His Abode,  Being Worth In Moveable

Goods And Substance To The Clear Value Of Forty Pounds,  Be

Henceforth Admitted In Trials Of Murders And Felonies In Every

Sessions And Gaol Delivery,  To Be Kept And Holden In And For The

Liberty Of Such Cities,  Boroughs,  And Towns Corporate,  Albeit They

Have No Freehold; Any Act,  Statute,  Use,  Custom,  Or Ordinance To

The Contrary Hereof Notwithstanding."   23 Henry Viii.,  Ch. 13.

(1531.)

 

In 1585 It Was Enacted,  "That In All Cases Where Any Jurors To Be

Returned For Trial Of Any Issue Or Issues Joined In Any Of The

Queen's Majesty's Courts Of King's Bench,  Common Pleas,  And The

Exchequer,  Or Before Judices Of Assize,  By The Laws Of This Realm

Now In Force,  Ought To Have Estate Of Freehold In Lands,

Tenements,  Or Hereditaments,  Of The Clear Yearly Value Of Forty

Shillings,  That In Every Such Case The Jurors That Shall Be

Returned From And After The End Of This Present Session Of

Parliament,  Shall Every Of Them Have Estate Of Freehold In Lands,

Tenements,  Or Hereditaments,  To The Clear Yearly Value Of Four

Pounds At The Least."   27 Elizabeth,  Ch. 6. (1585.)

 

In 1664-5 It Was Enacted "That All Jurors (Other Than Strangers

Upon Trials Per Medietatem Linquae) Who Are To Be Returned For The

Trials Of Issues Joined In Any Of (His) Majesty's Courts Of King's

Bench,  Common Pleas,  Or The Exchequer,  Or Before Justices Of

Assize,  Nisi Prius,  Oyer And Terminer,  Gaol Delivery,  Or General

Or Quarter Sessions Of The Peace From And After The Twentieth Day

Of April,  Which Shall Be In The Year Of Our Lord One Thousand Six

Hundred And Sixty-Five,  In Any County Of This Realm Of England,

Shall Every Of Them Then Have,  In Their Own Name,  Or In Trust For

Them,  Within The Same County,  Twenty Pounds,  By The Year,  At

Least,  Above Reprises,  In Their Own Or Their Wives Right,  Of

Freehold Lands,  Or Of Ancient Demesne,  Or Of Rents In Fee,

Fee-Tail,  Or For Life. And That In Every County Within The

Dominion Of Wales Every Such Juror Shall Then Have,  Within The

Some,  Eight Pounds By The Year,  At The Least,  Above Reprises,  In

Manner Aforesaid. All Which Persons Having Such Estate As

Aforesaid Are Hereby Enabled And Made Liable To Be Returned And

Serve As Jurors For The Trial Of Issues Before The Justices

Aforesaid,  Any Law Or Statute To The Contrary In Any Wise

Notwithstanding,"   16 And 17 Charles Ii.,  Ch. 5. (1664-5,)

 

By A Statute Passed In 1692,  Jurors In England Are To Have Landed

Estates Of The Value Of Ten Pounds A Year,  And Jurors In Wales To

Have Similar Estates Of The Realm Of Six Pounds A Year.   4 And 5

William And Mary,  Ch. 24,  Sec. 14,  (1692,)

 

By The Same Statute,  (Sec. 18,) Persons May Be Returned To Serve

Upon The Tales In Any County Of England,  Who Shall Have Within The

Same County,  Five Pounds By The Year,  Above Reprises,  In The

Manner Aforesaid.

 

By St. 3 George Ii.,  Ch. 25,  Sec. 10,  20,  No One Is To Be A Juror

In London,  Who Shall Not Be "An Householder Within The Said City,

And Have Lands,  Tenements,  Or Personal Estate,  To The Value Of One

Hundred Pounds."

 

By Another Statute,  Applicable Only To The County Of Middlesex,  It

Is Enacted,  "That All Leaseholders,  Upon Leases Where The Improved

Rents Or Value Shall Amount To Fifty Pounds Or Upwards Per Annum,

Over And Above All Ground Rents Or Other Reservations Payable By

Virtue Of The Said Leases,  Shall Be Liable And Obliged To Serve

Upon Juries When They Shall Be Legally Summoned For That

Purpose.,"   4 George Ii.,  Ch. 7,  Sec,  3. (1731.)

 

[5] A Mark Was Thirteen Shillings And Four Pence.

 

[6] Suppose These Statutes,  Instead Of Disfranchising All Whose

Freeholds Were Of Less Than The Standard Value Fixed By The

Statutes,  Had Disfranchised All Whose Freeholds Were Of Greater

Value Than The Same Standard   Would Anybody Ever Have Doubted

That Such Legislation Was Inconsistent With The English

Constitution; Or That It Amounted To An Entire Abolition Of The

Trial By Jury? Certainly Not. Yet It Was As Clearly Inconsistent

With The Common Law,  Or The English Constitution,  To Disfranchise

Those Whose Freeholds Fell Below Any Arbitrary Standard Fixed By

The Government,  As It Would Have Been To Disfranchise All Whose

Freeholds Rose Above That Standard.

 

[7] Lingard Says: "These Compurgators Or Jurors * * Were

Sometimes * * Drawn By Lot."   1 Lingard's History Of England, 

P. 300.

 

[8] Chapter 4,  P. 120,  Note.

 

[9] Editor's Note: (The Following Was Not In Spooner's Addition)

With The Ratification Of Article Xix  Of Amendment To The

Constitution For The United States,  August 20,  1920,  Women Were

Fully Enfranchised With All Rights Of Voting And Jury Service In All States

Of The Union.

 

 

 

Chapter 7 (Illegal Judges) Pg 129

It Is A Principle Of Magna Carta,  And Therefore Of The Trial By

Jury,  (For All Parts Of Magna Carta Must Be Construed Together,)

That No Judge Or Other Officer Appointed By The King,  Shall

Preside In Jury Trials,  In Criminal Cases,  Or "Pleas Of The

Crown."

 

This Provision Is Contained In The Great Charters Of Both John

And Henry,  And Is Second In Importance Only To The Provision

Guaranteeing The Trial By Jury,  Of Which It Is Really A Part.

Consequently,  Without The Observance Of This Prohibition,  There

Can Be No Genuine Or Legal   That Is,  Common Law   Trial By Jury.

At The Common Law,  All Officers Who Held Jury Trials,  Whether In

Civil Or Criminal Cases,  Were Chosen By The People. [1]

 

But Previous To Magna Carta,  The Kings Had Adapted The Practice

Of Sending Officers Of Their Own Appointment,  Called Justices,

Into The Counties,  To Hold Jury Trials In Some Cases; And Magna

Carta Authorizes This Practice To Be Continued So Far As It

Relates To Three Kinds Of Civil Actions,  To Wit: "Novel

Disseisin,  Mort De Ancestor,  And Darrein Presentment;" [2] But

Specially Forbids Its Being Extended To Criminal Cases,  Or Pleas

Of The Crown.

 

This Prohibition Is In These Words:

 

"Nullus Vicecomes,  Constabularius,  Coronator,  Vel Alii Balivi

Nostri,  Teneant Placita Coronae Nostrae." (No Sheriff,  Constable,

Coroner,  Or Other Our Bailiffs,  Shall Hold Pleas Of Our Crown.) 

John's Charter,  Ch. 53,  Henry's Ditto,  Ch. 17.

 

Some Persons Seem To Have Supposed That This Was A Prohibition

Merely Upon Officers Bearing The Specific Names Of "Sheriffs,

Constables,  Coroners And Bailiffs,"  To Hold Criminal Trials. But

Such Is Not The Meaning. If It Were,  The Name Could Be Changed,

And The Thing Retained; And Thus The Prohibition Be Evaded. The

Prohibition Applies (As Will Presently Be Seen) To All Officers

Of The King Whatsoever; And It Sets Up A Distinction Between

Officers Of The King,   ("Our Bailiffs,") And Officers Chosen By

The People.

 

The Prohibition Upon The King's Justices Sitting In Criminal

Trials,  Is Included In The Words "Vel Alii Balivi Nostri," (Or

Other Our Bailiffs.) The Word  Bailif Was Anciently A Sort Of

General Name For Judicial Officers And Persons Employed In And

About The Administration Of Justice. In Modern Times Its Use,  As

Applied To The Higher Grades Of Judicial Officers,  Has Been

Superseded By Other Words; And It Therefore Now,  More Generally,

If Not Universally,  Signifies An Executive Or Police Officer,  A

Servant Of Courts,  Rather Than One Whose Functions Are Purely

Judicial.

 

Chapter 7 (Illegal Judges) Pg 130

The Word Is A French Word,  Brought Into England By The Normans.

 

Coke Says,  "Baylife Is A French Word,  And Signifies An Officer

Concerned In The Administration Of Justice Of A Certain Province;

And Because A Sheriff Hath An Office Concerning The

Administration Of Justice Within His County,  Or Bailiwick,

Therefore Be Called His County Baliva Sua,  (His Bailiwick.)

 

"I Have Heard Great Question Made What The True Exposition Of

This Word Balivus Is. In The Statute Of Magna Carta,  Cap. 28,  The

Letter Of That Statute Is,  Nullus Balivus De Eaetero Ponat

Aliqnem Ad Legem Manifestam Nec Ad Juramentum Simplici Loquela

Sua Sine Testibus Fidelibus Ad Hoc Inductis." (No Bailiff From

Henceforth Shall Put Any One To His Open Law,  Nor To An Oath {Of

Self-Exculpation) Upon His Own Simple Accusation,  Or Complaint,

Without Faithful Witnesses Brought In For The Same.) "And Some

Have Said That Balivus In This Statute Signifieth Any Judge; For

The Law Must Be Waged And Made Before The Judge. And This Statute

(Say They) Extends To The Courts Of Common Pleas,  King's Bench,

&C;.,  For They Must Bring With Them Fideles Testes,  (Faithful

Witnesses,) &C;.,  And So Hath Been The Usage To This Day."   1

Coke's Inst.,  168 B.

 

Coke Makes Various References,  In His Margin To Bracton,  Fleta,

And Other Authorities,  Which I Have Not Examined,  But Which,  I

Presume,  Support The Opinion Expressed In This Quotation.

 

Coke Also,  In Another Place,  Under The Head Of The Chapter Just

Cited From Magna Carta,  That "No Bailiff Shall Put Any Man To His

Open Law," &C;.,  Gives The Following Commentary Upon It,  From The

Mirror Of Justices,  From Which It Appears That In The Time Of

Edward I.,  (1272 To 1307,) This Word Balivus Was Understood To

Include All Judicial,  As Well As All Other,  Officers Of The King.

 

The Mirror Says: "The Point Which Forbiddeth That No Bailiff Put

A Freeman To His Oath Without Suit,  Is To Be Understood In This

Manner,    That No Justice,  No Minister Of The King,  Nor Other

Steward,  Nor Bailiff,  Have Power To Make A Freeman Make Oath,  (Of

Self-Exculpation,) Without The King's Command,  [3] Nor Receive

Any Plaint,  Without Witnesses Present Who Testify The Plaint To

Be True."   Mirror Of Justices,  Ch. 5,  Sec. 2,  P. 257.

 

Coke Quotes This Commentary,  (In The Original French,) And Then

Endorses It In These Words:

 

"By This It Appeareth,  That Under This Word Balivus,  In This Act,

Is Comprehended Every Justice,  Minister Of The King,  Steward,  And

Bailiff."   2 Inst.,  44.

 

Coke Also,  In His Commentary Upon This Very Chapter Of Magna

Carta,  That Provides That "No Sheriff; Constable; Coroner,  Or

Other Our Bailiffs,  Shall Hold Pleas Of Our Crown," Expresses The

Opinion That It "Is A General Law," (That Is,  Applicable To All

Officers Of The King,) " By Reason Of The Words Vel Alii Balivi

Chapter 7 (Illegal Judges) Pg 131

Nostri,  (Or Other Our Bailiffs,) Under Which Words Are

Comprehended All Judges Or Justices Of Any Courts Of Justice.

"And He Cites A Decision In The King's Bench,  In The 17th Year Of

Edward I.,  (1289,) As Authority; Which Decision He Calls "A

Notable And Leading Judgment."   2 Inst.,  30   1.

 

And Yet Coke,  In Flat Contradiction Of This Decision,  Which He

Quotes With Such Emphasis And Approbation,  And In Flat

Contradiction Also Of The Definition He Repeatedly Gives Of The

Word Balivus Showing That It Embraced All Ministers Of The King

Whatsoever,  Whether High Or Low,  Judicial Or Executive,

Fabricates An Entirely Gratuitous Interpretation Of This Chapter

Of Magna Carta,  And Pretends That After All It Only Required That

Felonies Should He Tried Before The King's Justices,  On Account

Of Their Superior Iearning; And That It Permitted All Lesser

Offenses To Be Tried Before Inferior Officers,  (Meaning Of Course

The King's Inferior Officers.)   2 Inst.,  30.

 

And Thus This Chapter Of Magna Carta,  Which,  According To His Own

Definition Of The Word Balivus,  Applies To All Officers Of The

King; And Which,  According To The Common And True Definition Of

The Term "Pleas Of The Crown," Applies To All Criminal Cases

Without Distinction,  And Which,  Therefore,  Forbids Any Officer Or

Minister Of The King To Preside In A Jury Trial In Any Criminal

Case Whatsoever,  He Coolly And Gratuitously Interprets Into A

Mere Senseless Provision For Simply Restricting The Discretion Of

The King In Giving Names To His Own Officers Who Should Preside

At The Trials Of Particular Offences; As If The King,  Who Made

And Unmade All His Officers By A Word,  Could Not Defeat The Whole

Object Of The Prohibition,  By Appointing Such Individuals As He

Pleased,  To Try Such Causes As He Pleased,  And Calling Them By

Such Names As He Pleased,  If He Were But Permitted To Appoint And

Name Such Officers At All; And As If It Were Of The Least

Importance What Name An Officer Bore,  Whom The King Might

Appoint To A Particular Duty. [4]

 

Coke Evidently Gives This Interpretation Solely Because,  As He

Was Giving A General Commentary On Magna Carta,  He Was Bound

To

Give Some Interpretation Or Other To Every Chapter Of It; And For

This Chapter He Could Invent,  Or Fabricate,  (For It Is A Sheer

Fabrication,) No Interpretation Better Suited To His Purpose Than

This. It Seems Never To Have Entered His Mind,  (Or If It Did,  He

Intended That It Should Never Enter The Mind Of Anybody Else,)

That The Object Of The Chapter Could Be To Deprive The King Of

The Power Of Putting His Creatures Into Criminal Courts,  To Pack,

Cheat,  And Browbeat Juries,  And Thus Maintain His Authority By

Procuring The Conviction Of Those Who Should Transgress His Laws,

Or Incur His Displeasure.

 

This Example Of Coke Tends To Show How Utterly Blind,  Or How

Utterly Corrupt,  English Judges,  (Dependent Upon The Crown And

The Legislature),  Have Been In Regard To Everything In Magna

Carta,  That Went To Secure The Liberties Of The People,  Or Limit

The Power Of The Government.

 

Chapter 7 (Illegal Judges) Pg 132

Coke's Interpretation Of This Chapter Of Magna Carta Is Of A

Piece With His Absurd And Gratuitous Interpretation Of The Words

"Nec Super Eum Ibimus,  Nec Super Eum Mittemus," Which Was

Pointed

Out In A Former Article,  And By Which He Attempted To Give A

Judicial Power To The King And His Judges,  Where Magna Carta Had

Given It Only To A Jury. It Is Also Of A Piece With His Pretence

That There Was A Difference Between Fine And Amercement,  And That

Fines Might Be Imposed By The King,  And That Juries Were Required

Only For Fixing Amercements.

 

These Are Some Of The Innumerable Frauds By Which The English

People Have Been Cheated Out Of The Trial By Jury.

 

Ex Uno Disce Omnes. From One Judge Learn The Characters Of All.

[6]

 

I Give In The Note Additional And Abundant Authorities For The

Meaning Ascribed To The Word Bailiff. The Importance Of The

Principle Involved Will Be A Sufficient Excuse For Such An

Accumulation Of Authorities As Would Otherwise Be Tedious And

Perhaps Unnecessary. [7]

 

The Foregoing Interpretation Of The Chapter Of Magna Carta Now

Under Discussion,  Is Corroborated By Another Chapter Of Magna

Carta,  Which Specially Provides That The King's Justices Shall

"Go Through Every County" To "Take The Assizes" (Hold Jury

Trials) In Three Kinds Of Civil Actions,  To Wit,  "Novel

Disseisin,  Mort De Ancestor,  And Darrein Presentment;" But Makes

No Mention Whatever Of Their Holding Jury Trials In Criminal Cases,   

An Omission Wholly Unlikely To Be Made,  If It Were Designed

They Should Attend The Trial Of Such Causes. Besides,  The Here

Spoken Of (In John's Charter) Does Not Allow These Justices To

Sit Alone In Jury Trials,  Even In Civilactions; But Provides That

Four Knights,  Chosen By The County,  Shall Sit With Them To Keep

Them Honest.  When The King's Justices  Were Known To Be So

Corrupt And  Servile That The People Would Not Even Trust Them

To Sit Alone,   In Jury Trials,  In Civil Actions,  How Preposterous Is

It To Suppose  That They Would Not Only Suffer Them To Sit,  But To

Sit Alone,  In Criminal Ones.

 

It Is Entirely Incredible That Magna Carta,  Which Makes Such

Careful Provision In Regard To The King's Justices Sitting In

Civil Actions,  Should Make No Provision Whatever As To Their

Sitting In Criminal Trials,  If They Were To Be Allowed To Sit In

Them At All. Yet Magna Carta Has No Provision Whatever On The

Subject. [10]

 

But What Would Appear To Make This Matter Ahsolute1y Certain Is,

That Unless The Prohibition That "No Bailiff,  &C;.,  Of Ours Shall

Hold Pleas Of Our Crown," Apply To All Officers Of The King,

Justices As Well As Others,  It Would Be Wholly Nugatory For Any

Chapter 7 (Illegal Judges) Pg 133

Practical Or Useful Purpose,  Because The Prohibition Could Be

Evaded By The King,  At Any Time,  By Simply Changing The Titles Of

His Officers. Instead Of Calling Them "Sheriffs,  Coroners,

Constables And Bailiffs," He Could Call Them "Justices," Or

Anything Else He Pleased; And This Prohibition,  So Important To

The Liberty Of The People,  Would Then Be Entirely Defeated. The

King Also Could Make And Unmake "Justices" At His Pleasure; And

If He Could Appoint Any Officers Whatever To Preside Over Juries

In Criminal Trials,  He Could Appoint Any Tool That He Might At

Any Time Find Adapted To His Purpose. It Was As Easy To Make

Justices Of Jeffreys And Scroggs,  As Of Any Other Material; And

To Have Prohibited All The King's Officers,  Except His Justices,

From Presiding In Criminal Trials,  Would Therefore Have Been Mere

Fool's Play.

 

We Can All Perhaps Form Some Idea,  Though Few Of Us Will Be

Likely To Form Any Adequate Idea,  Of What A Different Thing The

Trial By Jury Would Have Been In Practice,  And Of What Would Have

Been The Difference To The Liberties Of England,  For Five Hundred

Years Last Past,  Had This Prohibition Of Magna Carta,  Upon The

King's Officers Sitting In The Trial Of Criminal Cases,  Been

Observed.

 

The Principle Of This Chapter Of Magna Carta,  As Applicable To

The Governments Of The United States Of America,  Forbids That Any

Officer Appointed Either By The Executive Or Legislative Power,

Or Dependent Upon Them For Their Salaries,  Or Responsible To Them

By Impeachment,  Should Preside Over A Jury In Criminal Trials. To

Have The Trial A Legal (That Is,  A Common Law) And True Trial By

Jury,  The Presiding Officers Must Be Chosen By The People,  And Be

Entirely Free From All Dependence Upon,  And All Accountability

To,  The Executive And Legislative Branches Of The Government.

[12]

 

[1] The Proofs Of This Principle Of The Common Law Have Already

Been Given On Page 120,  Note.

 

There Is Much Confusion And Contradiction Among Authors As To

The Manner In Which Sheriffs And Other Officers Were Appointed; Some

Maintaining That They Were Appointed By The King,  Others That

They Were Elected By The People. I Imagine That Both These

Opinions Are Correct,  And That Several Of The King's Officers

Bore The Same Official Names As Those Chosen By The People; And

That This Is The Cause Of The Confusion That Has Arisen On The

Subject.

 

It Seems To Be A Perfectly Well Established Fact That,  At Common

Law,  Several Magistrates,  Bearing The Names Of Aldermen,  Sheriff,

Stewards,  Coroners And Bailiffs,  Were Chosen By The People; And

Yet It Appears,  From Magna Carta Itself,  That Some Of The King's

Officers (Of Whom He Must Have Had Many) Were Also Called

"Sheriffs,  Constables,  Coroners,  And Bailiffs."

 

But Magna Carta,  In Various Instances,  Speaks Of Sheriffs And

Chapter 7 (Illegal Judges) Pg 134

Bailiffs As "Our Sheriff's And Bailiffs;" Thus Apparently

Intending To Recognize The Distinction Between Officers Of The

King,  Bearing Those Names,  And Other Officers,  Bearing The Same

Official Names,  But Chosen By The People. Thus It Says That "No

Sheriff Or Bailiff Of Ours,  Or Any Other (Officer),  Shall Take

Horses Or Carts Of Any Freeman For Carriage,  Unless With The

Consent Of The Freeman Himself."   John's Charter,  Ch. 36.

 

In A Kingdom Subdivided Into So Many Counties,  Hundreds,

Tithings,  Manors,  Cities And Boroughs,  Each Having A Judicial Or

Police Organization Of Its Own,  It Is Evident That Many Of The

Officers Must Have Been Chosen By The People,  Else The Government

Could Not Have Mainlined Its Popular Character. On The Other

Hand,  It Is Evident That The King,  The Executive Power Of The

Nation,  Must Have Had Large Numbers Of Officers Of His Own In

Every Part Of The Kingdom. And It Is Perfectly Natural That These

Different Sets Of Officers Should,  In Many Instances,  Bear The

Same Official Names; And,  Consequently That The King,  When

Speaking Of His Own Officers,  As Distinguished,  From Those Chosen

By The People,  Should Call Them "Our Sheriffs,  Bailiffs," &C;,  As

He Does In Magna Carta.

 

I Apprehend That Inattention To These Considerations Has Been The

Cause Of All The Confusion Of Ideas That Has Arisen On This

Subject,   A Confusion Very Evident In The Following Paragraph

From Dunham,  Which May Be Given As An Illustration Of That Which

Is Exhibited By Others On The Same Points.

 

"Subordinate To The Ealdormen Were The Gerefas,  The Sheriffs,  Or

Reeves,  Of Whom There Were Several In Every Shire,  Or County.

There Was One In Every Borough,  As A Judge. There Was One At

Every Gate,  Who Witnessed Purchases Outside The Walls; And There

Was One,  Higher Than Either,   The High Sheriff,   Who Was Probably

The Reeve Of The Shire. This Last Appears To Have Been Appointed

By The King. Their Functions Were To Execute The Decrees Of The

King,  Or Ealdormen,  To Arrest Prisoners,  To Require Bail For

Their Appearance At The Sessions,  To Collect Fines Or Penalties

Levied By The Court Of The Shire,  To Preserve The Public Peace,

And To Preside In A Subordinate Tribunal Of Their Own." 

Durham's Middle Ages,  Sec. 2,  B. 2,  Ch. 1.  - 57 Lardner's Cab.

Cyc.,  P 41.

 

The Confusion Of Duties Attributed To These Officers Indicates

Clearly Enough That Different Officers,  Bearing The Same Official

Names,  Must Have Had Different Duties,  And Have Derived Their

Authority From Different Sources,  To Wit,  The King,  And The

People.

 

[2] Darrein Presentement  Was An Inquest To Discover Who

Presented The Last Person To A Church; Mort De Ancestor,  Whether

The Last Possessor Was Seized Of Land In Demesne Of His Own Fee;

And Novel Disseisin,  Whether The Claimant Had Been Unjustly

Disseized Of His Freehold.

 

Chapter 7 (Illegal Judges) Pg 135

[3] He Has No Power To Do It,  Either With,  Or Without,  The King's

Command. The Prohibition Is Absolute,  Containing No Such

Qualification As Is Here Interpolated,  Viz.,  "Without The King's

Command." If It Could Be Done With The King's Command,  The King

Would Be Invested With Arbitrary Power In The Matter.

 

[4] The Absurdity Of This Doctrine Of Coke Is Made More Apparent

By The Fact That,  At That Time,  The "Justices" And Other Persons

Appointed By The King To Hold Courts Were Not Only Dependent Upon

The King For Their Offices,  And Removable At His Pleasure,  But

That The Usual Custom Was,  Not To Appoint Them With Any View To

Permanency,  But Only To Give Them Special Commissions For Trying

A Single Cause,  Or For Holding A Single Term Of A Court,  Or For

Making A Single Circuit; Which,  Being Done,  Their Commissions

Expired. The King,  Therefore,  Could,  And Undoubtedly Did,  Appoint

Any Individual He Pleased,  To Try Any Cause He Pleased,  With A

Special View To The Verdicts He Desired To Obtain In The

Particular Cases.

 

This Custom Of Commissioning Particular Persons To Hold Jury

Trials,  In Criminal Cases,  (And Probably Also In Civil Ones,) Was

Of Course A Usurpation Upon The Common Law,  But Had Been

Practised More Or Less From The Time Of William The Conqueror.

Palgrave Says:

 

"The Frequent Absence Of William From His Insular Dominions

Occasioned Another Mode Of Administration,  Which Ultimately

Produced Still Greater Changes In The Law. It Was The Practice Of

Appointing Justiciars To Represent The King's Person,  To Hold His

Court,  To Decide His Pleas,  To Dispense Justice On His Behalf,  To

Command The Military Levies,  And To Act As Conservators Of The

Peace In The King's Name. [5] .. The Justices Who Were Assigned

In The Name Of The Sovereign,  And Whose Powers Were Revocable At

His Pleasure,  Derived Their Authority Merely From Their Grant...

Some Of Those Judges Were Usually Deputed For The Purpose Of

Relieving The King From The Burden Of His Judicial Functions...

The Number As Well As The Variety Of Names Of The Justices

Appearing In The Early Chirographs Of 'Concords,' Leave Reason

For Doubting Whether,  Anterior To The Reign Of Henry Iii.,  (1216

To 1272,) A Court,  Whose Members Were Changing At Almost Every

Session,  Can Be Said To Have Been Permanently Constituted. It

Seems More Probable That The Individuals Who Composed The

Tribunal Were Selected As Suited The Pleasure Of The Sovereign,

And The Convenience Of The Clerks And Barons; And The History Of

Our Legal Administration Will Be Much Simplified,  If We Consider

All Those Courts Which Were Afterwards Denominated The

Exchequer,  The King's Bench,  The Common Pleas,  And The Chancery, 

As Being Originally Committees,  Selected By The King When Occasion

Required,  Out Of A Large Body,  For The Despatch Of Peculiar

Branches Of Business,  And Which Committees,  By Degrees,  Assumed

An Independent And Permanent Existence... Justices Itinerant,

Who,  Despatched Throughout The Land,  Decided The ' Pleas Of The

Crown,' May Be Obscurely Traced In The Reign Of The Conqueror;

Not,  Perhaps,  Appointed With Much Regularity,  But Despatched Upon

Chapter 7 (Illegal Judges) Pg 136

Peculiar Occasions And Emergencies."   1 Palgrave's Rise And

Progress,  &C;.,  P. 289 To 293.

 

The Following Statute,  Passed In 1354,  (139 Years After Magna

Carta,) Shows That Even After This Usurpation Of Appointing

"Justices " Of His Own,  To Try Criminal Cases,  Had Probably

Become Somewhat Established In Practice,  In Defiance Of Magna

Carta,  The King Was In The Habit Of Granting Special Commissions

To Still Other Persons,  (Especially To Sheriffs,    His Sheriffs,

No Doubt,) To Try Particular Cases:

 

"Because That The People Of The Realm Have Suffered Many Evils

And Mischiefs,  For That Sheriffs Of Divers Counties,  By Virtue Of

Commissions And General Writs Granted To Them At Their Own Suit,

For Their Singular Profit To Gain Of The People,  Have Made And

Taken Divers Inquests To Cause To Indict The People At Their

Will,  And Have Taken Fine And Ransom Of Them To Their Own Use,

And Have Delivered Them; Whereas Such Persons Indicted Were Not

Brought Before The King's Justices To Have Their Deliverance,  It

Is Accorded And Established,  For To Eschew All Such Evils And

Mischiefs,  That Such Commissions And Writs Before This Time Made

Shall Be Utterly Repealed,  And That From Henceforth No Such

Commissions Shall Be Granted."   St. 28 Edward Iii.,  Ch. 9,

(1354.)

 

How Silly To Suppose That The Illegality Of These Commissions To

Try Criminal Eases,  Could Have Been Avoided By Simply Granting

Them To Persons Under The Title Of "Justices," Instead Of

Granting Them To "Sheriffs." The Statute Was Evidently A Cheat,

Or At Least Designed As Such,  Inasmuch As It Virtually Asserts

The Right Of The King To Appoint His Tools,  Under The Name Of

"Justices," To Try Criminal Cases,  While It Disavows His Right To

Appoint Them Under The Name Of "Sheriffs."

 

Millar Says: "When The King's Bench Came To Have Its Usual

Residence At Westminster,  The Sovereign Was Induced To Grant

Special Commissions,  For Trying Particular Crimes,  In Such Parts

Of The Country As Were Found Most Convenient; And This Practice

Was Gradually Modeled Into A Regular Appointment Of Certain

Commissioners,  Empowered,  At Stated Seasons,  To Perform Circuits

Over The Kingdom,  And To Hold Courts In Particular Towns,  For The

Trial Of All Sorts Of Crimes. These Judges Of The Circuit,

However,  Never Obtained An Ordinary Jurisdiction,  But Continued,

On Every Occasion,  To Derive Their Authority From Two Special

Commissions: That Of Oyer And Terminer,  By Which They Were

Appointed To Hear And Determine All Treasons,  Felonies And

Misdemeanors,  Within Certain Districts; And That Of Gaol

Delivery,  By Which They Were Directed To Try Every Prisoner

Confined In The Gaols Of The Several Towns Falling Under Their

Inspection."   Millar's Hist. View Of Eng. Gov.,  Vol. 2,  Ch. 7,

P. 282.

 

The Following Extract From Gilbert Shows To What Lengths Of

Usurpation The Kings Would Sometimes Go,  In Their Attempts To Get

Chapter 7 (Illegal Judges) Pg 137

The Judicial Power Out Of The Hands Of The People,  And Entrust It

To Instruments Of Their Own Choosing:

 

"From The Time Of The Saxons," (That Is,  From The Commencement

Of The Reign Of William The Conqueror,) "Till The Reign Of Edward

The First,  (1272 To 1307,) The Several County Courts And Sheriffs

Courts Did Decline In Their Interest And Authority. The Methods

By Which They Were Broken Were Two-Fold. First,  By Granting

Commissions To The Sheriffs By Writ Of Justicies,  Whereby The

Sheriff Had A Particular Jurisdiction Granted Him To Be Judge Of

A Particular Cause,  Independent Of The Suitors Of The County

Court," (That Is,  Without A Jury;) "And These Commissions Were

After The Norman Form,  By Which (According To Which) All Power Of

Judicature Was Immediately Derived From The King."   Gilbert On

The Court Of Chancery,  P. L.

 

The Several Authorities Now Given Show That It Was The Custom Of

The Norman Kings,  Not Only To Appoint Persons To Sit As Judges In

Jury Trials,  In Criminal Cases,  But That They Also Commissioned

Individuals To Sit In Singular And Particular Eases,  As Occasion

Required; And That They Therefore Readily Could,  And Naturally

Would,  And Therefore Undoubtedly Did,  Commission Individuals

With A Special View To Their Adaptation Or Capacity To Procure Such

Judgments As The Kings Desired.

 

The Extract From Gilbert Suggests Also The Usurpation Of The

Norman Kings,  In Their Assumption That They,  (And Not The People,

As By The Common Law,) Were The Fountains Of Justice. It Was Only

By Virtue Of This Illegal Assumption That They Could Claim To

Appoint Their Tools To Hold Courts.

 

All These Things Show How Perfectly Lawless And Arbitrary The

Kings Were,  Both Before And After Magna Carta,  And How Necessary

To Liberty Was The Principle Of Magna Carta And The Common Law,

That No Person Appointed By The King Should Hold Jury Trials In

Criminal Cases.

 

[5] In This Extract,  Palgrave Seems To Assume That The King

Himself Had A Right To Sit As Judge,  In Jury Trials,  In The

County Courts,  In Both Civil And Criminal Cases. I Apprehend He

Had No Such Power At The Common Law,  But Only To Sit In The Trial

Of Appeals,  And In The Trial Of Peers,  And Of Civil Suits In

Which Peers Were Parties,  And Possibly In The Courts Of Ancient

Demesne.

 

[6] The Opinions And Decisions Of Judges And Courts Are

Undeserving Of The Least Reliance,  (Beyond The Intrinsic Merit Of

The Arguments Offered To Sustain Them,) And Are Unworthy Even To

Be Quoted As Evidence Of The Law,  When Those Opinions Or

Decisions Are Favorable To The Power Of The Government,  Or

Unfavorable To The Liberties Of The People. The Only Reasons That

Their Opinions,  When In Favor Of Liberty,  Are Entitled To Any

Confidence,  Are,  First,  That All Presumptions Of Law Are In Favor

Of Liberty; And,  Second,  That The Admissions Of All Men,  The

Chapter 7 (Illegal Judges) Pg 138

Innocent And The Criminal Alike,  When Made Against Their Own

Interests,  Are Entitled To Be Received As True,  Because It Is

Contrary To Human Nature For A Man To Confess Anything But Truth

Against Himself.

 

More Solemn Farces,  Or More Gross Impostures,  Were Never

Practised Upon Mankind,  Than Are All,  Or Very Nearly All,  Those

Oracular Responses By Which Courts Assume To Determine That

Certain Statutes,  In Restraint Of Individual Liberty,  Are Within

The Constitutional Power Of The Government,  And Are Therefore

Valid And Binding Upon The People.

 

The Reason Why These Courts Are So Intensely Servile And Corrupt,

Is,  That They Are Not Only Parts Of,  But The Veriest Creatures

Of,  The Very Governments Whose Oppressions They Are Thus Seeking

To Uphold. They Receive Their Offices And Salaries From,  And Are

Impeachable And Removable By,  The Very Governments Upon Whose

Acts They Affect To Sit In Judgment. Of Course,  No One With His

Eyes Open Ever Places Himself In A Position So Incompatible With

The Liberty Of Declaring His Honest Opinion,  Unless He Do It With

The Intention Of Becoming A Mere Instrument In The Hands Of The

Government For The Execution Of All Its Oppressions.

 

As Proof Of This,  Look At The Judicial History Of England For The

Last Five Hundred Years,  And Of America From Its Settlement. In

All That Time (So Far As I Know,  Or Presume) No Bench Of Judges,

(Probably Not Even Any Single Judge,) Dependent Upon The

Legislature That Passed The Statute,  Has Ever Declared A Single

Penal Statute Invalid,  On Account Of Its Being In Conflict Either

With The Common Law,  Which The Judges In England Have Been

Sworn To Preserve,  Or With The Written Constitutions,  (Recognizing

Men's Natural Rights,) Which The American Judges Were Under Oath

To Maintain. Every Oppression,  Every Atrocity Even,  That Has Ever

Been Enacted In Either Country,  By The Legislative Power,  In The

Shape Of A Criminal Law,  (Or,  Indeed,  In Almost Any Other Shape,)

Has Been As Sure Of A Sanction From The Judiciary That Was

Dependent Upon,  And Impeachable By,  The Legislature That Enacted

The Law,  As If There Were A Physical Necessity That The

Legislative Enactment And The Judicial Sanction Should Go

Together. Practically Speaking,  The Sum Of Their Decisions,  All

And Singular,  Has Been,  That There Are No Limits To The Power Of

The Government,  And That The People Have No Rights Except What

The Government Pleases To Allow To Them.

 

It Is Extreme Folly For A People To Allow Such Dependent,

Servile,  And Perjured Creatures To Sit Either In Civil Or

Criminal Trials; But To Allow Them To Sit In Criminal Trials,  And

Judge Of The People's Liberties,  Is Not Merely Fatuity,    It Is

Suicide.

 

[7] Coke,  Speaking Of The Word Bailiffs,  As Used In The Statute

Of 1 Westminster,  Ch. 35,  (1275,) Says:

 

"Here Bailiffs Are Taken For The Judges Of The Court,  As

Chapter 7 (Illegal Judges) Pg 139

Manifestly Appeareth Hereby."   2 Inst.,  229.

 

Coke Also Says,  ' It Is A Maxim In Law,  Aliguis Non Debet Esse

Judex In Propria Causa,  (No One Ought To Be Judge In His Own

Cause;) And Therefore A Fine Levied Before The Baylifes Of Salopwas

Reversed,  Because One Of The Baylifes Was Party To The Fine,

Quia Non Potest Esse Judex Et Pars," (Because One Cannot Be Judge

And Party.)   1 Inst.,  141 A.

 

In The Statute Of Gloucester,  Ch. 11 And 12,  (1278,) "The Mayor

And Bailiffs Of London (Undoubtedly Chosen By The People,  Or At

Any Rate Not Appointed By The King) Are Manifestly Spoken Of As

Judges,  Or Magistrates,  Holding Jury Trials,  As Follows:

 

Ch. Ii. "It Is Provided,  Also,  That If Any Man Lease His Tenement

In The City Of London,  For A Term Of Years,  And He To Whom The

Freehold Belongeth Causeth Himself To Be Impleaded By Collusion,

And Maketh Default After Default,  Or Cometh Into Court And Giveth

It Up,  For To Make The Termor (Lessee) Lose His Term,  (Lease,)

And The Demandant Hath His Suit,  So That The Termor May Recover

By Writ Of Covenant; The Mayor And Bailiffs May Inquire By A Good

Inquest,  (Jury,) In The Presence Of The Termor And The Demandant,

Whether The Demandant Moved His Plea Upon Good Right That He

Had,

Or By Collusion,  Or Fraud,  To Make The Termor Lose His Term; And

If It Be Found By The Inquest (Jury) That The Demandant Moved His

Plea Upon Good Right That He Had,  The Judgment Shall Be Given

Forthwith; And If It Be Found By The Inquest (Jury) That He

Impleaded Him (Self ) By Fraud,  To Put The Termor From His Term,

Then Shall The Termor Enjoy His Term,  And The Execution Of

Judgment For The Demandant Shall Be Suspended Until The Term Be

Expired."   4 Edward I.,  Ch. 11,  (1278.)

 

Coke,  In His Commentary On This Chapter,  Calls This Court Of "The

Mayor And Bailiffs" Of London,  " The Court Of The Hustings,  The

Greatest And Highest Court In London;" And Adds,  "Other Cities

Have The Like Court,  And So Called,  As York,  Lincoln,  Winchester,

&E;. Here The City Of London Is Named; But It Appeareth By That

Which Hath Been Said Out Of Fleta,  That This Act Extends To Such

Cities And Boroughs Privileged,    That Is,  Such As Have Such

Privilege To Hold Plea As London Hath."   2 Inst.,  322.

 

The 12th Chapter Of The Same Statute Is In The Following Words,

Which Plainly Recognize The Fact That " The Mayor And Bailiffs Of

London" Are Judicial Officers Holding Courts In London.

 

"It Is Provided,  Also,  That If A Man,  Impleaded For A Tenement In

The Same City,  (London,) Doth Vouch A Foreigner To Warranty,  That

He Shall Come Into The Chancery,  And Have A Writ To Summon His

Warrantor At A Certain Day Before The Justices Of The Beach,  And

Another Writ To The Mayor And Bailiff Of London,  That They Shall

Surcease (Suspend Proceedings) In The Matter That Is Before Them

By Writ,  Until The Plea Of The Warrantee Be Determined Before The

Justices Of The Bench; And When The Plea At The Bench Shall Be

Chapter 7 (Illegal Judges) Pg 140

Determined,  Then Shall He That Is Vouched Be Commanded To Go Into

The City," (That Is,  Before "The Mayor And Bailiffs " Court,) "To

Answer Unto The Chief Plea; And A Writ Shall Be Awarded At The

Suit Of The Demandant By The Justices Unto The Mayor And

Bailiffs,  That They Shall Proceed In The Plea," &C;.   6 Edward

I.,  Ch. 12,  (1278.)

 

Coke,  In His Commentary On This Chapter,  Also Speaks Repeatedly

Of "The Mayor And Bailiffs" As Judges Holding Courts,  And Also

Speaks Of This Chapter As Applicable Not Only To "The Citie Of

London,  Specially Named For The Cause Aforesaid,  But Extended By

Equity To All Other Privileged Places," (That Is,  Privileged To

Have A Court Of "Mayor And Bailiffs,") "Where Foreign Voucher Is

Made,  As To Chester,  Durham,  Salop," &E;.   2 Inst.,  325   7.

 

Bailie.   In Scotch Law,  A Municipal Magistrate,  Corresponding

With The English Alderman.[8]   Burrill's Law Dictionary.

 

Bailliffe  Baillif. Fr. A Bailiff: A Ministerial Officer With

Duties Similar To Those Of A Sheriff. * * The Judge Of A Court. A

Municipal Magistrate,  &C;.   Burrill's Law Dict.

 

Bailiff - The Word Bailiff Is Of Norman Origin,  And Was Applied

In England,  At An Early Period,  (After The Example,  It Is Said,

Of The French,) To The Chief Magistrates Of Counties,  Or Shires,

Such As The Alderman,  The Reeve,  Or Sheriff,  And Also Of Inferior

Jurisdictions,  Such As Hundreds And Wapentakes.   Spelman,  Voc.

Balivus; 1 Bl. Com.,344. See Bailli,  Ballivus. The Latin Ballivus

Occurs,  Indeed,  In The Laws Of Edward The Confessor,  But Spelman

Thinks It Was Introduced By A Later Hand. Balliva (Bailiwick) Was

The Word Formed From Ballivus,  To Denote The Extent Of Territory

Comprised Within A Bailiff's Jurisdiction; And Bailiwick Is Still

Retained In Writs And Other Proceedings,  As The Name Of A

Sheriff's County.   1 Bl. Com.,  344. See Balliva. The Office Of

Bailiff Was At First Strictly,  Though Not Exclusively,  A Judicial

One. In France,  The Word Had The Sense Of What Spelman Calls

Justitia Tutelaris. Ballivus Occurs Frequently In The Regiam

Majestatem,  In The Sense Of A Judge.   Spelman. In Its Sense Of A

Deputy,  It Was Formerly Applied,  In England,  To Those Officers

Who,  By Virtue Of A Deputation,  Either From The Sheriff Or The

Lords Of Private Jurisdictions,  Exercised Within The Hundred,  Or

Whatever Might Be The Limits Of Their Bailiwick,  Certain Judicial

And Ministerial Functions. With The Disuse Of Private And Local

Jurisdictions,  The Meaning Of The Term Became Commonly Restricted

To Such Persons As Were Deputed By The Sheriff To Assist Him In

The Merely Ministerial Portion Of His Duty; Such As The Summoning

Of Juries,  And The Execution Of Writs.   Brande.. The Word

Bailiff Is Also Applied In England To The Chief Magistrates Of

Certain Towns And Jurisdictions,  To The Keepers Of Castles,

Forests And Other Places,  And To The Stewards Or Agents Of Lords

Of Manors.   Burrill's Law Dict.

 

"Bailiff,  (From The Lat. Ballivus; Fr. Baillif,  I. E.,  Praefectus

Provinciae,) Signifies An Officer Appointed For The

Chapter 7 (Illegal Judges) Pg 141

Administration Of Justice Within A Certain District. The Office,

As Well As The Name,  Appears To Have Been Derived From The

French," &C;.   Brewster's Encyclopedia.

 

Millar Says,  "The French Monarchs,  About This Period,  Were Not

Content With The Power Of Receiving Appeals From The Several

Courts Of Their Barons. An Expedient Was Devised Of Sending Royal

Bailiffs Into Different Parts Of The Kingdom,  With A Commission

To Take Cognizance Of All Those Causes In Which The Sovereign Was

Interested,  And In Reality For The Purpose Of Abridging And

Limiting The Subordinate Jurisdiction Of The Neighboring Feudal

Superiors. By An Edict Of Phillip Augustus,  In The Year 1190,

Those Bailiffs Were Appointed In All The Principal Towns Of The

Kingdom."   Millar's Hist. View Of The Eng. Gov.,  Vol. Ii.,  Ch.

8,  P. 126.

 

"Bailiff- Office.   Magistrates Who Formerly Administered Justice

In The Parliaments Or Courts Of France,  Answering To The English

Sheriffs,  As Mentioned By Bracton."   Bouvier's Law Dict.

 

"There Be Several Officers Called Bailiffs,  Whose Offices And

Employments Seem Quite Different From Each Other... The Chief

Magistrate,  In Divers Ancient Corporations,  Are Called Bailiffs,

As In Ipswich,  Yarmouth,  Colchester,  &C;. There Are,  Likewise,

Officers Of The Forest,  Who Are Termed Bailiffs."   1 Bacon's

Abridgment,  498   9.

 

" Bailiff Signifies A Keeper Or Superintendent,  And Is Directly

Derived From The French Word Bailli,  Which Appears To Come From

The Word Balivus,  And That From Bagalus,  A Latin Word Signifying

Generally A Governor,  Tutor,  Or Superintendent... The French Word

Bailli Is Thus Explained By Richelet,  (Dictionaire,  &E;.:)

Bailli.  He Who In A Province Has The Superintendence Of Justice,

Who Is The Ordinary Judge Of The Nobles,  Who Is Their Head For

The Ban And Arriere Ban,  [9] And Who Maintains The Right And

Property Of Others Against Those Who Attack Them... All The

Various Officers Who Are Called By This Name,  Though Differing As

To The Nature Of Their Employments,  Seem To Have Some Kind Of

Superintendence Intrusted To Them By Their Superior."   Political

Dictionary.

 

" Bailiff,  Balivus. From The French Word Bayliff,  That Is,

Praefectus Provinciae,  And As The Name,  So The Office Itself Was

Answerable To That Of France,  Where There Were Eight Parliaments,

Which Were High Courts From Whence There Lay No Appeal,  And

Within The Precincts Of The Several Parts Of That Kingdom Which

Belonged To Each Parliament,  There Were Several Provinces To

Which Justice Was Administered By Certain Officers Called

Bailiffs; And In England We Have Several Counties In Which

Justice Hath Been,  And Still Is,  In Small Suits,  Administered To

The Inhabitants By The Officer Whom We Now Call Sheriff,  Or

Viscount; (One Of Which Names Descends From The Saxons,  The

Other From The Normans.) And,  Though The Sheriff Is Not Called

Bailiff,  Yet It Was Probable That Was One Of His Names Also,  Because 

Chapter 7 (Illegal Judges) Pg 142

The County Is Often Called Balliva; As In The Return Of A Writ,  Where

The Person Is Not Arrested,  The Sheriff Saith,  Infra-Nominatus,

A. B. Non Est Inventus In Balliva Mea,  &C;.; (The Within Named A.

B. Is Not Found In My Bailiwick,  &C;.) And In The Statute Of

Magna Carta,  Ch. 28,  And 14 Ed. 8,  Ch. 9,  The Word Bailiff Seems

To Comprise As Well Sheriffs,  As Bailiffs Of Hundreds.

 

Bailies,  In Scotland,  Are Magistrates Of Burghs,  Possessed Of

Certain Jurisdictions,  Having The Same Power Within Their

Territory As Sheriffs In The County.

 

As England Is Divided Into Counties,  So Every County Is Divided

Into Hundreds; Within Which,  In Ancient Times,  The People Had

Justice Administered To Them By The Several Officers Of Every

Hundred,  Which Were The Bailiffs. And It Appears By Bracton,

(Lib. 3,  Tract. 2,  Ch. 34,) That Bailiffs Of Hundreds Might

Anciently Hold Plea Of Appeal And Approvers; But Since That Time

The Hundred Courts,  Except Certain Franchises,  Are Swallowed In

The County Courts; And Now The Bailiff's Name And Office Is Grown

Into Contempt,  They Being Generally Officers To Serve Writs,

&C;.,  Within Their Liberties; Though,  In Other Respects,  The Name

Is Still In Good Esteem,  For The Chief Magistrates In Divers

Towns Are Called Bailiffs; And Sometimes The Persons To Whom The

King's Castles Are Committed Are Termed Bailiffs,  As The Bailiffof

Dover Castle,  &C;.,

 

"Of The Ordinary Bailiffs There Are Several Sorts,  Viz.,  Bailiffsof

Liberties; Sheriffs' Bailiffs; Bailiffs Of Lords Of Manors; Bailiffs Of

Husbandry,  &C;.

 

"Bailiffs Of Liberties Or Franchises Are To Be Sworn To Take

Distresses,  Truly Impanel Jurors,  Make Returns By Indenture

Between Them And Sheriffs,  &C;.

 

"Bailiffs Of Courts Baron Summon Those Courts,  And Execute The

Process Thereof. " Besides These,  There Are Also Bailiffs Of The

Forest... "  Jacob's Law Dict. Tomlin's Do.

 

"Bailiwick,  Balliva,    Is Not Only Taken For The County,  But

Signifies Generally That Liberty Which Is Exempted From The

Sheriff Of The County,  Over Which The Lord Of The Liberty

Appointeth A Bailiff,  With Such Powers Within His Precinct As An

Under-Sheriff Exerciseth Under The Sheriff Of The County; Such As

The Bailiff Of Westminster."   Jacob's Law Dict. Tomlin's Do.

 

"A Bailiff Of A Leet,  Court-Baron,  Manor,  Balivus Letae,  Baronis,

Manerii.   He Is One That Is Appointed By The Lord,  Or His

Steward,  Within Every Manor,  To Do Such Offices As Appertain

Thereunto,  As To Summon The Court,  Warn The Tenants And Resiants;

Also,  To Summon The Leet And Homage,  Levy Fines,  And Make

Distresses,  &C;.,  Of Which You May Read At Large In Kitchen's

Court-Leet And Court-Baron."   A Law Dictionary,  Anonymous,  (In

Suffolk Law Library.)

Chapter 7 (Illegal Judges) Pg 143

Bailliff   In England An Officer Appointed By The Sheriff.

Bailiff's Are Either Special,  And Appointed,  For Their

Adroitness,  To Arrest Persons; Or Bailiffs Of Hundreds,  Who

Collect Fines,  Summon Juries,  Attend The Assizes,  And Execute

Writs And Processes,  The Sheriff In England Is The King's

Bailiff. 

 

"The Office Of Bailiff Formerly Was High And Honorable In

England,  And Officers Under That Title On The Continent Are Still

Invested With Important Functions."   Webster.

 

"Bailli,  (Scotland.)   An Alderman; A Magistrate Who Is Second In

Rank In A Royal Burgh."   Worcester.

 

"Baili,  Or Bailiff.   (Sorte D'officier De Justice.) A Bailiff; A

Sort Of Magistrate."   Boyer's French Dict.

 

"By Some Opinions,  A Bailiff,  In Magna Carta,  Ch. 28,  Signifies

Any Judge."   Cunningham's Law Dict.

 

"Bailiff.   In The Court Of The Greek Emperors There Was A Grand

Bajulos,  First Tutor Of The Emperor's Children. The

Superintendent Of Foreign Merchants Seems Also To Have Been

Called Bajulos; And,  As He Was Appointed By The Venetians,  This

Title (Balio) Was Transferred To The Venetian Ambassador. From

Greece,  The Official Bajulos (Ballivus,  Bailli,  In France;

Bailiff,  In England,) Was Introduced Into The South Of Europe,

And Denoted A Superintendent; Hence The Eight Ballivi Of The

Knights Of St. John,  Which Constitute Its Supreme Council. In

France,  The Royal Bailiffs Were Commanders Of The Militia,

Administrators Or Stewards Of The Domains,  And Judges Of Their

Districts. In The Course Of Time,  Only The First Duty Remained To

The Bailiff; Hence He Was Bailli D'epee,  And Laws Were

Administered In His Name By A Lawyer,  As His Deputy,  Lieutenant

De Robe. The Seigniories,  With Which High Courts Were Connected,

Employed Bailiffs,  Who Thus Constituted,  Almost Everywhere,  The

Lowest Order Of Judges. From The Courts Of The Nobility,  The

Appellation Passed To The Royal Courts; From Thence To The

Parliaments. In The Greater Bailiwicks Of Cities Of Importance,

Henry Ii. Established A Collegial Constitution Under The Name Of

Presidial Courts... The Name Of Bailiff Was Introduced Into

England With William I. The Counties Were Also Called Bailiwicks,

(Bailivae,) While The Subdivisions Were Called Hundreds,  But,  As

The Courts Of The Hundreds Have Long Since Ceased,  The English

Bailiffs Are Only A Kind Of Subordinate Officers Of Justice,  Like

The French Huissiers. These Correspond Very Nearly To The

Officers Called Constables In The United States. Every Sheriff

Has Someof Them Under Him,  For Whom He Is Answerable. In Some

Cities The Highest Municipal Officer Yet Bears This Name,  As The

High Bailiff Of Westminster. In London,  The Lord Mayor Is At The

Same Time Bailiff; (Which Title He Bore Before The Present Became

Usual,) And Administers,  In This Quality,  The Criminal

Jurisdiction Of The City,  In The Court Of Old Bailey,  Where There

Are,  Annually,  Eight Sittings Of The Court,  For The City Of

Chapter 7 (Illegal Judges) Pg 144

London And The County Of Middlesex. Usually,  The Recorder Of

London Supplies His Place As Judge. In Some Instances The Term

Bailiff,  In England,  Is Applied To The Chief Magistrates Of

Towns,  Or To The Commanders Of Particular Castles,  As That Of

Dover. The Term Baillie,  In Scotland,  Is Applied To A Judicial

Police-Officer,  Having Powers Very Similar To Those Of Justices

Of Peace In The United States."   Encyclopaedia Americana.

 

[8] Alderman Was A Title Anciently Given To Various Judicial Officers,

As The Alderman Of All England,  Alderman Of The King,  Alderman

Of The County,  Alderman Of The City Or Borough,  Alderman Of The

Hundred Or Wapentake. These Were All Judicial Officers. See Law

Dictionaries.

 

[9] "Ban And Arriere Ban,  A Proclamation,  Whereby All That Hold

Lands Of The Crown,  (Except Some Privileged Officers And

Citizens,) Are Summoned To Meet At A Certain Place In Order To

Serve The King In His Wars,  Either Personally,  Or By Proxy." 

Boyer.

 

[10] Perhaps It May Be Said (And Such,  It Has Already Been Seen,

Is The Opinion Of Coke And Others) That The Chapter Of Magna

Carta,  That "No Bailiff From Henceforth Shall Put Any Man To His

Open Law,  (Put Him On Trial,) Nor To An Oath (That Is,  An Oath Of

Self- Exculpation) Upon His (The Bailiff's) Own Accusation Or

Testimony,  Without Credible Witnesses Brought In To Prove The

Charge," Is Itself A " Provision In Regard To The King's Justices

Sitting In Criminal Trials," And Therefore Implies That They Areto Sit

In Such Trials.

 

But,  Although The Word Bailiff Includes All Judicial,  As Well As

Other,  Officers,  And Would Therefore In This Case Apply To The

King's Justices,  If They Were To Sit In Criminal Trials; Yet This

Particular Chapter Of Magna Carta Evidently Does Not Contemplate

"Bailiffs" While Acting In Their Judicial Capacity,  (For They

Were Not Allowed To Sit In Criminal Trials At All,) But Only In

The Character Of Witnesses,  And That The Meaning Of The Chapter

Is,  That The Simple Testimony (Simplici Loquela) Of "No Bailiff,"

(Of Whatever Kind,) Unsupported By Other And "Credible

Witnesses," Shall Be Sufficient To Put Any Man On Trial,  Or To

His Oath Of Self-Exculpation." [11]

 

It Will Be Noticed That The Words Of This Chapter Are Not,  "No

Bailiff Of Ours,"   That Is,  Of The King,    As In Some Other

Chapters Of Magna Carta; But Simply "No Bailiff,"&C;. The

Prohibition,  Therefore,  Applied To All "Bailiffs,"   To Those

Chosen By The People,  As Well As Those Appointed By The King. And

The Prohibition Is Obviously Founded Upon The Idea (A Very Sound

One In That Age Certainly,  And Probably Also In This) That Public

Officers (Whether Appointed By King Or People) Have Generally,  Or

At Least Frequently,  Too Many Interests And Animosities Against

Accused Persons,  To Make It,  Safe To Convict Any Man On Their

Testimony Alone.

 

Chapter 7 (Illegal Judges) Pg 145

The Idea Of Coke And Others,  That The Object Of This Chapter Was

Simply To Forbid Magistrates To Put A Man On Trial,  When There

Were No Witnesses Against Him,  But Only The Simple Accusation Or

Testimony Of The Magistrates Themselves,  Before Whom He Was To

Be Tried,  Is Preposterous; For That Would Be Equivalent To Supposing

That Magistrates Acted In The Triple Character Of Judge,  Jury And

Witnesses,  In The Same Trial; And That,  Therefore,  In Such Case,

They Needed To Be Prohibited From Condemning A Man On Their Own

Accusation Or Testimony Alone. But Such A Provision Would Have

Been Unnecessary And Senseless,  For Two Reasons; First,  Because

The Bailiffs Or Magistrates Had No Power To "Hold Pleas Of The

Crown," Still Less To Try Or Condemn A Man; That Power Resting

Wholly With The Juries; Second,  Because If Bailiffs Or

Magistrates Could Try And Condemn A Man,  Without A Jury,  The

Prohibition Upon Their Doing So Upon Their Own Accusation Or

Testimony Alone,  Would Give No Additional Protection To The

Accused,  So Long As These Same Bailiffs Or Magistrates Were

Allowed To Decide What Weight Should Be Given,  Both To Their Own

Testimony And That Of Other Witnesses,  For,  If They Wished To

Convict,  They Would Of Course Decide That Any Testimony,  However

Frivolous Or Irrelevant,  In Addition To Their Own,  Was Sufficient.

Certainly A Magistrate Could Always Procure Witnesses

Enough To Testify To Something Or Other,  Which He Himself Could

Decide To Be Corroborative Of His Own Testimony. And Thus The

Prohibition Would Be Defeated In Fact,  Though Observed In Form.

 

[11] At The Common Law,  Parties,  In Both Civil And Criminal

Cases,  Were Allowed To Swear In Their Own Behalf; And It Will Be

So Again,  If The True Trial By Jury Should Be Reestablished.

 

[12] In This Chapter I Have Called The Justices "Presiding

Officers," Solely For The Want Of A Better Term. They Are Not

"Presiding Officers," In The Sense Of Having Any Authority Over

The Jury; But Are Only Assistants To,  And Teachers And Servants

Of,  The Jury. The Foreman Of The Jury Is Properly The "Presiding

Officer," So Far As There Is Such An Officer At All. The Sheriff

Has No Authority Except Over Other Persons Than The Jury.

 

 

 

 

Chapter 8 (The Free Administration Of Justice) Pg 146

The  Free Administration Of Justice Was A Principle Of The Common

Law; And It Must Necessarily Be A Part Of Every System Of

Government Which Is Not Designed To Be An Engine In The Hands Of

The Rich For The Oppression Of The Poor.

 

In Saying That The Free Administration Of Justice Was A Principle

Of The Common Law,  I Mean Only That Parties Were Subjected To No

Costs For Jurors,  Witnesses,  Writs,  Or Other Necessaries For The

Trial,  Preliminary To The Trial Itself. Consequently,  No One

Could Lose The Benefit Of A Trial,  For The Want Of Means To

Defray Expenses. But After The Trial,  The Plaintiff Or Defendant

Was Liable To Be Amerced,  (By The Jury,  Of Course,) For Having

Troubled The Court With The Prosecution Or Defence Of An Unjust

Suit.

 

[1] But It Is Not Likely That The Losing Party Was Subjected To

An Amercement As A Matter Of Course,  But Only In Those Cases

Where The Injustice Of His Cause Was So Evident As To Make Him

Inexcusable In Bringing It Before The Courts.

 

All The Freeholders Were Required To Attend The Courts,  That They

Might Serve As Jurors And Witnesses,  And Do Any Other Service

That Could Legally Be Required Of Them; And Their Attendance Was

Paid For By The State. In Other Words,  Their Attendance And

Service At The Courts Were Part Of The Rents Which They Paid The

State For Their Lands.

 

The Freeholders,  Who Were Thus Required Always To Attendthe

Courts,  Were Doubtless The Only Witnesses Who Were Usually

Required In Civil Causes. This Was Owing To The Fact That,  In

Those Days,  When The People At Large Could Neither Write Nor

Read,  Few Contracts Were Put In Writing. The Expedient Adopted

For Proving Contracts,  Was That Of Making Them In The Presence Of

Witnesses,  Who Could Afterwards Testify To The Transactions. Most

Contracts In Regard To Lands Were Made At The Courts,  In The

Presence Of The Freeholders There Assembled. [2]

 

In The King's Courts It Was Specially Provided By Magna Carta

That "Justice And Right" Should Not Be "Sold;" That Is,  That The

King Should Take Nothing From The Parties For Administering

Justice.

 

The Oath Of A Party To The Justice Of His Cause Was All That Was

Necessary To Entitle Him To The Benefit Of The Courts Free Of All

Expense; (Except The Risk Of Being Amerced After The Trial,  In

Case The Jury Should Think He Deserved It. [3])

 

This Principle Of The Free Administration Of Justice Connects

Itself Necessarily With The Trial By Jury,  Because A Jury Could

Not Rightfully Give Judgment Against Any Man,  In Either A Civil

Or Criminal Case,  If They Had Any Reason To Suppose He Had Been

Unable To Procure His Witnesses.

 

The True Trial By Jury Would Also Compel The Free Administration

Of Justice From Another Necessity,  Viz.,  That Of Preventing

Private Quarrels; Because,  Unless The Government Enforced A Man's

Rights And Redressed His Wrongs,  Free Of Expense To Him,  A Jury

Would Be Bound To Protect Him In Taking The Law Into His Own

Hands. A Man Has A Natural Right To Enforce His Own Rights And

Redress His Own Wrongs. If One Man Owe Another A Debt,  And Refuse

To Pay It,  The Creditor Has A Natural Right To Seize Sufficient

Property Of The Debtor,  Wherever He Can Find It,  To Satisfy The

Debt. If One Man Commit A Trespass Upon The Person,  Property Or

Character Of Another,  The Injured Party Has A Natural Right,

Chapter 8 (The Free Administration Of Justice) Pg 147

Either To Chastise The Aggressor,  Or To Take Compensation For The

Injury Out Of His Property. But As The Government Is An Impartial

Party As Between These Individuals,  It Is More Likely To Do

Exactjustice Between Them Than The Injured Individual Himself Would

Do. The Government,  Also,  Having More Power At Its Command,  Is

Likely To Right A Man's Wrongs More Peacefully Than The Injured

Party Himself Could Do It. If,  Therefore,  The Government Will Do

The Work Of Enforcing A Man's Rights,  And Redressing His Wrongs,

Promptly,  And Free Of Expense To Him,  He Is Under A Moral

Obligation To Leave The Work In The Hands Of The Government; But

Not Otherwise. When The Government Forbids Him To Enforce His

Own Rights Or Redress His Own Wrongs,  And Deprives Him Of All Means

Of Obtaining Justice,  Except On The Condition Of His Employing

The Government To Obtain It For Him,  And Of Paying The Government

For Doing It,  The Government Becomes Itself The Protector And

Accomplice Of The Wrong-Doer. If The Government Will Forbid A Man

To Protect His Own Rights,  It Is Bound,  To Do It For Him,  Free Of

Expense To Him. And So Long As Government Refuses To Do This,

Juries,  If Hey Knew Their Duties,  Would Protect A Man In

Defending His Own Rights.

 

Under The Prevailing System,  Probably One Half Of The Community

Are Virtually Deprived Of All Protection For Their Rights,  Except

What The Criminal Law Affords Them. Courts Of Justice,  For All

Civil Suits,  Are As Effectually Shut Against Them,  As Though It

Were Done By Bolts And Bars. Being Forbidden To Maintain Their

Own Rights By Force,    As,  For Instance,  To Compel The Payment Of

Debts,   And Being Unable To Pay The Expenses Of Civil Suits,

They Have No Alternative But Submission To Many Acts Of

Injustice,  Against Which The Government Is Bound Either To

Protect Them,  Free Of Expense,  Or Allow Them To Protect

Themselves.

 

There Would Be The Same Reason In Compelling A Party To Pay The

Judge And Jury For Their Services,  That There Is In Compelling

Him To Pay The Witnesses,  Or Any Other Necessary Charges. [4]

 

This Compelling Parties To Pay The Expenses Of Civil Suits Is One

Of The Many Cases In Which Government Is False To The Fundamental

Principles On Which Free Government Is Based. What Is The Object

Of Government,  But To Protect Men's Rights? On What Principle

Does A Man Pay His Taxes To The Government,  Except On That Of

Contributing His Proportion Towards The Necessary Cost Of

Protecting The Rights Of All? Yet,  When His Own Rights Are

Actually Invaded,  The Government,  Which He Contributes To

Support,  Instead Of Fulfilling Its Implied Contract,  Becomes His

Enemy,  And Not Only Refuses To Protect His Rights,  (Except At His

Own Cost,) But Even Forbids Him To Do It Himself.

 

All Free Government Is Founded On The Theory Of Voluntary

Association; And On The Theory That All The Parties To It

Voluntarily Pay Their Taxes For Its Support,  On The Condition Of

Receiving Protection In Return. But The Idea That Any Poor Man

Would Voluntarily Pay Taxes To Build Up A Government,  Which Will

Chapter 8 (The Free Administration Of Justice) Pg 148

Neither Protect His Rights,  (Except At A Cost Which He Cannot

Meet,) Nor Suffer Himself To Protect Them By Such Means As May Be

In His Power,  Is Absurd.

 

Under The Prevailing System,  A Large Portion Of The Lawsuits

Determined In Courts,  Are Mere Contests Of Purses Rather Than Of

Rights. And A Jury,  Sworn To Decide Causes "According To The

Evidence" Produced,  Are Quite Likely,  For Aught They Themselves

Can Know,  To Be Deciding Merely The Comparative Length Of The

Parties' Purses,  Rather Than The Intrinsic Strength Of Their

Respective Rights. Jurors Ought To Refuse To Decide A Cause At

All,  Except Upon The Assurance That All The Evidence,  Necessary

To A Full Knowledge Of The Cause,  Is Produced. This Assurance

They Can Seldom Have,  Unless The Government Itself Produces All

The Witnesses The Parties Desire.

 

In Criminal Cases,  The Atrocity Of Accusing A Man Of Crime,  And

Then Condemning Him Unless He Prove His Innocence At His Own

Charges,  Is So Evident That A Jury Could Rarely,  If Ever,  Be

Justified In Convicting A Man Under Such Circumstances.

 

But The Free Administration Of Justice Is Not Only Indispensable

To The Maintenance Of Right Between Man And Man; It Would Also

Promote Simplicity And Stability In The Laws. The Mania For

Legislation Would Be,  In An Important Degree,  Restrained,  If The

Government Were Compelled To Pay The Expenses Of All The Suits

That Grew Out Of It.

 

The Free Administration Of Justice Would Diminish And Nearly

Extinguish Another Great Evil,    That Of Malicious Civil Suits It

Is An Old Saying,  That "Multi Litigant In Foro,  Non Ut Aliquid

Lucentur,  Sed Ut Vexant Alios." (Many Litigate In Court,  Not That

They May Gain Anything,  But That They May Harass Others.) Many

Men,  From Motives Of Revenge And Oppression,  Are Willing To Spend

Their Own Money In Prosecuting A Groundless Suit,  If They Can

Thereby Compel Their Victims,  Who Are Less Able Than Themselves

To Bear The Loss,  To Spend Money In The Defence. Under The

Prevailing System,  In Which The Parties Pay The Expenses Of Their

Suits,  Nothing But Money Is Necessary To Enable Any Malicious Man

To Commence And Prosecute A Groundless Suit,  To The Terror,

Injury,  And Perhaps Ruin,  Of Another Man. In This Way,  A Court Of

Justice,  Into Which None But A Conscientious Plaintiff Certainly

Should Ever Be Allowed To Enter,  Becomes An Arena Into Which Any

Rich And Revengeful Oppressor May Drag Any Man Poorer Than

Himself,  And Harass,  Terrify,  And Impoverish Him,  To Almost Any

Extent. It Is A Scandal And An Outrage,  That Government Should

Suffer Itself To Be Made An Instrument,  In This Way,  For The

Gratification Of Private Malice. We Might Nearly As Well Have No

Courts Of Justice,  As To Throw Them Open,  As We Do,  For Such

Flagitious Uses. Yet The Evil Probably Admits Of No Remedy Except

A Free Administration Of Justice. Under A Free System,  Plaintiffs

Could Rarely Be Influenced By Motives Of This Kind; Because They

Could Put Their Victim To Little Or No Expense,  Neither Pending

The Suit,  (Which It Is The Object Of The Oppressor To Do,) Nor At

Chapter 8 (The Free Administration Of Justice) Pg 149

Its Termination. Besides,  If The Ancient Common Law Practice

Should Be Adopted,  Of Amercing A Party For Troubling The Courts

With Groundless Suits,  The Prosecutor Himself Would,  In The End,

Be Likely To Be Amerced By The Jury,  In Such A Manner As To Make

Courts Of Justice A Very Unproitable Place For A Man To Go To

Seek Revenge.

 

In Estimating The Evils Of This Kind,  Resulting From The Present

System,  We Are To Consider That They Are Not,  By Any Means,

Confined To The Actual Suits In Which This Kind Of Oppression Is

Practised; But We Are To Include All Those Cases In Which The

Fear Of Such Oppression Is Used As A Weapon To Compel Men Into A

Surrender Of Their Rights.

 

[1] 2 Sullivan Lectures,  234-5. 3 Blackstone,  274-5,  376. Sullivan

Says That Both Plaintiff's And Defendants Were Liable To

Amercement. Blackstone Speaks Of Plaintiffs Being Liable,  Without

Saying Whether Defendants Were So Or Not. What The Rule Really

Was I Do Not Know. There Would Seem To Be Some Reason In

Allowing Defendants To Defend Themselves,  At Their Own Charges, 

Without Exposing Themselves To Amercement In Case Of Failure.

 

[2] When Any Other Witnesses Than Freeholders Were Required In A

Civil Suit,  I Am Not Aware Of The Manner In Which Their

Attendance Was Procured; But It Was Doubtless Done At The Expense

Either Of The State Or Of The Witnesses Themselves. And It Was

Doubt Less The Same In Criminal Cases.

 

[3] "All Claims Were Established In The First Stage By The Oath

Of The Plaintiff,  Except When Otherwise Specially Directed By The

Law. The Oath,  By Which Any Claim Was Supported,  Was Called The

Fore-Oath,  Or ' Praejuramentum,' And It Was The Foundation Of His

Suit. One Of The Cases Which Did Not Require This Initiatory

Confirmation,  Was When Cattle Could Be Tracked Into Another Man's

Land,  And Then The Foot-Mark Stood For The Fore-Oath."   2

Palgrave's Rise And Progress,  &C;.,  114.

 

[4] Among The Necessary Expenses Of Suits,  Should Be Reckoned

Reasonable Compensation To Counsel,  For They Are Nearly Or Quite

As Important To The Administration Of Justice,  As Are Judges,

Jurors,  Or Witnesses; And The Universal Practice Of Employing

Them,  Both On The Part Of Governments And Of Private Persons,

Shows That Their Importance Is Generally Understood. As A Mere

Matter Of Economy,  Too,  It Would Be Wise For The Government To

Pay Them,  Rather Than They Should Not Be Employed; Because They

Collect And Arrange The Testimony And The Law Beforehand,  So As

To Be Able To Present The Whole Case To The Court And Jury

Intelligibly,  And In A Short Space Of Time. Whereas,  If They Were

Not Employed,  The Court And Jury Would Be Under The Necessity

Either Of Spending Much More Time Than Now In The Investigation

Of Causes,  Or Of Despatching Them In Haste,  And With Little

Regard To Justice. They Would Be Very Likely To Do The Latter,

Thus Defeating The Whole Object Of The People In Establishing

Courts. 

Chapter 8 (The Free Administration Of Justice) Pg 150

 

To Prevent The Abuse Of This Right,  It Should Perhaps Be Left

Discretionary With The Jury In Each Case To Determine Whether The

Counsel Should Receive Any Pay   And,  If Any,  How Much   From The

Government.

 

Chapter 9 (The Criminal Intent) Pg 151

It Is A Maxim Of The Common Law That There Can Be No Crime

Without A Criminal Intent. And It Is A Perfectly Clear Principle,

Although One Which Judges Have In A Great Measure Overthrown In

Practice,  That Jurors Are To Judge Of The Moral Intent Of An

Accused Person,  And Hold Him Guiltless,  Whatever His Act,  Unless

They Find Him To Have Acted With A Criminal Intent; That Is,  With

A Design To Do What He Knew To Be Criminal.

 

This Principle Is Clear,  Because The Question For A Jury To

Determine Is,  Whether The Accused Be Guilty,  Or Not Guilty. Guiltis A

Personal Quality Of The Actor,   Not Necessarily Involved In

The Act,  But Depending Also Upon The Intent Or Motive With Which

The Act Was Done. Consequently,  The Jury Must Find That He Acted

From A Criminal Motive,  Before They Can Declare Him Guilty.

 

There Is No Moral Justice In,  Nor Any Political Necessity For,

Punishing A Man For Any Act Whatever That He May Have Committed,

If He Have Done It Without Any Criminal Intent. There Can Be No

Moral Justice In Punishing For Such An Act,  Because,  There Having

Been No Criminal Motive,  There Can Have Been No Other Motive

Which Justice Can Take Cognizance Of,  As Demanding Or Justifying

Punishment. There Can Be No Political Necessity For Punishing,  To

Warn Against Similar Acts In Future,  Because,  If One Man Have

Injured Another,  However Unintentionally,  He Is Liable,  And

Justly Liable,  To A Civil Suit For Damages; And In This Suit He

Will Be Compelled To Make Compensation For The Injury,

Notwithstanding His Innocence Of Any Intention To Injure. He Must

Bear The Consequences Of His Own Act,  Instead Of Throwing Them

Upon Another,  However Innocent He May Have Been Of Any Intention

To Do Wrong. And The Damages He Will Have To Pay Will Be A

Sufficient Warning To Him Not To Do The Like Act Again.

 

If It Be Alleged That There Are Crimes Against The Public,  (As

Treason,  For Example,  Or Any Other Resistance To Government,) For

Which Private Persons Can Recover No Damages,  And That There Is A

Political Necessity For Punishing For Such Offences,  Even Though

The Party Acted Conscientiously,  The Answer Is,    The Government

Must Bear With All Resistance That Is Not So Clearly Wrong As To

Give Evidence Of Criminal Intent. In Other Words,  The Government,

In All Its Acts,  Must Keep Itself So Clearly Within The Limits Of

Justice,  As That Twelve Men,  Taken At Random,  Will All Agree That

It Is In The Right,  Or It Must Incur The Risk Of Resistance,

Chapter 9 (The Criminal Intent) Pg 152

Without Any Power To Punish It. This Is The Mode In Which The

Trial By Jury Operates To Prevent The Government From Falling

Into The Hands Of A Party,  Or A Faction,  And To Keep It Within

Such Limits As All,  Or Substantially All,  The People Are Agreed

That It May Occupy.

 

This Necessity For A Criminal Intent,  To Justify Conviction,  Is

Proved By The Issue Which The Jury Are To Try,  And The Verdict

They Are To Pronounce. The "Issue" They Are To Try Is,  "Guilty,"Or

"Not Guilty." And Those Are The Terms They Are Required To Use

In Rendering Their Verdicts. But It Is A Plain Falsehood To Say

That A Man Is "Guilty," Unless He Have Done An Act Which He Knew

To Be Criminal.

 

This Necessity For A Criminal Intent   In Other Words,  For Guilt 

As A Preliminary To Conviction,  Makes It Impossible That A Man

Can Be Rightfully Convicted For An Act That Is Intrinsically

Innocent,  Though Forbidden By The Government; Because Guilt Is An

Intrinsic Quality Of Actions And Motives,  And Not One That Can Be

Imparted To Them By Arbitrary Legislation. All The Efforts Of The

Government,  Therefore,  To "Make Offences By Statute," Out Of Acts

That Are Not Criminal By Nature,  Must Necessarily Be Ineffectual,

Unless A Jury Will Declare A Man "Guilty" For An Act That Is

Really Innocent.

 

The Corruption Of Judges,  In Their Attempts To Uphold The

Arbitrary Authority Of The Government,  By Procuring The

Conviction Of Individuals For Acts Innocent In Themselves,  And

Forbidden Only By Some Tyrannical Statute,  And The Commission Of

Which Therefore Indicates No Criminal Intent,  Is Very Apparent.

 

To Accomplish This Object,  They Have In Modern Times Held It To

Be Unnecessary That Indictments Should Charge,  As By The Common

Law They Were Required To Do,  That An Act Was Done "Wickedly,"

"Feloniously," "With Malice Aforethought," Or In Any Other Manner

That Implied A Criminal Intent,  Without Which There Can Be No

Criminality; But That It Is Sufficient To Charge Simply That It

Was Done " Contrary To The Form Of The Statute In Such Case Made

And Provided." This Form Of Indictment Proceeds Plainly Upon The

Assumption That The Government Is Absolute,  And That It Has

Authority To Prohibit Any Act It Pleases,  However Innocent In Its

Nature The Act May Be. Judges Have Been Driven To The Alternative

Of Either Sanctioning This New Form Of Indictment,  (Which They

Never Had Any Constitutional Right To Sanction,) Or Of Seeing The

Authority Of Many Of The Statutes Of The Government Fall To The

Ground; Because The Acts Forbidden By The Statutes Were So

Plainly Innocent In Their Nature,  That Even The Government Itself

Had Not The Face To Allege That The Commission Of Them Implied Or

Indicated Any Criminal Intent.

 

To Get Rid Of The Necessity Of Showing A Criminal Intent,  And

Thereby Further To Enslave The People,  By Reducing Them To The

Necessity Of A Blind,  Unreasoning Submission To The Arbitrary

Will Of The Government,  And Of A Surrender Of All Right,  On Their

Chapter 9 (The Criminal Intent) Pg 153

Own Part,  To Judge What Are Their Constitutional And Natural

Rights And Liberties,  Courts Have Invented Another Idea,  Which

They Have Incorporated Among The Pretended Maxims,  Upon Which

They Act In Criminal Trials,  Viz.,  That "Ignorance Of The Law

Excuses No One." As If It Were In The Nature Of Things Possible

That There Could Be An Excuse More Absolute And Complete. What

Else Than Ignorance Of The Law Is It That Excuses Persons Under

The Years Of Discretion,  And Men Of Imbecile Minds? What Else

Than Ignorance Of The Law Is It That Excuses Judges Themselves

For All Their Erroneous Decisions? Nothing. They Are Every Day

Committing Errors,  Which Would Be Crimes,  But For Their Ignorance

Of The Law. And Yet These Same Judges,  Who Claim To Be Learned In

The Law,  And Who Yet Could Not Hold Their Offices For A Day,  But

For The Allowance Which The Law Makes For Their Ignorance,  Are

Continually Asserting It To Be A "Maxim" That "Ignorance Of The

Law Excuses No One;" (By Which,  Of Course,  They Really Mean That

It Excuses No One But Themselves; And Especially That It Excuses

No Unlearned Man,  Who Comes Before Them Charged With Crime.)

 

This Preposterous Doctrine,  That "Ignorance Of The Law Excuses No

One," Is Asserted By Courts Because It Is An Indispensable One To

The Maintenance Of Absolute Power In The Government. It Is

Indispensable For This Purpose,  Because,  If It Be Once Admitted

That The People Have Any Rights And Liberties Which The

Government Cannot Lawfully Take From Them,  Then The Question

Arises In Regard To Every Statute Of The Government,  Whether It

Be Law,  Or Not; That Is,  Whether It Infringe,  Or Not,  The Rights

And Liberties Of The People. Of This Question Every Man Must Of

Course Judge According To The Light In His Own Mind. And No Man

Can Be Convicted Unless The Jury Find,  Not Only That The Statute

Is Law,    That It Does Not Infringe The Rights And Liberties Of

The People,    But Also That It Was So Clearly Law,  So Clearly

Consistent With The Rights And Liberties Of The People,  As That

The Individual Himself,  Who Transgressed It,  Knew It To Be So,

And Therefore Had No Moral Excuse For Transgressing It.

Governments See That If Ignorance Of The Law Were Allowed To

Excuse A Man For Any Act Whatever,  It Must Excuse Him For

Transgressing All Statutes Whatsoever,  Which He Himself Thinks

Inconsistent With His Rights And Liberties. But Such A Doctrine

Would Of Course Be Inconsistent With The Maintenance Of Arbitrary

Power By The Government; And Hence Governments Will Not Allow

The Plea,  Although They Will Not Confess Their True Reasons For

Disallowing It.

 

The Only Reasons,  (If They Deserve The Name Of Reasons),  That I

Ever Knew Given For The Doctrine That Ignorance Of The Law

Excuses No One,  Are These:

 

1. "The Reason For The Maxim Is That Of Necessity. It Prevails,

'Not That All Men Know The Law,  But Because It Is An Excuse Which

Every Man Will Make,  And No Man Can Tell How To Confute Him.' 

Selden,  (As Quoted In The 2d Edition Of Starkie On Slander,

Prelim. Disc.,  P. 140,  Note.)"   Law Magazine,  (London,) Vol. 27,

P. 97.

Chapter 9 (The Criminal Intent) Pg 154

 

This Reason Impliedly Admits That Ignorance Of The Law Is,

Intrinsically,  An Ample And Sufficient Excuse For A Crime; And

That The Excuse Ought To Be Allowed,  If The Fact Of Ignorance

Could But Be Ascertained. But It Asserts That This Fact Is

Incapable Of Being Ascertained,  And That Therefore There Is A

Necessity For Punishing The Ignorant And The Knowing   That Is,

The Innocent And The Guilty   Without Discrimination.

This Reason Is Worthy Of The Doctrine It Is Used To Uphold; As If

A Plea Of Ignorance,  Any More Than Any Other Plea,  Must

Necessarily Be Believed Simply Because It Is Urged; And As If It

Were Not A Common And Every-Day Practice Of Courts And Juries,  In

Both Civil And Criminal Cases,  To Determine The Mental Capacity

Of Individuals; As,  For Example,  To Determine Whether They Are Of

Sufficient Mental Capacity To Make Reasonable Contracts; Whether

They Are Lunatic; Whether They Are Compotes Mentis,  "Of Sound

Mind And Memory," &. &. And There Is Obviously No More

Difficulty In A Jury's Determining Whether An Accused Person Knew

The Law In A Criminal Case,  Than There Is In Determining Any Of These

Other Questions That Are Continually Determined In Regard To A

Man's Mental Capacity. For The Question To Be Settled By The Jury

Is Not Whether The Accused Person Knew The Particular Penalty

Attached To His Act,  (For At Common Law No One Knew What Penalty

A Jury Would Attach To An Offence,) But Whether He Knew That His

Act Was Intrinsically Criminal. If It Were Intrinsically Criminal, 

It Was Criminal At Common Law. If It Was Not Intrinsically Criminal, 

It Was Not Criminal At Common Law. (At Least,  Such Was The General

Principle Of The Common Law. There May Have Been Exceptions In

Practice,  Owing To The Fact That The Opinions Of Men,  As To What Was

Intrinsically. Criminal,  May Not Have Been In All Cases Correct.)

 

A Jury,  Then,  In Judging Whether An Accused Person Knew His Act

To Be Illegal,  Were Bound First To Use Their Own Judgments,  As To

Whether The Act Were Intrinsically Criminal. If Their Own Judgments

Told Them The Act Was Intrinsically And Clearlycriminal,  They Would

Naturally And Reasonably Infer That The Accused Also Understood That

It Was Intrinsically Criminal,  (And Consequently Illegal,) Unless It

Should Appear That He Was Either Below Themselves In The Scale Of

Intellect,  Or Had Had Less Opportunities Of Knowing What Acts Were

Criminal. In Short,  They Would Judge,  From Any And Every Means They

Might Have Of Judging; And If They Had Any Reasonable Doubt That He

Knew His Act To Be Criminal In Itself,  They Would Be Bound To Acquit

Him.

 

The Second Reason That Has Been Offered For The Doctrine That

Ignorance Of The Law Excuses No One,  Is This:

 

"Ignorance Of The Municipal Law Of The Kingdom,  Or Of The Penalty

Thereby Inflicted On Offenders,  Doth Not Excuse Any That Is Of

The Age Of Discretion And Compos Mentis,  From The Penalty Of The

Breach Of It; Because Every Person,  Of The Age Of Discretion And

Compos Mentis,  Is Bound To Know The Law,  And Presumed To Do So.

"Ignorantia Eorum,,  Quae Quis Scire Tenetur Non Excusat."

(Ignorance Of Those Things Which Every One Is Bound To Know,  Does

Chapter 9 (The Criminal Intent) Pg 155

Not Excuse.)   1 Hale's Pleas Of The Crown,  42. Doctor And

Student,  Dialog. 2,  Ch. 46. Law Magazine,  (London,) Vol. 27,  P.

97.

 

The Sum Of This Reason Is,  That Ignorance Of The Law Excuses No

One,  (Who Is Of The Age Of Discretion And Is Compos Mentis,)

Because Every Such Person "Is Bound To Know The Law." But This Is

Giving No Reason At All For The Doctrine,  Since Saying That A Man

"Is Bound To Know The Law," Is Only Saying,  In Another Form,  That

"Ignorance Of The Law Does Not Excuse Him." There Is No

Difference At All In The Two Ideas. To Say,  Therefore,  That

"Ignorance Of The Law Excuses No One,  Because Every One Is Bound

To Know The Law," Is Only Equivalent To Saying That "Ignorance Of

The Law Excuses No One,  Because Ignorance Of The Law Excuses No

One." It Is Merely Reasserting The Doctrine,  Without Giving Any

Reason At All.

 

And Yet These Reasons,  Which Are Really No Reasons At All,  Are

The Only Ones,  So Far As I Know,  That Have Ever Been Offered For

This Absurd And Brutal Doctrine.

 

The Idea Suggested,  That " The Age Of Discretion" Determines The

Guilt Of A Person,    That There Is A Particular Age,  Prior To Which

All Persons Alike Should Be Held Incapable Of Knowing Any Crime, 

And Subsequent To Which All Persons Alike Should Be Held

Capable Of Knowing All Crimes,   Is Another Of This Most

Ridiculous Nest Of Ideas. All Mankind Acquire Their Knowledge Of

Crimes,  As They Do Of Other Things,  Gradually. Some They Learn At

An Early Age; Others Not Till A Later One. One Individual

Acquires A Knowledge Of Crimes,  As He Does Of Arithmetic,  At An

Earlier Age Than Others Do. And To Apply The Same Presumption To

All,  On The Ground Of Age Alone,  Is Not Only Gross Injustice,  But

Gross Folly. A Universal Presumption Might,  With Nearly Or Quite

As Much Reason,  Be Founded Upon Weight,  Or Height,  As Upon Age.

[1]

 

This Doctrine,  That "Ignorance Of The Law Excuses No One," Is

Constantly Repeated In The Form That "Every One Is Bound To Know

The Law." The Doctrine Is True In Civil Matters,  Especially In

Contracts,  So Far As This: That No Man,  Who Has The Ordinary Capacity

To Make Reasonable Contracts,  Can Escape The Consequences Of

His Own Agreement,  On The Ground That He Did Not Know The Law

Applicable To It. When A Man Makes A Contract,  He Gives The Other

Party Rights; And He Must Of Necessity Judge For Himself,  And Take

His Own Risk,  As To What Those Rights Are,   Otherwise The Contract

Would Not Be Binding,  And Men Could Not Make Contracts That

Would Convey Rights To Each Other. Besides,  The Capacity To Make

Reasonable Contracts, 

 

Implies And Includes A Capacity To Form A Reasonable Judgment As

To The Law Applicable To Them. But In Criminal Matters,  Where The

Question Is One Of Punishment,  Or Not; Where No Second Party Has

Acquired Any Right To Have The Crime Punished,  Unless It Were

Committed With Criminal Intent,  (But Only To Have It Compensated

For By Damages In A Civil Suit,") And When The Criminal Intent Is

The Only Moral Justification For The Punishment,  The Principle

Does Not Apply,  And A Man Is Bound To Know The Law Only As Well

As He Reasonably May. The Criminal Law Requires Neither

Impossibilities Nor Extraordinaries Of Any One. It Requires Only

Thoughtfulness And A Good Conscience. It Requires Only That A Man

Fairly And Properly Use The Judgment He Possesses,  And The Means

He Has Of Learning His Duty. It Requires Of Him Only The Same

Care To Know His Duty In Regard To The Law,  That He Is Morally

Bound To Use In Other Matters Of Equal Importance. And This Care

It Does Require Of Him. Any Ignorance Of The Law,  Therefore,  That

Is Unnecessary,  Or That Arises From Indifference Or Disregard Of

One's Duty,  Is No Excuse. An Accused Person,  Therefore,  May Be

Rightfully Held Responsible For Such A Knowledge Of The Law As Is

Common To Men In General,  Having No Greater Natural Capacities

Than Himself,  And No Greater Opportunities For Learning The Law.

And He Can Rightfully Be Held To No Greater Knowledge Of The Law

Than This. To Hold Him Responsible For A Greater Knowledge Of The

Law Than Is Common To Mankind,  When Other Things Are Equal,

Would Be Gross Injustice And Cruelty. The Mass Of Mankind Can

Give But Little Of Their Attention To Acquiring A Knowledge Of The

Law. Their Other Duties In Life Forbid It. Of Course,  They Cannot

Investigate Abstruse Or Difficult Questions. All That Can

Rightfully Be Required Of Each Of Them,  Then,  Is That He Exercise

Such A Candid And Conscientious Judgment As It Is Common

Formankind Generally To Exercise In Such Matters. If He Have Done

This,  It Would Be Monstrous To Punish Him Criminally For His

Errors; Errors Not Of Conscience,  But Only Of Judgment. It Would

Also Be Contrary To The First Principles Of A Free Government

(That Is,  A Government Formed By Voluntary Association) To Punish

Men In Such Cases,  Because It Would Be Absurd To Suppose That Any

Man Would Voluntarily Assist To Establish Or Support A Government

That Would Punish Himself For Acts Which He Himself Did Not Know

To Be Crimes. But A Man May Reasonably Unite With His Fellow-Men

To Maintain A Government To Punish Those Acts Which He Himself

Considers Criminal,  And May Reasonably Acquiesce In His Own

Liability To Be Punished For Such Acts. As Those Are The Only

Grounds On Which Any One Can Be Supposed To Render Any Voluntary

Support To A Government,  It Follows That A Government Formed By

Voluntary Association,  And Of Course Having No Powers Except Such

As All The Associates Have Consented That It May Have,  Can Have

No Power To Punish A Man For Acts Which He Did Not Himself Know

To Be Criminal.

 

The Safety Of Society,  Which Is The Only Object Of The Criminal

Law,  Requires Only That Those Acts Which Are Understood By

Mankind At Large To Be Intrinsically Criminal,  Should He Punished

As Crimes. The Remaining Few (If There Are Any) May Safely Be

Left To Go Unpunished. Nor Does The Safety Of Society Require

That Any Individuals,  Other Than Those Who Have Sufficient Mental

Capacity To Understand That Their Acts Are Criminal,  Should Be

Criminally Punished. All Others May Safely Be Left To Their

Liability,  Under The Civil Law,  To Compensate For Their

Unintentional Wrongs.

Chapter 9 (The Criminal Intent) Pg 156

 

The Only Real Object Of This Absurd And Atrocious Doctrine,  That

"Ignorance Of The Law (That Is,  Of Crime) Excuses No One," And

That "Everyone Is Bound To Know The Criminal Law," (That Is,

Bound To Know What Is A Crime,) Is To Maintain An Entirely

Arbitrary Authority On The Part Of The Government,  And To Deny To

The People All Right To Judge For Themselves What Their Own

Rights And Liberties Are. In Other Words,  The Whole Object Of The

Doctrine Is To Deny To The People Themselves All Right To Judge

What Statutes And Other Acts Of The Government Are Consistent Or

Inconsistent With Their Own Rights And Liberties; And Thus To

Reduce The People To The Condition Of Mere Slaves To A Despotic

Power,  Such As The People Themselves Would Never Have

Voluntarily Established,  And The Justice Of Whose Laws The People

Themselves Cannot Understand.

 

Under The True Trial By Jury All Tyranny Of This Kind Would Be

Abolished. A Jury Would Not Only Judge What Acts Were Really

Criminal,  But They Would Judge Of The Mental Capacity Of An

Accused Person,  And Of His Opportunities For Understand- Ing The

True Character Of His Conduct. In Short,  They Would Judge Of His

Moral Intent From All The Circumstances Of The Case,  And Acquit

Him,  If They Had Any Reasonable Doubt That He Knew That He Was

Committing A Crime. [2]

 

[1] This Presumption,  Founded Upon Age Alone,  Is As Absurd In

Civil Matters As In Criminal. What Can Be More Entirely Ludicrous

Than The Idea That All Men (Not Manifestly Imbecile) Become

Mentally Competent To Make All Contracts Whatsoever On The Day

They Become Twenty-One Years Of Age?   And That,  Previous To That

Day,  No Man Becomes Competent To Make Any Contract Whatever,

Except For The Present Supply Of The Most Obvious Wants Of

Nature? In Reason,  A Man's Legal Competency To Make

Binding Contracts,  In Any And Every Case Whatever,  Depends

Wholly Upon His Mental Capacity To Make Reasonable Contracts In

Each Particular Case. It Of Course Requires More Capacity To Make A

Reasonable Contract In Some Cases Than In Others. It Requires,

For Example,  More Capacity To Make A Reasonable Contract In The

Purchase Of A Large Estate,  Than In The Purchase Of A Pair Of

Shoes. But The Mental Capacity To Make A Reasonable Contract,  In

Any Particular Case,  Is,  In Reason,  The Only Legal Criterion Of

The Legal Competency To Make A Binding Contract In That Case. The

Age,  Whether More Or Less Than Twenty-One Years,  Is Of No Legal

Consequence Whatever,  Except That It Is Entitled To Some

Consideration As Evidence Of Capacity.

 

It May Be Mentioned,  In This Connection,  That The Rules That

Prevail,  That Every Man Is Entitled To Freedom From Parental

Authority At Twenty-One Years Of Age,  And No One Before That Age,

Are Of The Same Class Of Absurdities With Those That Have Been

Mentioned. The Only Ground On Which A Parent Is Ever Entitled To

Exercise Authority Over His Child,  Is That The Child Is Incapable

Of Taking Reasonable Care Of Himself. The Child Would Be Entitled

To His Freedom From His Birth,  If He Were At That Time Capable Of

Chapter 9 (The Criminal Intent) Pg 157

Taking Reasonable Care Of Himself. Some Become Capable Of Taking

Care Of Themselves At An Earlier Age Than Others. And Whenever

Any One Becomes Capable Of Taking Reasonable Care Of Himself,  And

Not Until Then,  He Is Entitled To His Freedom,  Be His Age More Or

Less.

 

These Principles Would Prevail Under The True Trial By Jury,  The

Jury Being The Judges Of The Capacity Of Every Individual Whose

Capacity Should Be Called In Question.

 

[2] In Contrast To The Doctrines Of The Text,  It May Be Proper To

Present More Distinctly The Doctrines That Are Maintained By

Judges,  And That Prevail In Courts Of Justice. Of Course,  No

Judge,  Either Of The Present Day,  Or Perhaps Within The Last Five

Hundred Years,  Has Admitted The Right Of A Jury To Judge Of The

Justice Of A Law,  Or To Hold Any Law Invalid For Its Injustice.

Every Judge Asserts The Power Of The Government To Punish For

Acts That Are Intrinsically Innocent,  And Which Therefore Involve

Or Evince No Criminal Intent.  To Accommodate The Administration

Of Law To This Principle,  All Judges,  So Far As I Am Aware,  Hold

It To Be Unnecessary That An Indictment Should Charge,  Or That A

Jury Should Find,  That An Act Was Done With A Criminal Intent,

Except In Those Cases Where The Act Is Malum In Se,   Criminal In

Itself. In All Other Cases,  So Far As I Am Aware,  They Hold It

Sufficient That The Indictment Charge,  And Consequently That The

Jury Find,  Simply That The Act Was Done " Contrary To The Form Of

The Statute In Such Case Made And Provided;" In Other Words,

Contrary To The Orders Of The Government.

 

All These Doctrines Prevail Universally Among Judges,  And Are,  I

Think,  Uniformly Practised Upon In Courts Of Justice; And They

Plainly Involve The Most Absolute Despotism On The Part Of The

Government.

 

But There Is Still Another Doctrine That Extensively,  And Perhaps

Most Generally,  Prevails In Practice,  Although Judges Are Not

Agreed In Regard To Its Soundness. It Is This: That It Is Not

Even Necessary That The Jury Should See Or Know,  For Themselves,

What The Law Is That Is Charged To Have Been Violated; Nor To See

Or Know,  For Themselves,  That The Act Charged Was In Violation Of

Any Law Whatever;   But That It Is Sufficient That They Be Simply

Told By The Judge That Any Act Whatever,  Charged In An

Indictment,  Is In Violation Of Law,  And That They Are Then Bound

Blindly To Receive The Declaration As True,  And Convict A Man

Accordingly,  If They Find That He Has Done The Act Charged.

 

This Doctrine Is Adopted By Many Among The Most Eminent Judges,

And The Reasons For It Are Thus Given By Lord Mansfield:

 

"They (The Jury) Do Not Know,  And Are Not Presumed To Know,  The

Law. They Are Not Sworn To Decide The Law;" [3] They Are Not

Required To Do It... The Jury Ought Not To Assume The

Jurisdiction Of Law. They Do Not Know,  And Are Not Presumed To

Know,  Anything Of The Matter. They Do Not Understand The Language

Chapter 9 (The Criminal Intent) Pg 158

In Which It Is Conceived,  Or The Meaning Of The Terms. They Have

No Rule To Go By But Their Passions And Wishes."   8 Term Rep.,

428,  Note.

 

What Is This But Saying That The People,  Who Are Supposed To Be

Represented In Juries,  And Who Institute And Support The

Government,  (Of Course For The Protection Of Their Own Rights And

Liberties,  As They Understand Them,  For Plainly No Other Motive

Can Be Attributed To Them,) Are Really The Slaves Of A Despotic

Power,  Whose Arbitrary Commands Even They Are Not Supposed

Competent To Understand,  But For The Transgression Of Which They

Are Nevertheless To Be Punished As Criminals

 

This Is Plainly The Sum Of The Doctrine,  Because The Jury Are The

Peers (Equals) Of The Accused,  And Are Therefore Supposed To Know

The Law As Well As He Does,  And As Well As It Is Known By The

People At Large. If They (The Jury) Are Not Presumed To Know The

Law,  Neither The Accused Nor The People At Large Can Be Presumed

To Know It. Hence,  It Follows That One Principle Of The Truetrial By

Jury Is,  That No Accused Person Shall Be Held Responsible For Any

Other Or Greater Knowledge Of The Law Than Is Common To His

Political Equals,  Who Will Generally Be Men Of Nearly Similar

Condition In Life. But The Doctrine Of Mansfield Is,  That The Body

Of The People,  From Whom Jurors Are Taken,  Are Responsible To A

Law,  Which It Is Agreed They Cannot Understand. What Is This But

Despotism?   And Not Merely Despotism,  But Insult And Oppression

Of The Intensest Kind?

 

[3] This Declaration Of Mansfield,  That Juries In England "Are

Not Sworn To Decide The Law" In Criminal Cases,  Is A Plain

Falsehood. They Are Sworn To Try The Whole Case At Issue Between

The King And The Prisoner,  And That Includes The Law As Well As

The Fact. See Jurors Oath,  Page 85.

 

This Doctrine Of Mansfield Is The Doctrine Of All Who Deny The

Right Of Juries To Judge Of The Law,  Although All May Not Choose

To Express It In So Blunt And Unambiguous Terms. But The Doctrine

Evidently Admits Of No Other Interpretation Or Defence.

 

 

Chapter 10 (Moral Considerations For Jurors) Pg 159

 

The Trial By Jury Must,  If Possible,  Be Construed To Be Such That

A Man Can Rightfully Sit In A Jury,  And Unite With His Fellows In

Giving Judgment. But No Man Can Rightfully Do This,  Unless He

Hold In His Own Hand Alone A Veto Upon Any Judgment Or Sentence

Whatever To Be Rendered By The Jury Against A Defendant,  Which

Veto He Must Be Permitted To Use According To His Own Discretion

And Conscience,  And Not Bound To Use According To The Dictation

Of Either Legislatures Or Judges.

 

Chapter 10 (Moral Considerations For Jurors) Pg 160

The Prevalent Idea,  That A Juror May,  At The Mere Dictation Of A

Legislature Or A Judge,  And Without The Concurrence Of His Own

Conscience Or Understanding,  Declare A Man "Guilty," And Thus In

Effect License The Government To Punish Him; And That The

Legislature Or The Judge,  And Not Himself,  Has In That Case All

The Moral Responsibility For The Correctness Of The Principles On

Which The Judgment Was Rendered,  Is One Of The Many Gross

Impostures By Which It Could Hardly Have Been Supposed That Any

Sane Man Could Ever Have Been Deluded,  But Which Governments

Have Nevertheless Succeeded In Inducing The People At Large To Receive

And Act Upon.

 

As A Moral Proposition,  It Is Perfectly Self-Evident That,  Unless

Juries Have All The Legal Rights That Have Been Claimed For Them

In The Preceding Chapters,    That Is,  The Rights Of Judging What

The Law Is,  Whether The Law Be A Just One,  What Evidence Is

Admissible,  What Weight The Evidence Is Entitled To,  Whether An

Act Were Done With A Criminal Intent,  And The Right Also To Limit

The Sentence,  Free Of All Dictation From Any Quarter,    They Have

No Moral Right To Sit In The Trial At All,  And Cannot Do So

Without Making Themselves Accomplices In Any Injustice That They

May Have Reason To Believe May Result From Their Verdict. It Is

Absurd To Say That They Have No Moral Responsibility For The Use

That May Be Made Of Their Verdict By The Government,  When They

Have Reason To Suppose It Will Be Used For Purposes Of Injustice.

 

It Is,  For Instance,  Manifestly Absurd To Say That Jurors Have No

Moral Responsibility For The Enforcement Of An Unjust Law,  When

They Consent To Render A Verdict Of Guilty For The Transgression

Of It; Which Verdict They Know,  Or Have Good Reason To Believe,

Will Be Used By The Government As A Justification For Inflicting

A Penalty.

 

It Is Absurd,  Also,  To Say That Jurors Have No Moral

Responsibility For A Punishment Indicted Upon A Man Against Law,

When,  At The Dictation Of A Judge As To What The Law Is,  They

Have Consented To Render A Verdict Against Their Own Opinions Of

The Law.

 

It Is Absurd,  Too,  To Say That Jurors Have No Moral

Responsibility For The Conviction And Punishment Of An Innocent

Man,  When They Consent To Render A Verdict Against Him On The

Strength Of Evidence,  Or Laws Of Evidence,  Dictated To Them By

The Court,  If Any Evidence Or Laws Of Evidence Have Been

Excluded,  Which They (The Jurors) Think Ought To Have Been

Admitted In His Defence.

 

It Is Absurd To Say That Jurors Have No Moral Responsibility For

Rendering A Verdict Of "Guilty" Against A Man,  For An Act Which

He Did Not Know To Be A Crime,  And In The Commission Of Which,

Therefore,  He Could Have Had No Criminal Intent,  In Obedience To

The Instructions Of Courts That "Ignorance Of The Law (That Is,

Of Crime) Excuses No One."

 

Chapter 10 (Moral Considerations For Jurors) Pg 161

It Is Absurd,  Also,  To Say That Jurors Have No Moral

Responsibility For Any Cruel Or Unreasonable Sentence That May Be

Inflicted Even Upon A Guilty Man,  When They Consent To Render A

Verdict Which They Have Reason To Believe Will Be Used By The

Government As A Justification For The Infliction Of Such

Sentence.

 

The Consequence Is,  That Jurors Must Have The Whole Case In Their

Hands,  And Judge Of Law,  Evidence,  And Sentence,  Or They Incur

The Moral Responsibility Of Accomplices In Any Injustice Which

They Have Reason To Believe Will Be Done By The Government On The

Authority Of Their Verdict.

 

The Same Principles Apply To Civil Cases As To Criminal. If A

Jury Consent,  At The Dictation Of The Court,  As To Either Law Or

Evidence,  To Render A Verdict,  On The Strength Of Which They Have

Reason To Believe That A Man's Property Will Be Taken From Him

And Given To Another,  Against Their Own Notions Of Justice,  They

Make Themselves Morally Responsible For The Wrong.

 

Every Man,  Therefore,  Ought To Refuse To Sit In A Jury,  And To

Take The Oath Of A Juror,  Unless The Form Of The Oath Be Such As

To Allow Him To Use His Own Judgment,  On Every Part Of The Case,

Free Of All Dictation Whatsoever,  And To Hold In His Own Hand A

Veto Upon Any Verdict That Can Be Rendered Against A Defendant,

And Any Sentence That Can Be Inflicted Upon Him,  Even If He Be

Guilty.

 

Of Course,  No Man Can Rightfully Take An Oath As Juror,  To Try A

Case "According To Law," (If By Law Be Meant Anything Other Than

His Own Ideas Of Justice,) Nor "According To The Law And The

Evidence,  As They Shall Be Given Him." Nor Can He Rightfully Take

An Oath Even To Try A Case "According To The Evidence," Because

In All Cases He May Have Good Reason To Believe That A Party Has

Been Unable To Produce All The Evidence Legitimately Entitled To

Be Received. The Only Oath Which It Would Seem That A Man Can

Rightfully Take As Juror,  In Either A Civil Or Criminal Case,  Is,

That He "Will Try The Case According To His Conscience." Of

Course,  The Form May Admit Of Variation,  But This Should Be The

Substance. Such,  We Have Seen,  Were The Ancient Common Law

Oaths.

 

 

 

 

Chapter 11 (Authority Of Magna Carta) Pg 162

 

Probably No Political Compact Between King And People Was

Ever

Entered Into In A Manner To Settle More Authoritatively The

Fundamental Law Of A Nation,  Than Was Magna Carta. Probably No

People Were Ever More United And Resolute In Demanding From

Their

Chapter 11 (Authority Of Magna Carta) Pg 163

King A Definite And Unambiguous Acknowledgment Of Their Rights

And Liberties,  Than Were The English At That Time. Probably No

King Was Ever More Completely Stripped Of All Power To Maintain

His Throne,  And At The Same Time Resist The Demands Of His

People,  Than Was John On The 15th Day Of June,  1215. Probably No

King Every Consented,  More Deliberately Or Explicitly,  To Hold

His Throne Subject To Specific And Enumerated Limitations Upon

His Power,  Than Did John When He Put His Seal To The Great

Charter Of The Liberties Of England. And If Any Political Compact

Between King And People Was Ever Valid To Settle The Liberties Of

The People,  Or To Limit The Power Of The Crown,  That Compact Is

Now To Be Found In Magna Carta. If,  Therefore,  The Constitutional

Authority Of Magna Carta Had Rested Solely Upon The Compact Of

John With His People,  That Authority Would Have Been Entitled To

Stand Forever As The Supreme Law Of The Land,  Unless Revoked By

The Will Of The People Themselves.

 

But The Authority Of Magna Carta Does Not Rest Alone Upon The

Compact With John. When,  In The Next Year,  (1216,) His Son,  Henry

Iii.,  Came To The Throne,  The Charter Was Ratified By Him,  And

Again In 1217,  And Again In 1225,  In Substantially The Same Form,

And Especially Without Allowing Any New Powers,  Legislative,

Judicial,  Or Executive,  To The King Or His Judges,  And Without

Detracting In The Least From The Powers Of The Jury. And From The

Latter Date To This,  The Charter Has Remained Unchanged.

 

In The Course Of Two Hundred Years The Charter Was Confirmed By

Henry And His Successors More Than Thirty Times. And Although

They Were Guilty Of Numerous And Almost Continual Breaches Of It,

And Were Constantly Seeking To Evade It,  Yet Such Were The

Spirit,  Vigilance And Courage Of The Nation,  That The Kings Held

Their Thrones Only On The Condition Of Their Renewed And Solemn

Promises Of Observance. And It Was Not Until 1429,  (As Will Be

More Fully Shown Hereafter,) When A Truce Between Themselves,

And

A Formal Combination Against The Mass Of The People,  Had Been

Entered Into,  By The King,  The Nobility,  And The "Forty Shilling

Freeholders," (A Class Whom Mackintosh Designates As "A Few

Freeholders Then Accounted Wealthy," [1]) By The Exclusion Of All

Others Than Such Freeholders From All Voice In The Election Of

Knights To Represent The Counties In The House Of Commons,  That A

Repetition Of These Confirmations Of Magna Carta Ceased To Be

Demanded. And Obtained. [2]

 

The Terms And The Formalities Of Some Of These "Confirmations"

Make Them Worthy Of Insertion At Length.

 

Hume Thus Describes One Which Took Place In The 38th Year Of

Henry Iii. (1253):

 

" But As They (The Barons) Had Experienced His (The King's)

Frequent Breach Of Promise,  They Required That He Should Ratify

The Great Charter In A Manner Still More Authentic And Solemn

Than Any Which He Had Hitherto Employed. All The Prelates And

Chapter 11 (Authority Of Magna Carta) Pg 164

Abbots Were Assembled. They Held Burning Tapers In Their Hands.

The Great Charter Was Read Before Them. They Denounced The

Sentence Of Excommunication Against Every One Who Should

Thenceforth Violate That Fundamental Law. They Threw Their Tapers

On The Ground,  And Exclaimed,  May The Soul Of Every One Who

Incurs This Sentence So Stink And Corrupt In Hell! The King Bore

A Part In This Ceremony,  And Subjoined,  ' So Help Me God! I Will

Keep All These Articles Inviolate,  As I Am A Man,  As I Am A

Christian,  As I Am A Knight,  And As I Am A King Crowned And

Anointed.' "   Hume,  Ch. 12. See Also Blackstone's Introd. To The

Charters. Black. Law Tracts,  Oxford Ed.,  P. 332. Makintosh's

Hist. Of Eng.,  Ch. 3. Lardner's Cab. Cyc.,  Vol. 45,  P. 233   4. 

 

The Following Is The Form Of "The Sentence Of Excommunication"

Referred To By Hume:

 

"The Sentence Of Curse,  Given By The Bishops,  Against The

Breakers Of The Charters.

 

"The Year Of Our Lord A Thousand Two Hundred And Fifty-Three,  The

Third Day Of May,  In The Great Hall Of The King At Westminster,

In The Presence,  And By The Assent,  Of The Lord Henry,  By The

Grace Of God King Of England,  And The Lords Richard,  Earl Of

Cornwall,  His Brother,  Roger (Bigot) Earl Of Norfolk And

Suffolk;,  Marshal Of England,  Humphrey,  Earl Of Hereford,  Henry,

Earl Of Oxford,  John,  Earl Of Warwick,  And Other Estates Of The

Realm Of England: We,  Boniface,  By The Mercy Of God Archbishop

Of

Canterbury,  Primate Of All England,  F. Of London,  H. Of Ely,  S.

Of Worcester,  F. Of Lincoln,  W. Of Norwich,  P. Of Hereford,  W. Of

Salisbury,  W. Of Durham,  R. Of Exeter,  M. Of Carlisle,  W. Of

Bath,  E. Of Rochester,  T. Of Saint David's,  Bishops,  Appareled In

Pontificals,  With Tapers Burning,  Against The Breakers Of The

Church's Liberties,  And Of The Liberties Or Free Customs Of The

Realm Of England,  And Especially Of Those Which Are Contained In

The Charter Of The Common Liberties Of The Realm,  And The

Charter

Of The Forest,  Have Solemnly Denounced The Sentence Of

Excommunication In This Form. By The Authority Of Almighty God,

The Father,  The Son,  And The Holy Ghost,  And Of The Glorious

Mother Of God,  And Perpetual Virgin Mary,  Of The Blessed Apostles

Peter And Paul,  And Of All Apostles,  Of The Blessed Thomas,

Archbishop And Martyr,  And Of All Martyrs,  Of Blessed Edward Of

England,  And Of All Confessors And Virgins,  And Of All The Saints

Of Heaven: We Excommunicate,  Accurse,  And From The Thresholds

(Liminibus) Of Our Holy Mother The Church,  We Sequester,  All

Those That Hereafter Willingly And Maliciously Deprive Or Spoil

The Church Of Her Right: And All Those That By Any Craft Or

Wiliness Do Violate,  Break,  Diminish,  Or Change The Church's

Liberties,  Or The Ancient Approved Customs Of The Realm,  And

Especially The Liberties And Free Customs Contained In The

Charters Of The Common Liberties,  And Of The Forest,  Conceded By

Our Lord The King,  To Archbishops,  Bishops,  And Other Prelates Of

England And Likewise To The Earls,  Barons,  Knights,  And Other

Chapter 11 (Authority Of Magna Carta) Pg 165

Freeholders Of The Realm: And All That Secretly,  Or Openly,  By

Deed,  Word,  Or Counsel,  Do Make Statutes,  Or Observe Them Being

Made,  And That Bring In Customs,  Or Keep Them When They Be

Brought In,  Against The Said Liberties,  Or Any Of Them,  The

Writers And Counselors Of Said Statutes,  And The Executors Of

Them,  And A11 Those That Shall Presume To Judge According To

Them. All And Every Which Persons Before Mentioned,  That

Wittingly Shall Commit Anything Of The Premises,  Let Them Well

Know That They Incur The Aforesaid Sentence,  Ipso Facto,  (I. E..

Upon The Deed Being Done.) And Those That Ignorantly Do So,  And

Be Admonished,  Except They Reform Themselves Within Fifteen Days

After The Time Of The Admonition,  And Make Full Satisfaction For

That They Have Done,  At The Will Of The Ordinary,  Shall Be From

That Time Forth Included In The Same Sentence. And With The Same

Sentence We Burden All Those That Presume To Perturb The Peace Of

Our Sovereign Lord The King,  And Of The Realm. To The Perpetual

Memory Of Which Thing,  We,  The Aforesaid Prelates,  Have Put Our

Seals To These Presents."   Statutes Of The Realm,  Vol. 1,  P. 6.

Ruffhead's Statutes,  Vol. 1,  P. 20.

 

One Of The Confirmations Of The Charters,  By Edward I.,  Was By

Statute,  In The 25th Year Of His Reign,  (1297,) In The Following

Terms. The Statute Is Usually Entitled. "Confirmatio

Cartarum,"(Confirmation Of The Charters.)

 

Ch. 1.  "Edward,  By The Grace Of God,  King Of England,  Lord Of

Ireland,  And Duke Of Guyan,  To All Those That These Presents

Shall Hear Or See,  Greeting. Know Ye,  That We,  To The Honor Of

Cod,  And Of Holy Church,  And To The Profit Of Our Realm,  Have

Granted,  For Us And Our Heirs,  That The Charter Of Liberties,  And

The Charter Of The Forest,  Which Were Made By Common Assent Of

All The Realm,  In The Time Of King Henry Our Father,  Shall Be

Kept In Every Point Without Breach. And We Will That The Same

Charters Shall Be Sent Under Our Seal,  As Well To Our Justices Of

The Forest,  As To Others,  And To All Sheriff's Of Shires,  And To

All Our Other Officers,  And To All Our Cities Throughout The

Realm,  Together With Our Writs,  In The Which It Shall He

Contained,  That They Cause The Aforesaid Charters To Be

Published,  And To Declare To The People That We Have Confirmed

Them At All Points; And To Our Justices,  Sheriffs,  Mayors,  And

Other Ministers,  Which Under Us Have The Laws Of Our Land To

Guide,  That They Allow The Same Charters,  In All Their Points,  In

Pleas Before Them,  And In Judgment; That Is,  To Wit,  The Great

Charter As The Common Law,  And The Charter Of The Forest For The

Wealth Of Our Realm.

 

Ch. 2. "And We Will That If Any Judgment Be Given From Henceforth

Contrary To The Points Of The Charters Aforesaid By The Justices,

Or By Any Others Our Ministers That Hold Plea Before Them,

Against The Points Of The Charters,  It Shall Be Undone And Holden

For Naught.

 

Ch. 3. "And We Will,  That The Same Charters Shall Be Sent,  Under

Our Seal,  To Cathedral Churches Throughout Our Realms There To

Chapter 11 (Authority Of Magna Carta) Pg 166

Remain,  And Shall Be Read Before The People Two Times In The

Year.

 

Ch. 4. "And That All Archbishops And Bishops Shall Pronounce The

Sentence Of Excommunication Against All Those That By Word,  Deed,

Or Counsel,  Do Contrary To The Foresaid Charters,  Or That In Any

Point Break Or Undo Them. And That The Said Curses Be Twice A

Year Denounced And Published By The Prelates Aforesaid. And If

The Same Prelates,  Or Any Of Them,  Be Remiss In The Denunciation

Of The Said Sentences,  The Archbishops Of Canterbury And York-,

For The Time Being,  Shall Compel And Distrain Them To Make The

Denunciation In The Form Aforesaid."   St. 25 Edward I.,  (1297.).

Statutes Of The Realm,  Vol. L,  P. 123.

 

It Is Unnecessary To Repeat The Terms Of The Various

Confirmations,  Most Of Which Were Less Formal Than Those That

Have Been Given,  Though Of Course Equally Authoritative. Most Of

Them Are Brief,  And In The Form Of A Simple Statute,  Or Promise,

To The Effect That "The Great Charter,  And The Charter Of The

Forest,  Shall Be Firmly Kept And Maintained In All Points." They

Are To Be Found Printed With The Other Statutes Of The Realm. One

Of Them,  After Having "Again Granted,  Renewed And Confirmed" The

Charters,  Requires As Follows:

 

"That The Charters Be Delivered To Every Sheriff Of England Under

The King's Seal,  To Be Read Four Times In The Year Before The

People In The Full County," (That Is,  At The County Court,) "That

Is,  To Wit,  The Next County (Court) After The Feast Of Saint

Michael,  And The Next County (Court) After Christmas,  And At The

Next County (Court) After Easter,  And At The Next County (Court)

After The Feast Of Saint John "  28 Edward I.,  Ch. 1,  (1300.) V

 

Lingard Says,  "The Charter Was Ratified Four Times By Henry Iii.,

Twice By Edward I.,  Fifteen Times By Edward Iii.,  Seven Times By

Richard Ii.,  Six Times By Henry Iv.,  And Once By Henry V.;"

Making Thirty-Five Times In All.   3 Lingard,  50,  Note,  Philad.

Ed.

 

Coke Says Magna Carta Was Confirmed Thirty-Two Times.   Preface

To 2 Inst.,  P. 6.

 

Lingard Calls These "Thirty-Five Successive Ratifications" Of The

Charter,  "A Sufficient Proof How Much Its Provisions Were

Abhorred By The Sovereign,  And How Highly They Were Prized By The

Nation."   3 Lingard,  50.

 

 

 

 

 

Mackintosh Says,  "For Almost Five Centuries (That Is,  Until 1688)

It (Magna Carta) Was Appealed To As The Decisive Authority On

Behalf Of The People,  Though Commonly So Far Only As The

Necessities Of Each Case Demanded."   Mackintosh's Hist. Of Eng.

Chapter 11 (Authority Of Magna Carta) Pg 167

Ch. 3. 45 Lardner's Cab. Cyc.,  221.

 

Coke,  Who Has Labored So Hard To Overthrow The Most Vital

Principles Of Magna Carta,  And Who,  Therefore,  Ought To Be

Considered Good Authority When He Speaks In Its Favor,  [3] Says:

 

"It Is Called Magna Carta,  Not That It Is Great In Quantity,  For

There Be Many Voluminous Charters Commonly Passed,  Specially In

These Later Times,  Longer Than This Is; Nor Comparatively In

Respect That It Is Greater Than Charta De Foresta,  But In Respect

Of The Great Importance And Weightiness Of The Matter,  As

Hereafter Shall Appear; And Likewise For The Same Cause Charta De

Foresta; And Both Of Them Are Called Magnae Char- Tae Libertatum

Angliae,  (The Great Charters Of The Liberties Of England.)

 

"And It Is Also Called Charta Libertatum Regni,  (Charter Of The

Liberties Of The Kingdom;) And Upon Great Reason It Is So Called

Of The Effect,  Quia Liberos Facit,  (Because It Makes Men Free.)

Sometime For The Same Cause (It Is Called) Communis Libertas,

(Common Liberty,) And Le Chartre Des Franchises,  (The Charter Of

Franchises.)

 

"It Was For The Most Part Declaratory Of The Principal Grounds Of

The Fundamental Laws Of England,  And For The Residue It Is

Additional To Supply Some Defects Of The Common Law.

 

"Also,  By The Said Act Of 25 Edward I.,  (Called Confirmatio

Chartarum,) It Is Adjudged In Parliament That The Great Charter

And The Charter Of The Forest Shall Be Taken As The Common Law.

 

"They (Magna Carta And Carta De Foresta) Were,  For The Most Part,

But Declarations Of The Ancient Common Laws Of England,  To The

Observation And Keeping Whereof,  The King Was Bound And Sworn.

 

"After The Making Of Magna Charta,  And Charta De Foresta,  Divers

Learned Men In The Laws,  That I May Use The Words Of The Record,

Kept Schools Of The Law In The City Of London,  And Taught Such As

Resorted To Them The Laws Of The Realm,  Taking Their Foundation

Of Magna Charta And Charta De Foresta.

 

"And The Said Two Charters Have Been Confirmed,  Established,  And

Commanded To Be Put In Execution By Thirty-Two Several Acts Of

Parliament In All.

 

"This Appeareth Partly By That Which Hath Been Said,  For That It

Hath So Often Been Confirmed By The Wise Providence Of So Many

Acts Of Parliament.

 

"And Albeit Judgments In The King's Courts Are Of High Regard In

Law,  And Judicia (Judgments) Are Accounted As Jurisdicta,  (The

Speech Of The Law Itself,) Yet It Is Provided By Act Of

Parliament,  That If Any Judgment Be Given Contrary To Any Of The

Points Of The Great Charter And Charta De Foresta,  By The

Justices,  Or By Any Other Of The King's Ministers,  &C;.,  It Shall

Chapter 11 (Authority Of Magna Carta) Pg 168

Be Undone,  And Holden For Naught.

 

"And That Both The Said Charters Shall Be Sent Under The Great

Seal To All Cathedral Churches Throughout The Realm,  There To

Remain,  And Shall Be Read To The People Twice Every Year.

 

"The Highest And Most Binding Laws Are The Statutes Which Are

Established By Parliament; And By Authority Of That Highest Court

It Is Enacted (Only To Show Their Tender Care Of Magna Carta And

Carta De Foresta) That If Any Statute Be Made Contrary To The

Great Charter,  Or The Charter Of The Forest,  That Shall Be Holden

For None; By Which Words All Former Statutes Made Against Either

Of Those Charters Are Now Repealed; And The Nobles And Great

Officers Were To Be Sworn To The Observation Of Magna Charta And

Charta De Foresta.

 

"Magna Fuit Quondam Magnae Reverentia Chartae." (Great Was

Formerly The Reverence For Magna Carta.)   Coke's Proem To 2

Inst.,  P. 1 To 7.

 

Coke Also Says,  "All Pretence Of Prerogative Against Magna Charta

Is Taken Away."   2 Inst.,  36.

 

He Also Says,  "That After This Parliament (52 Henry Iii.,  In

1267) Neither Magna Carta Nor Carta De Foresta Was Ever

Attempted To Be Impugned Or Questioned."   2 Inst.,  102. [4]

 

To Give All The Evidence Of The Authority Of Magna Carta,  It

Would Be Necessary To Give The Constitutional History Of England

Since The Year 1215. This History Would Show That Magna Carta,

Although Continually Violated And Evaded,  Was Still Acknowledged

As Law By The Government,  And Was Held Up By The People As The

Great Standard And Proof Of Their Rights And Liberties. It Would

Show Also That The Judicial Tribunals,  Whenever It Suited Their

Purposes To Do So,  Were In The Habit Of Referring To Magna Carta

As Authority,  In The Same Manner,  And With The Same Real Or

Pretended Veneration,  With Which American Courts Now Refer To The

Constitution Of The United States,  Or The Constitutions Of The

States. And,  What Is Equally To The Point,  It Would Show That

These Same Tribunals,  The Mere Tools Of Kings And Parliaments,

Would Resort To The Same Artifices Of Assumption,  Precedent,

Construction,  And False Interpretation,  To Evade The Requirements

Of Magna Carta,  And To Emasculate It Of All Its Power For The

Preservation Of Liberty,  That Are Resorted To By American Courts

To Accomplish The Same Work On Our American Constitutions.

 

I Take It For Granted,  Therefore,  That If The Authority Of Magna

Carta Had Rested Simply Upon Its Character As A Compact Between

The King And The People,  It Would Have Been Forever Binding Upon

The King,  (That Is,  Upon The Government,  For The King Was The

Government,) In His Legislative,  Judicial,  And Executive

Character; And That There Was No Constitutional Possibility Of

His Escaping From Its Restraints,  Unless The People Themselves

Should Freely Discharge Him From Them.

Chapter 11 (Authority Of Magna Carta) Pg 169

 

But The Authority Of Magna Carta Does Not Rest,  Either Wholly Or

Mainly,  Upon Its Character As A Compact. For Centuries Before The

Charter Was Granted,  Its Main Principles Constituted "The Law Of

The Land,"   The Fundamental And Constitutional Law Of The Realm,

Which The Kings Were Sworn To Maintain. And The Principal Benefit

Of The Charter Was,  That It Contained A Written Description And

Acknowledgment,  By The King Himself,  Of What The Constitutional

Law Of The Kingdom Was,  Which His Coronation Oath Bound Him To

Observe. Previous To Magna Carta,  This Constitutional Law Rested

Mainly In Precedents,  Customs,  And The Memories Of The People.

And If The King Could But Make One Innovation Upon This Law,

Without Arousing Resistance,  And Being Compelled To Retreat From

His Usurpation,  He Would Cite That Innovation As A Precedent For

Another Act Of The Same Kind; Next,  Assert A Custom; And,

Finally,  Raise A Controversy As To What The Law Of The Land

Really Was. The Great Object Of The Barons And People,  In

Demanding From The King A Written Description And

Acknowledgment

Of The Law Of The Land,  Was To Put An End To All Disputes Of This

Kind,  And To Put It Out Of The Power Of The King To Plead Any

Misunderstanding Of The Constitutional Law Of The Kingdom. And

The Charter,  No Doubt,  Accomplished Very Much In This Way. After

Magna Carta,  It Required Much More Audacity,  Cunning,  Or

Strength,  On The Part Of The King,  Than It Had Before,  To Invade

The People's Liberties With Impunity. Still,  Magna Carta,  Like

All Other Written Constitutions,  Proved Inadequate To The Full

Accomplishment Of Its Purpose; For When Did A Parchment Ever

Have

Power Adequately To Restrain A Government,  That Had Either

Cunning To Evade Its Requirements,  Or Strength To Overcome Those

Who Attempted Its Defence? The Work Of Usurpation,  Therefore,

Though Seriously Checked,  Still Went On,  To A Great Extent,  After

Magna Carta. Innovations Upon The Law Of The Land Are Still Made

By The Government. One Innovation Was Cited As A Precedent;

Precedents Made Customs; And Customs Became Laws,  So Far As

Practice Was Concerned; Until The Government,  Composed Of The

King,  The High Functionaries Of The Church,  The Nobility,  A House

Of Commons Representing The "Forty Shilling Freeholders," And A

Dependent And Servile Judiciary,  All Acting In Conspiracy Against

The Mass Of The People,  Became Practically Absolute,  As It Is At

This Day.

 

As Proof That Magna Carta Embraced Little Else Than What Was

Previously Recognized As The Common Law,  Or Law Of The Land,  I

Repeat Some Authorities That Have Been Already Cited.

Crabbe Says,  "It Is Admitted On All Hands That It (Magna Carta)

Contains Nothing But What Was Confirmatory Of The Common Law

And

The Ancient Usages Of The Realm; And Is,  Properly Speaking,  Only

An Enlargement Of The Charter Of Henry I. And His Successors." 

Crabbe's Hist. Of The Eng. Law,  P. 127.

 

Blackstone Says,  "It Is Agreed By All Our Historians That The

Chapter 11 (Authority Of Magna Carta) Pg 170

Great Charter Of King John Was,  For The Most Part,  Compiled From

The Ancient Customs Of The Realm,  Or The Laws Of Edward The

Confessor; By Which They Mean The Old Common Law Which Was

Established Under Our Saxon Princes."   Blackstone's Introd. To

The Charters. See Blackstone's Law Tracts,  Oxford Ed.,  P. 289.

 

Coke Says,  " The Common Law Is The Most General And Ancient Law

Of The Realm... The Common Law Appeareth In The Statute Of Magna

Carta,  And Other Ancient Statutes,  (Which For The Most Part Are

Affirmations Of The Common Law,) In The Original Writs,  In

Judicial Records,  And In Our Books Of Terms And Years."   1

Inst.,  115 B.

 

Coke Also Says,  "It (Magna Carta) Was For The Most Part

Declaratory Of The Principal Grounds Of The Fundamental Laws Of

England,  And For The Residue It Was Additional To Supply Some

Defects Of The Common Law... They (Magna Carta And Carta De

Foresta) Were,  For The Most Part,  But Declarations Of The Ancient

Common Laws Of England,  To The Observation And Keeping Whereof

The King Was Bound And Sworn."   Preface To 2 Inst.,  P. 3 And 5.

 

Hume Says,  "We May Now,  From The Tenor Of This Charter,  (Magna

Carta,) Conjecture What Those Laws Were Of King Edward,  (The

Confessor,) Which The English Nation During So Many Generations

Still Desired,  With Such An Obstinate Perseverance,  To Have

Recalled And Established. They Were Chiefly These Latter Articles

Of Magna Carta; And The Barons Who,  At The Beginning Of These

Commotions,  Demanded The Revival Of The Saxon Laws,

Undoubtedly

Thought That They Had Sufficiently Satisfied The People,  By

Procuring Them This Concession,  Which Comprehended The Principal

Objects To Which They Had So Long Aspired."   Hume,  Ch. 11.

 

Edward The First Confessed That The Great Charter Was

Substantially Identical With The Common Law,  As Far As It Went,

When He Commanded His Justices To Allow "The Great Charter As The

Common Law," " In Pleas Before Them,  And In Judgment," As Has

Been Already Cited In This Chapter.   25 Edward I.,  Ch. 1,

(1297.)

 

In Conclusion Of This Chapter,  It May Be Safely Asserted That The

Veneration,  Attachment,  And Pride,  Which The English Nation,  For

More Than Six Centuries,  Have Felt Towards Magna Carta,  Are In

Their Nature Among The Most Irrefragable Of All Proofs That It

Was The Fundamental Law Of The Land,  And Constitutionally Binding

Upon The Government; For,  Otherwise,  It Would Have Been,  In Their

Eyes,  An Unimportant And Worthless Thing. What Those Sentiments

Were I Will Use The Words Of Others To Describe,    The Words,

Too,  Of Men,  Who,  Like All Modern Authors Who Have Written On The

Same Topic,  Had Utterly Inadequate Ideas Of The True Character Of

The Instrument On Which They Lavished Their Eulogiums.

 

Hume,  Speaking Of The Great Charter And The Charter Of The

Forest,  As They Were Confirmed By Henry Iii.,  In 1217,  Says:"Thus

These Famous Charters Were Brought Nearly To The Shape In Which

They Have Ever Since Stood; And They Were,  During Many

Generations,  The Peculiar Favorites Of The English Nation,  And

Esteemed The Most Sacred Rampart To National Liberty And

Independence. As They Secured The Rights Of All Orders Of Men,

They Were Anxiously Defended By All,  And Became The Basis,  In A

Manner,  Of The English Monarchy,  And A Kind Of Original Contract,

Which Both Limited The Authority Of The King And Ensured The

Conditional Allegiance Of His Subjects. Though Often Violated,

They Were Still Claimed By The Nobility And People; And,  As No

Precedents Were Supposed Valid That Infringed Them,  They Rather

Acquired Than Lost Authority,  From The Frequent Attempts Made

Against Them In Several Ages,  By Regal And Arbitrary Power." 

Hume,  Ch. 12.

 

Mackintosh Says,  "It Was Understood By The Simplest Of The

Unlettered Age For Whom It Was Intended. It Was Remembered By

Them... For Almost Five Centuries It Was Appealed To As The

Decisive Authority On Behalf Of The People... To Have Produced

It,  To Have Preserved It,  To Have Matured It,  Constitute The

Immortal Claim Of England On The Esteem Of Mankind. Her Bacons

Arid Shakspeares,  Her Miltons And Newtons,  With All The Truth

Which They Have Revealed,  And All The Generous Virtues Which They

Have Inspired,  Are Of Inferior Value When Compared With The

Subjection Of Men And Their Rulers To The Principles Of Justice;

If,  Indeed,  It Be Not More True That These Mighty Spirits Could

Not Have Been Formed Except Under Equal Laws,  Nor Roused To Full

Activity Without The Influence Of That Spirit Which The Great

Charter Breathed Over Their Forefathers."   Mackintosh's Hist. Of

Eng.,  Ch. 3,  [8]

 

Of The Great Charter,  The Trial By Jury Is The Vital Part,  And

The Only Part That Places The Liberties Of The People In Their

Own Keeping. Of This Blackstone Says:

 

"The Trial By Jury,  Or The Country,  Per Patriam,  Is Also That

Trial By The Peers Of Every Englishman,  Which,  As The Grand

Bulwark Of His Liberties,  Is Secured To Him By The Great Charter;

Nullus Liber Homo Capiatur,  Vel Imprisonetur,  Aut Exuletur,  Aut

Aliquo Modo Destruatur,  Nisi Per Legale Judicial Parium Suorum,

Vel Per Legem Terrae.

 

The Liberties Of England Cannot But Subsist So Long As This

Palladium Remains Sacred And Inviolate,  Not Only From All Open,

Attacks,  Which None Will Be So Hardy As To Make,  But Also From

All Secret Machinations Which May Sap And Undermine It." [9]

 

"The Trial By Jury Ever Has Been,  And I Trust Ever Will Be,

Looked Upon As The Glory Of The English Law... It Is The Most

Transcendent Privilege Which Any Subject Can Enjoy Or Wish For,

That He Cannot Be Affected In His Property,  His Liberty,  Or His

Person,  But By The Unanimous Consent Of Twelve Of His Neighbors

And Equals."[10]

 

Chapter 11 (Authority Of Magna Carta) Pg 171

Hume Calls The Trial By Jury "An Institution Admirable In Itself,

And The Best Calculated For The Preservation Of Liberty And The

Administration Of Justice,  That Ever Was Devised By The Wit Of

Man." [11]

 

An Old Book,  Called "English Liberties," Says:"English

Parliaments Have All Along Been Most Zealous For Preserving This

Great Jewel Of Liberty,  Trials By Juries Having No Less Than

Fifty-Eight Several Times,  Since The Norman Conquest,  Been

Established And Confirmed By The Legislative Power,  No One

Privilege Besides Having Been Ever So Often Remembered In

Parliament."{12]

 

[1] Mackintosh's Hist. Of Eng.,  Ch. 3. 45 Lardner's Cab. Cyc.,

354.

 

[2] "Forty Shilling Freeholders" Were Those "People Dwelling And

Resident In The Same Counties,  Whereof Every One Of Them Shall

Have Free Land Or Tenement To The Value Of Forty Shillings By The

Year At The Least Above All Charges." By Statute 8 Henry 6,  Ch.

7,  (1429,) These Freeholders Only Were Allowed To Vote For

Members Of Parliament From The Counties.

 

[3] He Probably Speaks In Its Favor Only To Blind The Eyes Of The

People To The Frauds He Has Attempted Upon Its True Meaning.

 

[4] It Will Be Noticed That Coke Calls These Confirmations Of The

Charter "Acts Of Parliament," Instead Of Acts Of The King Alone.

This Needs Explanation.

 

It Was One Of Coke's Ridiculous Pretences,  That Laws Anciently

Enacted By The King,  At The Request,  Or With The Consent,  Or By

The Advice,  Of His Parliament,  Was "An Act Of Parliament,"

Instead Of The Act Of The King. And In The Extracts Cited,  He

Carries This Idea So Far As To Pretend That The Various

Confirmations Of The Great Charter Were "Acts Of Parliament,"

Instead Of The Acts Of The Kings. He Might As Well Have Pretended

That The Original Grant Of The Charter Was An "Act Of Parliament;

"Because It Was Not Only Granted At The Request,  And With The

Consent,  And By The Advice,  But On The Compulsion Even,  Of Those

Who Commonly Constituted His Parliaments. Yet This Did Not Make

The Grant Of The Charter "An Act Of Parliament." It Was Simply An

Act Of The King.

 

The Object Of Coke,  In This Pretence,  Was To Furnish Some Color

For The Palpable False- Hood That The Legislative Authority,

Which Parliament Was Trying To Assume In His Own Day,  And Which

It Finally Succeeded In Obtaining,  Had A Precedent In The Ancient

Constitution Of The Kingdom.

 

There Would Be As Much Reason In Saying That,  Because The Ancient

Kings Were In The Habit Of Passing Laws In Special Answer To The

Petitions Of Their Subjects,  Therefore Those Petitioners Were A

Part Of The Legislative Power Of The Kingdom.

Chapter 11 (Authority Of Magna Carta) Pg 172

 

One Great Objection To This Argument Of Coke,  For The Legislative

Authority Of The Ancient Parliaments,  Is That A Very Large 

Probably Much The Larger   Number Of Legislative Acts Were Done

Without The Advice,  Consent,  Request,  Or Even Presence,  Of A

Parliament. Not Only Were Many Formal Statutes Passed Without

Any Mention Of The Consent Or Advice Of Parliament,  But A Simple

Order Of The King In Council,  Or A Simple Proclamation,  Writ,  Or

Letter Under Seal,  Issued By His Command,  Had The Same Force As

What Coke Calls "An Act Of Parliament." And This Practice

Continued,  To A Considerable Extent At Least,  Down To Coke's Own

Time.

 

The Kings Were Always In The Habit Of Consulting Their

Parliaments,  More Or Less,  In Regard To Matters Of Legislation,  

Not Because Their Consent Was Constitutionally Necessary,  But In

Order To Make Influence In Favor Of Their Laws,  And Thus Induce

The People To Observe Them,  And The Juries To Enforce Them.

The General Duties Of The Ancient Parliaments Were Not

Legislative,  But Judicial,  As Will Be Shown More Fully Hereafter.

The People Were Not Represented In The Parliaments At The Time Of

Magna Carta,  But Only The Archbishops,  Bishops,  Earls,  Barons,

And Knights; So That Little Or Nothing Would Have Been Gained For

Liberty By Coke's Idea That Parliament Had A Legislative Power.

He Would Only Have Substituted An Aristocracy For A King. Even

After The Commons Were Represented In Parliament,  They For Some

Centuries Appeared Only As Petitioners,  Except In The Matter Of

Taxation,  When Their Consent Was Asked. And Almost The Only

Source Of Their Influence On Legislation Was This: That They

Would Sometimes Refuse Their Consent To The Taxation,  Unless The

King Would Pass Such Laws As They Petitioned For; Or,  As Would

Seem To Have Been Much More Frequently The Case,  Unless He Would

Abolish Such Laws And Practices As They Remonstrated Against.

The Influence,  Or Power Of Parliament,  And Especially Of The

Commons,  In The General Legislation Of The Country,  Was A Thing

Of Slow Growth,  Having Its Origin In A Device Of The King To Get

Money Contrary To Law,  (As Will Be Seen In The Next Volume,) And

Not At All A Part Of The Constitution Of The Kingdom,  Nor Having

Its Foundation In The Consent Of The People. The Power,  As At

Present Exercised,  Was Not Fully Established Until 1688,  (Near

Five Hundred Years After Magna Carta,) When The House Of

Commons (Falsely So Called) Had Acquired Such Influence As The

Representative,  Not Of The People,  But Of The Wealth,  Of The

Nation,  That They Compelled,  The King To Discard The Oath Fixed

By The Constitution Of The Kingdom; (Which Oath Has Been Already

Given In A Former Chapter,  [5] And Was,  In Substance,  To Preserve

And Execute The Common Law,  The Law Of The Land,    Or,  In The

Words Of The Oath,  "The Just Laws And Customs Which The Common

People Had Chosen;") And To Swear That He Would "Govern The

People Of This Kingdom Of England,  And The Dominions Thereto

Belonging,  Accordingto The Statutes In Parliament Agreed On,  And

The Laws And Customs Of The Same." [6]

 

The Passage And Enforcement Of This Statute,  And The Assumption

Chapter 11 (Authority Of Magna Carta) Pg 173

Of This Oath By The King,  Were Plain Violations Of The English

Constitution,  Inasmuch As They Abolished,  So Far As Such An Oath

Could Abolish,  The Legislative Power Of The King,  And Also "Those

Just Laws And Customs Which The Common People (Through Their

Juries) Had Chosen," And Substituted The Will Of Parliament In

Their Stead.

 

Coke Was A Great Advocate For The Legislative Power Of

Parliament,  As A Means Of Restraining The Power Of The King. As

He Denied All Power To Juries To Decide Upon The Obligation Of

Laws,  And As He Held That The Legislative Power Was "So

Transcendent And Absolute As (That) It Cannot Be Confined,  Either

For Causes Or Persons,  Within Any Bounds," [7] He Was Perhaps

Honest In Holding That It Was Safer To Trust This Terrific Power

In The Hands Of Parliament,  Than In The Hands Of The King. His

Error Consisted In Holding That Either The King Or Parliament Had

Any Such Power,  Or That They Had Any Power At All To Pass Laws

That Should Be Binding Upon A Jury.

 

These Declarations Of Coke,  That The Charter Was Confirmed By

Thirty-Two "Acts Of Parliament," Have A Mischievous Bearing In

Another Respect. They Tend To Weaken The Authority Of The

Charter,  By Conveying The Impression That The Charter Itself

Might Be Abolished By "Act Of Parliament." Coke Himself Admits

That It Could Not Be Revoked Or Rescinded By The King; For He

Says,  "All Pretence Of Prerogative Against Magna Carta Is Taken

Away." (2 Inst.,  36.)

 

He Knew Perfectly Well,  And The Whole English Nation Knew,  That

The King Could Not Lawfully Infringe Magna Carta. Magna Carta,

Therefore,  Made It Impossible That Absolute Power Could Ever Be

Practically Established In England,  In The Hands Of The King.

Hence,  As Coke Was An Advocate For Absolute Power,    That Is,  For

A Legislative Power "So Transcendent And Absolute As (That) It

Cannot,  Be Confined,  Either For Causes Or Persons,  Within Any

Bounds,"   There Was No Alternative For Him But To Vest This

Absolute Power In Parliament. Had He Not Vested It In Parliament,

He Would Have Been Obliged To Abjure It Altogether,  And To

Confess That The People,  Through Their Juries,  Had The Right To

Judge Of The Obligation Of All Legislation Whatsoever; In Other

Words,  That They Had The Right To Confine The Government Within

The Limits Of "Those Just Laws And Customs Which The Common

People (Acting As Jurors) Had Chosen." True To His Instincts,  As

A Judge,  And As A Tyrant,  He Assumed That This Absolute Power Was

Vested In The Hands Of Parliament.

 

But The Truth Was That,  As By The English Constitution Parliament

Had No Authority At All For General Legislation,  It Could No More

Confirm,  Than It Could Abolish,  Magna Carta.

 

These Thirty-Two Confirmations Of Magna Carta,  Which Coke

Speaks Of As "Acts Of Parliament," Were Merely Acts Of The King. The

Parliaments,  Indeed,  By Refusing To Grant Him Money,  Except,  On

That Condition,  And Otherwise,  Had Contributed To Oblige Him To

Chapter 11 (Authority Of Magna Carta) Pg 174

Make The Confirmations; Just As They Had Helped To Oblige Him By

Arms To Grant The Charter In The First Place. But The Confirmations

Themselves Were Nevertheless Constitutionally,  As Well As Formally, 

The Acts Of The King Alone.

 

[5] See Page 103.

 

[6]St. 1.William And Mary,  Ch. 6,  (1688)

 

[7]4. Inst.,  36.

 

[8] Under The Head Of "John."

 

[9] 4 Blackstone,  849-50.

 

[10] 3 Blackstone,  379.

 

[11] Hume,  Ch. 2.

 

[12] Page 203,  5th Edition,  1721.

 

Chapter 12 (Limitations Imposed Upon The Majority By The Trial By Jury Pg 175

The Principal Objection,  That Will Be Made To The Doctrine Of

This Essay,  Is,  That Under It,  A Jury Would Paralyze The Power Of

The Majority,  And Veto All Legislation That Was Not In Accordance

With The Will Of The Whole,  Or Nearly The Whole,  People.

 

The Answer To This Objection Is,  That The Limitation,  Which Would

Be Thus Imposed Upon The  Legislative Power,  (Whether That Power

Be Vested In The Majority,  Or Minority,  Of The People,) Is The

Crowning Merit Of The Trial By Jury. It Has Other Merits; But,

Though Important In Themselves,  They Are Utterly Insignificant

And Worthless In Comparison With This.

 

It Is This Power Of Vetoing All Partial And Oppressive

Legislation,  And Of Restricting The Government To The Maintenance

Of Such Laws As The Whole,  Or Substantially The Whole,  People Are

Agreed In,  That Makes The Trial By Jury "The Palladium Of

Liberty." Without This Power It Would Never Have Deserved That

Name.

 

The Will,  Or The Pretended Will,  Of The Majority,  Is The Last

Lurking Place Of Tyranny At The Present Day. The Dogma,  That

Certain Individuals And Families Have A Divine Appointment To

Govern The Rest Of Mankind,  Is Fast Giving Place To The One That

The Larger Number Have A Right To Govern The Smaller; A Dogma,

Which May,  Or May Not,  Be Less Oppressive In Its Practical

Operation,  But Which Certainly Is No Less False Or Tyrannical In

Chapter 12 (Limitations Imposed Upon The Majority By The Trial By Jury) Pg 176

Principle,  Than The One It Is So Rapidly Supplanting. Obviously

There Is Nothing In The Nature Of Majorities,  That Insures

Justice At Their Hands. They Have The Same Passions As

Minorities,  And They Have No Qualities Whatever That Should Be

Expected To Prevent Them From Practising The Same Tyranny As

Minorities,  If They Think It Will Be For Their Interest To Do So.

 

There Is No Particle Of Truth In The Notion That The Majority

Have A Right To Rule,  Or To Exercise Arbitrary Power Over,  The

Minority,  Simply Because The Former Are More Numerous Than The

Latter. Two Men Have No More Natural Right To Rule One,  Than One

Has To Rule Two. Any Single Man,  Or Any Body Of Men,  Many Or Few,

Have A Natural Right To Maintain Justice For Themselves,  And For

Any Others Who May Need Their Assistance Against The Injustice Of

Any And All Other Men,  Without Regard To Their Numbers; And

Majorities Have No Right To Do Any More Than This. The Relative

Numbers Of The Opposing Parties Have Nothing To Do With The

Question Of Right. And No More Tyrannical Principle Was Ever

Avowed,  Than That The Will Of The Majority Ought To Have The

Force Of Law,  Without Regard To Its Justice; Or,  What Is The Same

Thing,  That The Will Of The Majority Ought Always To Be Presumed

To Be In Accordance With Justice. Such A Doctrine Is Only Another

Form Of The Doctrine That Might Makes Right.

 

When Two Men Meet One Upon The Highway,  Or In The Wilderness,

Have They A Right To Dispose Of His Life,  Liberty,  Or Property At

Their Pleasure,  Simply Because They Are The More Numerous Party?

Or Is He Bound To Submit To Lose His Life,  Liberty,  Or Property,

If They Demand It,  Merely Because He Is The Less Numerous Party?

Or,  Because They Are More Numerous Than He,  Is He Bound To

Presume That They Are Governed Only By Superior Wisdom,  And The

Principles Of Justice,  And By No Selfish Passion That Can Lead

Them To Do Him A Wrong? Yet This Is The Principle,  Which It Is

Claimed Should Govern Men In All Their Civil Relations To Each

Other. Mankind Fall In Company With Each Other On The Highway Or

In The Wilderness Of Life,  And It Is Claimed That The More

Numerous Party,  Simply By Virtue Of Their Superior Numbers,  Have

The Right Arbitrarily To Dispose Of The Life,  Liberty,  And

Property Of The Minority; And That The Minority Are Bound,  By

Reason Of Their Inferior Numbers,  To Practise Abject Submission,

And Consent To Hold Their Natural Rights,   Any,  All,  Or None,  As

The Case May Be,   At The Mere Will And Pleasure Of The Majority;

As If All A Man's Natural Rights Expired,  Or Were Suspended By

The Operation Of A Paramount Law,  The Moment He Came Into The

Presence Of Superior Numbers.

 

If Such Be The True Nature Of The Relations Men Hold To Each

Other In This World,  It Puts An End To All Such Things As Crimes,

Unless They Be Perpetrated Upon Those Who Are Equal Or Superior,

In Number,  To The Actors. All Acts Committed Against Persons

Inferior In Number To The Aggressors,  Become But The Exercise At

Rightful Authority. And Consistency With Their Own Principles

Requires That All Governments,  Founded On The Will Of The

Majority,  Should Recognize This Plea As A Sufficient

Chapter 12 (Limitations Imposed Upon The Majority By The Trial By Jury) Pg 177

Justification For All Crimes Whatsoever.

 

If It Be Said That The Majority Should Be Allowed To Rule,  Not

Because They Are Stronger Than The Minority,  But Because Their

Superior Numbers Furnish A Probability That They Are In The

Right; One Answer Is,  That The Lives,  Liberties,  And Properties

Of Men Are Too Valuable To Them,  And The Natural Presumptions Are

Too Strong In Their Favor,  To Justify The Destruction Of Them By

Their Fellow-Men On A Mere Balancing Of Probabilities,  Or On Any

Ground Whatever Short Of Certainty Beyond A Reasonable Doubt.

This Last Is The Moral Rule Universally Recognized To Be Binding

Upon Single Individuals. And In The Forum Of Conscience The Same

Rule Is Equally Binding Upon Governments,  For Governments Are

Mere Associations Of Individuals. This Is The Rule On Which The

Trial By Jury Is Based. And It Is Plainly The Only Rule That

Ought To Induce A Man To Submit His Rights To The Adjudication Of

His Fellow-Men,  Or Dissuade Him From A Forcible Defence Of Them.

 

Another Answer Is,  That If Two Opposing Parties Could Be Supposed

To Have No Personal Interests Or Passions Involved,  To Warp Their

Judgments,  Or Corrupt Their Motives,  The Fact That One Of The

Parties Was More Numerous Than The Other,  (A Fact That Leaves The

Comparative Intellectual Competency Of The Two Parties Entirely

Out Of Consideration,) Might,  Perhaps,  Furnish A Slight,  But At

Best Only A Very Slight,  Probability That Such Party Was On The

Side Of Justice. But When It Is Considered That The Parties Are

Liable To Differ In Their Intellectual Capacities,  And That One,

Or The Other,  Or Both,  Are Undoubtedly Under The Influence Of

Such Passions As Rivalry,  Hatred,  Avarice,  And Ambition.

Passions That Are Nearly Certain To Pervert Their Judgments,  And

Very Likely To Corrupt Their Motives,   All Probabilities Founded

Upon A Mere Numerical Majority,  In One Party,  Or The Other,

Vanish At Once; And The Decision Of The Majority Becomes,  To All

Practical Purposes,  A Mere Decision Of Chance. And To Dispose Of

Men's Properties,  Liberties,  And Lives,  By The Mere Process Of

Enumerating Such Parties,  Is Not Only As Palpable Gambling As Was

Ever Practised,  But It Is Also The Most Atrocious That Was Ever

Practised,  Except In Matters Of Government. And Where

Government Is Instituted On This Principle,  (As In The United States,  For

Example,) The Nation Is At Once Converted Into One Great Gambling

Establishment; Where All The Rights Of Men Are The Stakes; A Few

Bold Bad Men Throw The Dice   (Dice Loaded With All The Hopes,

Fears,  Interests,  And Passions Which Rage In The Breasts Of

Ambitious And Desperate Men,)   And All The People,  From The

Interests They Have Depending,  Become Enlisted,  Excited,

Agitated,  And Generally Corrupted,  By The Hazards Of The Game.

 

The Trial By Jury Disavows The Majority Principle Altogether; And

Proceeds Upon The Ground That Every Man Should Be Presumed To

Be Entitled To Life,  Liberty,  And Such Property As He Has In His

Possession; And That The Government Should Lay Its Hand Upon None

Of Them,  (Except For The Purpose Of Bringing Them Before A

Tribunal For Adjudication,) Unless It Be First Ascertained.,

Chapter 12 (Limitations Imposed Upon The Majority By The Trial By Jury) Pg 178

Beyond A Reasonable Doubt,  In Every Individual Case,  That Justice

Requires It.

 

To Ascertain Whether There Be Such Reasonable Doubt,  It Takes

Twelve Men By Lot From The Whole Body Of Mature Men. If Any Of

These Twelve Are Proved To Be Under The Influence Of Any Special

Interest Or Passion,  That May Either Pervert Their Judgments,  Or

Corrupt Their Motives,  They Are Set Aside As Unsuitable For The

Performance Of A Duty Requiring Such Absolute Impartiality And

Integrity; And Others Substituted In Their Stead. When The Utmost

Practicable Impartiality Is Attained On The Part Of The Whole

Twelve,  They Are Sworn To The Observance Of Justice; And Their

Unanimous Concurrence Is Then Held To Be Necessary To Remove That

Reasonable Doubt,  Which,  Unremoved,  Would Forbid The

Government To Lay Its Hand On Its Victim.

 

Such Is The Caution Which The Trial By Jury Both Practises And

Inculcates,  Against The Violation Of Justice,  On The Part Of The

Government,  Towards The Humblest Individual,  In The Smallest

Matter Affecting His Civil Rights,  His Property,  Liberty,  Or

Life. And Such Is The Contrast,  Which The Trial By Jury Presents,

To That Gambler's And Robber's Rule,  That The Majority Have A

Right,  By Virtue Of Their Superior Numbers,  And Without Regard To

Justice,  To Dispose At Pleasure Of The Property And Persons Of

All Bodies Of Men Less Numerous Than Themselves.

 

The Difference,  In Short,  Between The Two Systems,  Is This. The

Trial By Jury Protects Person And Property,  Inviolate To Their

Possessors,  From The Hand Of The Law,  Unless Justice,  Beyond A

Reasonable Doubt,  Require Them To Be Taken. The Majority

Principle Takes Person And Property From Their Possessors,  At The

Mere Arbitrary Will Of A Majority,  Who Are Liable And Likely To

Be Influenced,  In Taking Them,  By Motives Of Oppression,  Avarice,

And Ambition.

 

If The Relative Numbers Of Opposing Parties Afforded Sufficient

Evidence Of The Comparative Justice Of Their Claims The

Government Should Carry The Principle Into Its Courts Of Justice;

And Instead Of Referring Controversies To Impartial And

Disinterested Men,   To Judges And Jurors,  Sworn To Do Justice,

And Bound Patiently To Hear And Weigh All The Evidence And

Arguments That Can Be Offered On Either Side,   It Should Simply

Count The Plaintiff's And Defendants In Each Case,  (Where There

Were More Than One Of Either,) And Then Give The Case To The

Majority; After Ample Opportunity Had Been Given To The

Plaintiffs And Defendants To Reason With,  Flatter,  Cheat,

Threaten,  And Bribe Each Other,  By Way Of Inducing Them To Change

Sides. Such A. Process Would Be Just As Rational In Courts Of

Justice,  As In Halls Of Legislation; For It Is Of No Importance

To A Man,  Who Has His Rights Taken From Him,  Whether It Be Done

By A Legislative Enactment,  Or A Judicial Decision.

 

In Legislation,  The People Are All Arranged As Plaintiff's And

Defendants In Their Own Causes; (Those Who Are In Favor Of A

Chapter 12 (Limitations Imposed Upon The Majority By The Trial By Jury) Pg 179

Particular Law,  Standing As Plaintiff's,  And Those Who Are

Opposed To The Same Law,  Standing As Defendants); And To Allow

These Causes To Be Decided By Majorities,  Is Plainly As Absurd As

It Would Be To Allow Judicial Decisions To Be Determined By The

Relative Number Of Plaintiffs And Defendants.

 

If This Mode Of Decision Were Introduced Into Courts Of Justice,

We Should See A Parallel,  And Only A Parallel,  To That System Of

Legislation Which We Witness Daily. We Should See Large Bodies Of

Men Conspiring To Bring Perfectly Groundless Suits,  Against Other

Bodies Of Men,  For Large Sums Of Money,  And To Carry Them By

Sheer Force Of Numbers; Just As We Now Continually See Large

Bodies Of Men Conspiring To Carry,  By Mere Force Of Numbers,  Some

Scheme Of Legislation That Will,  Directly Or Indirectly,  Take

Money Out Of Other Men's Pockets,  And Put It Into Their Own. And

We Should Also See Distinct Bodies Of Men,  Parties In Separate

Suits,  Combining And Agreeing All To Appear And Be Counted As

Plaintiffs Or Defendants In Each Other's Suits,  For The Purpose

Of Ekeing Out The Necessary Majority; Just As We Now See Distinct

Bodies Of Men,  Interested In Separate Schemes Of Ambition Or

Plunder,  Conspiring To Carry Through A Batch Of Legislative

Enactments,  That Shall Accomplish Their Several Purposes.

 

This System Of Combination And Conspiracy Would Go On,  Until At

Length Whole States And A Whole Nation Would Become Divided Into

Two Great Litigating Parties,  Each Party Composed Of Several

Smaller Bodies,  Having Their Separate Suits,  But All Confederating

For The Purpose Of Making Up The Necessary Majority In Each Case.

The Individuals Composing Each Of These Two Great Parties,  Would

At Length Become So Accustomed To Acting Together,  And So Well

Acquainted With Each Others' Schemes,  And So Mutually

Dependent Upon Each Others' Fidelity For Success,  That They Would

Become Organized As Permanent Associations; Bound Together By

That Kind Of Honor That Prevails Among Thieves; And Pledged By

All Their Interests,  Sympathies,  And Animosities,  To Mutual

Fidelity,  And To Unceasing Hostility To Their Opponents; And

Exerting All Their Arts And All Their Resources Of Threats,

Injuries,  Promises,  And Bribes,  To Drive Or Seduce From The Other

Party Enough To Enable Their Own To Retain Or Acquire Such A

Majority As Would Be Necessary To Gain Their Own Suits,  And

Defeat The Suits Of Their Opponents. All The Wealth And Talent Of

The Country Would Become Enlisted In The Service Of These Rival

Associations; And Both Would At Length Become So Compact,  So Well

Organized,  So Powerful,  And Yet Always So Much In Need Of

Recruits,  That A Private Person Would Be Nearly Or Quite Unable

To Obtain Justice In The Most Paltry Suit With His Neighbor,

Except On The Condition Of Joining One Of These Great Litigating

Associations,  Who Would Agree To Carry Through His Cause,  On

Condition Of His Assisting Them To Carry Through All The Others,

Good And Bad,  Which They Had Already Undertaken. If He Refused

This,  They Would Threaten To Make A Similar Offer To His

Antagonist,  And Suffer Their Whole Numbers To Be Counted Against

Him.

 

Chapter 12 (Limitations Imposed Upon The Majority By The Trial By Jury) Pg 180

Now This Picture Is No Caricature,  But A True And Honest

Likeness. And Such A System Of Administering Justice,  Would Be No

More False,  Absurd,  Or Atrocious,  Than That System Of Working By

Majorities,  Which Seeks To Accomplish,  By Legislation,  The Same

Ends Which,  In The Case Supposed,  Would Be Accomplished By

Judicial Decisions.

 

Again,  The Doctrine That The Minority Ought To Submit To The Will

Of The Majority,  Proceeds,  Not Upon The Principle That Government

Is Formed By Voluntary Association,  And For An Agreed Purpose,  On

The Part Of All Who Contribute To Its Support,  But Upon The

Presumption That All Government Must Be Practically A State Of

War And Plunder Between Opposing Parties; And That In Order To

Save Blood,  And Prevent Mutual Extermination,  The Parties Come To

An Agreement That They Will Count Their Respective Numbers

Periodically,  And The One Party Shall Then Be Permitted Quietly

To Rule And Plunder,  (Restrained Only By Their Own Discretion,)

And The Other Submit Quietly To Be Ruled And Plundered,  Until The

Time Of The Next Enumeration.

 

Such An Agreement May Possibly Be Wiser Than Unceasing And

Deadly Conflict; It Nevertheless Partakes Too Much Of The Ludicrous

To Deserve To Be Seriously Considered As An Expedient For The

Maintenance Of Civil Society. It Would Certainly Seem That

Mankind Might Agree Upon A Cessation Of Hostilities,  Upon More

Rational And Equitable Terms Than That Of Unconditional

Submission On The Part Of The Less Numerous Body. Unconditional

Submission Is Usually The Last Act Of One Who Confesses Himself

Subdued And Enslaved. How Any One Ever Came To Imagine That

Condition To Be One Of Freedom,  Has Never Been Explained. And As

For The System Being Adapted To The Maintenance Of Justice Among

Men,  It Is A Mystery That Any Human Mind Could Ever Have Been

Visited With An Insanity Wild Enough To Originate The Idea.

 

If It Be Said That Other Corporations,  Than Governments,

Surrender Their Affairs Into The Hands Of The Majority,  The

Answer Is,  That They Allow Majorities To Determine Only Trifling

Matters,  That Are In Their Nature Mere Questions Of Discretion,

And Where There Is No Natural Presumption Of Justice Or Right On

One Side Rather Than The Other. They Never Surrender To The

Majority The Power To Dispose Of; Or,  What Is Practically The

Same Thing,  To Determine,  The Rights Of Any Individual Member.

The Rights Of Every Member Are Determined By The Written

Compact,  To Which All The Members Have Voluntarily Agreed.

 

For Example. A Banking Corporation Allows A Majority To

Determine Such Questions Of Discretion As Whether The Note Of

A Or Of B Shall Be Discounted; Whether Notes Shall Be Discounted

On One,  Two,  Or Six Days In The Week; How Many Hours In A Day

Their Banking-House Shall Be Kept Open; How Many Clerks Shall

Be Employed; What Salaries They Shall Receive,  And Such Like

Matters,  Which Are In Their Nature Mere Subjects Of Discretion,

And Where There Are No Natural Presumptions Of Justice Or Right

In Favor Of One Course Over The Other. But No Banking Corporation

Chapter 12 (Limitations Imposed Upon The Majority By The Trial By Jury) Pg 181

Allows A Majority,  Or Any Other Number Of Its Members Less Than

The Whole,  To Divert The Funds Of The Corporation To Any Other

Purpose Than The One To Which Every Member Of The Corporation

Has Legally Agreed That They May Be Devoted; Nor To Take The Stock Of

One Member And Give It To Another; Nor To Distribute The

Dividends Among The Stockholders Otherwise Than To Each One The

Proportion Which He Has Agreed To Accept,  And All The Others Have

Agreed That He Shall Receive. Nor Does Any Banking Corporation

Allow A Majority To Impose Taxes Upon The Members For The

Payment Of The Corporate Expenses,  Except In Such Proportions As

Every Member Has Consented That They May Be Imposed. All These

Questions,  Involving The Rights Of The Members As Against Each

Other,  Are Fixed By The Articles Of The Association,   That Is,  By

The Agreement To Which Every Member Has Personally Assented.

 

What Is Also Specially To Be Noticed,  And What Constitutes A

Vital Difference Between The Banking Corporation And The

Political Corporation,  Or Government,  Is,  That In Case Of

Controversy Among The Members Of The Banking Corporation,  As To

The Rights Of Any Member,  The Question Is Determined,  Not By Any

Number,  Either Majority,  Or Minority,  Of The Corporation Itself,

But By Persons Out Of The Corporation; By Twelve Men Acting As

Jurors,  Or By Other Tribunals Of Justice,  Of Which No Member Of

The Corporation Is Allowed To Be A Part. But In The Case Of The

Political Corporation,  Controversies Among The Parties To It,  As

To The Rights Of Individual Members,  Must Of Necessity Be Settled

By Members Of The Corporation Itself,  Because There Are No

Persons Out Of The Corporation To Whom The Question Can Be

Referred.

 

Since,  Then,  All Questions As To The Rights Of The Members Of The

Political Corporation,  Must Be Determined By Members Of The

Corporation Itself,  The Trial By Jury Says That No Man's Rights, 

Neither His Right To His Life,  His Liberty,  Nor His Property, 

Shall Be Determined By Any Such Standard As The Mere Will And

Pleasure Of Majorities; But Only By The Unanimous Verdict Of A

Tribunal Fairly Representing The Whole People,   That Is,  A

Tribunal Of Twelve Men,  Taken At Random From The Whole Body,  And

Ascertained To Be As Impartial As The Nature Of The Case Will

Admit,  And Sworn To The Observance Of Justice. Such Is The

Difference In The Two Kinds Of Corporations; And The Custom Of

Managing By Majorities The Mere Discretionary Matters Of Business

Corporations,  (The Majority Having No Power To Determine The

Rights Of Any Member,) Furnishes No Analogy To The Practice,

Adopted By Political Corporations,  Of Disposing Of All The Rightsof

Their Members By The Arbitrary Will Of Majorities.

 

But Further. The Doctrine That The Majority Have A Right To Rule,

Proceeds Upon The Principle That Minorities Have No Rights In The

Government; For Certainly The Minority Cannot Be Said To Have Any

Rights In A Government,  So Long As The Majority Alone Determine

What Their Rights Shall Be. They Hold Everything,  Or Nothing,  As

The Case May Be,  At The Mere Will Of The Majority.

 

Chapter 12 (Limitations Imposed Upon The Majority By The Trial By Jury) Pg 182

It Is Indispensable To A "Free Government," (In The Political

Sense Of That Term,) That The Minority,  The Weaker Party,  Have A

Veto Upon The Acts Of The Majority. Political Liberty Is Liberty

For The Weaker Party In A Nation. It Is Only The Weaker Party

That Lose Their Liberties,  When A Government Becomes Oppressive.

The Stronger Party,  In All Governments,  Are Free By Virtue Of

Their Superior Strength. They Never Oppress Themselves.

 

Legislation Is The Work Of This Stronger Party; And If,  In

Addition To The Sole Power Of Legislating,  They Have The Sole

Power Of Determining What Legislation Shall Be Enforced,  They

Have All Power In Their Hands,  And The Weaker Party Are The

Subjects Of An Absolute Government.

 

Unless The Weaker Party Have A Veto,  Either Upon The Making,  Or

The Enforcement Of Laws,  They Have No Power Whatever In The

Government,  And Can Of Course Have No Liberties Except Such As

The Stronger Party,  In Their Arbitrary Discretion,  See Fit To

Permit Them To Enjoy.

 

In England And The United States,  The Trial By Jury Is The Only

Institution That Gives The Weaker Party Any Veto Upon The Power

Of The Stronger. Consequently It Is The Only Institution,  That

Gives Them Any Effective Voice In The Government,  Or Any Guaranty

Against Oppression.

 

Suffrage,  However Free,  Is Of No Avail For This Purpose; Because

The Suffrage Of The Minority Is Overborne By The Suffrage Of The

Majority,  And Is Thus Rendered Powerless For Purposes Of

Legislation. The Responsibility Of Officers Can Be Made Of No

Avail,  Because They Are Responsible Only To The Majority. The

Minority,  Therefore,  Are Wholly Without Rights In The Government,

Wholly At The Mercy Of The Majority,  Unless,  Through The Trial By

Jury,  They Have A Veto Upon Such Legislation As They Think

Unjust.

 

Government Is Established For The Protection Of The Weak Against

The Strong. This Is The Principal,  If Not The Sole,  Motive For

The Establishment Of All Legitimate Government. Laws,  That Are

Sufficient For The Protection Of The Weaker Party,  Are Of Course

Sufficient For The Protection Of The Stronger Party; Because The

Strong Can Certainly Need No More Protection Than The Weak. It

Is,  Therefore,  Right That The Weaker Party Should Be Represented

In The Tribunal Which Is Finally To Determine What Legislation

May Be Enforced; And That No Legislation Shall Be Enforced

Against Their Consent. They Being Presumed To Be Competent Judges

Of What Kind Of Legislation Makes For Their Safety,  And What For

Their Injury,  It Must Be Presumed That Any Legislation,  Which

They Object To Enforcing,  Tends To Their Oppression,  And Not To

Their Security.

 

There Is Still Another Reason Why The Weaker Party,  Or The

Minority,  Should Have A Veto Upon All Legislation Which They

Disapprove. That Reason Is,  That That Is The Only Means By Which

Chapter 12 (Limitations Imposed Upon The Majority By The Trial By Jury) Pg 183

The Government Can Be Kept Within The Limits Of The Contract,

Compact,  Or Constitution,  By Which The Whole People Agree To

Establish Government. If The Majority Were Allowed To Interpret

The Compact For Themselves,  And Enforce It According To Their Own

Interpretation,  They Would,  Of Course,  Make It Authorize Them To

Do Whatever They Wish To Do.

 

The Theory Of Free Government Is That It Is Formed By The

Voluntary Contract Of The People Individually With Each Other.

This Is The Theory,  (Although It Is Not,  As It Ought To Be,  The

Fact,) In All The Governments In The United States,  As Also In

The Government Of England. The Theory Assumes That Each Man,

Who Is A Party To The Government,  And Contributes To Its Support, 

Has Individually And Freely Consented To It. Otherwise The

Government Would Have No Right To Tax Him For Its Support,  

For Taxation Without Consent Is Robbery. This Theory,  Then, 

Necessarily Supposes That This Government,  Which Is Formed By

The Free Consent Of All,  Has No Powers Except Such As All The

Parties To It Have Individually Agreed That It Shall Have: And

Especially That It Has No Power To Pass Any Laws,  Except Such

As All The Parties Have Agreed That It May Pass.

 

This Theory Supposes That There May Be Certain Laws That Will Be

Beneficial To All,   So Beneficial That All Consent To Be Taxed

For Their Maintenance. For The Maintenance Of These Specific

Laws,  In Which All Are Interested,  All Associate. And They

Associate For The Maintenance Of Those Laws Only,  In Which Allare

Interested. It Would Be Absurd To Suppose That All Would

Associate,  And Consent To Be Taxed,  For Purposes Which Were

Beneficial Only To A Part; And Especially For Purposes That Were

Injurious To Any. A Government Of The Whole,  Therefore,  Can Have

No Powers Except Such As All The Parties Consent That It May

Have. It Can Do Nothing Except What All Have Consented That It

May Do. And If Any Portion Of The People,   No Matter How Large

Their Number,  If It Be Less Than The Whole,   Desire A Government

For Any Purposes Other Than Those That Are Common To All,  And

Desired By All,  They Must Form A Separate Association For Those

Purposes. They Have No Right,   By Perverting This Government Of

The Whole,  To The Accomplishment Of Purposes Desired Only By A

Part,    To Compel Any One To Contribute To Purposes That Are

Either Useless Or Injurious To Himself.

 

Such Being The Principles On Which The Government Is Formed,  The

Question Arises,  How Shall This Government,  Where Formed,  Be Kept

Within The Limits Of The Contract By Which It Was Established?

How Shall This Government,  Instituted By The Whole People,  Agreed

To By The Whole People,  Supported By The Contributions Of The

Whole People,  Be Confined To The Accomplishment Of Those

Purposes Alone,  Which The Whole People Desire? How Shall It Be

Preserved From Degeneration Into A Mere Government For The Benefit

Of A Part Only Of Those Who Established,  And Who Support It? How Shall

It Be Prevented From Even Injuring A Part Of Its Own Members,  For

The Aggrandizement Of The Rest? Its Laws Must Be,  (Or At Least

Now Are,) Passed,  And Most Of Its Other Acts Performed,  By Mere

Chapter 12 (Limitations Imposed Upon The Majority By The Trial By Jury) Pg 184

Agents,   Agents Chosen By A Part Of The People,  And Not By The

Whole. How Can These Agents Be Restrained From Seeking Their Own

Interests,  And The Interests Of Those Who Elected Them,  At The

Expense Of The Rights Of The Remainder Of The People,  By The

Passage And Enforcement Of Laws That Shall Be Partial,  Unequal,

And Unjust In Their Operation? That Is The Great Question. And

The Trial By Jury Answers It. And How Does The Trial By Jury

Answer It? It Answers It,  As Has Already Been Shown Throughout

This Volume,  By Saying That These Mere Agents And Attorneys,  Who

Are Chosen By A Part Only Of The People,  And Are Liable To Be

Influenced By Partial And Unequal Purposes,  Shall Not Have

Unlimited Authority In The Enactment And Enforcement Of Laws;

That They Shall Not Exercise All The Functions Of Government. It

Says That They Shall Never Exercise That Ultimate Power Of

Compelling Obedience To The Laws By Punishing For Disobedience,

Or Of Executing The Laws Against The Person Or Property Of Any

Man,  Without First Getting The Consent Of The People,  Through A

Tribunal That May Fairly Be Presumed To Represent The Whole,  Or

Substantially The Whole,  People. It Says That If The Power To

Make Laws,  And The Power Also To Enforce Them,  Were Committed To

These Agents,  They Would Have All Power,   Would Be Absolute

Masters Of The People,  And Could Deprive Them Of Their Rights At

Pleasure. It Says,  Therefore,  That The People Themselves Will

Hold A Veto Upon The Enforcement Of Any And Every Law,  Which

These Agents May Enact,  And That Whenever The Occasion Arises For

Them To Give Or Withhold Their Consent,   Inasmuch As The Whole

People Cannot Assemble,  Or Devote The Time And Attention

Necessary To The Investigation Of Each Case,   Twelve Of Their

Number Shall Be Taken By Lot,  Or Otherwise At Random,  From The

Whole Body; That They Shall Not Be Chosen By Majorities,  (The

Same Majorities That Elected The Agents Who Enacted The Laws To

Be Put In Issue,) Nor By Any Interested Or Suspected Party; That

They Shall Not Be Appointed By,  Or Be In Any Way Dependent Upon,

Those Who Enacted The Law; That Their Opinions,  Whether For Or

Against The Law That Is In Issue,  Shall Not Be Inquired Of

Beforehand; And That If These Twelve Men Give Their Consent To

The Enforcement Of The Law,  Their Consent Shall Stand For The

Consent Of The Whole.

 

This Is The Mode,  Which The Trial By Jury Provides,  For Keeping

The Government Within The Limits Designed By The Whole People,

Who Have Associated For Its Establishment. And It Is The Only

Mode,  Provided Either By The English Or American Constitutions,

For The Accomplishment Of That Object.

 

But It Will,  Perhaps,  Be Said That If The Minority Can Defeat The

Will Of The Majority,  Then The Minority Rule The Majority. But

This Is Not True In Any Unjust Sense. The Minority Enact No Laws

Of Their Own. They Simply Refuse Their Assent To Such Laws Of The

Majority As They Do Not Approve. The Minority Assume No Authority

Over The Majority; They Simply Defend Themselves. They Do Not

Interfere With The Right Of The Majority To Seek Their Own

Happiness In Their Own Way,  So Long As They (The Majority) Do Not

Interfere With The Minority. They Claim Simply Not To Be

Chapter 12 (Limitations Imposed Upon The Majority By The Trial By Jury) Pg 185

Oppressed,  And Not To Be Compelled To Assist In Doing Anything

Which They Do Not Approve. They Say To The Majority,  " We Will

Unite With You,  If You Desire It,  For The Accomplishment Of All

Those Purposes,  In Which We Have A Common Interest With You.

You Can Certainly Expect Us To Do Nothing More. If You Do Not Choose

To Associate With Us On Those Terms,  There Must Be Two Separate

Associations. You Must Associate For The Accomplishment Of Your

Purposes; We For The Accomplishment Of Ours."

 

In This Case,  The Minority Assume No Authority Over The Majority;

They Simply Refuse To Surrender Their Own Liberties Into The

Hands Of The Majority. They Propose A Union; But Decline

Submission. The Majority Are Still At Liberty To Refuse The

Connection,  And To Seek Their Own Happiness In Their Own Way,

Except That They Cannot Be Gratified In Their Desire To Become

Absolute Masters Of The Minority.

 

But,  It May Be Asked,  How Can The Minority Be Trusted To Enforce

Even Such Legislation As Is Equal And Just? The Answer Is,  That

They Are As Reliable For That Purpose As Are The Majority; They

Are As Much Presumed To Have Associated,  And Are As Likely To

Have Associated,  For That Object,  As Are The Majority; And They

Have As Much Interest In Such Legislation As Have The Majority.

They Have Even More Interest In It; For,  Being The Weaker Party,

They Must Rely On It For Their Security,    Having No Other

Security On Which They Can Rely. Hence Their Consent To The

Establishment Of Government,  And To The Taxation Required For Its

Support,  Is Presumed,  (Although It Ought Not To Be Presumed,)

Without Any Express Consent Being Given. This Presumption Of

Their Consent To Be Taxed For The Maintenance Of Laws,  Would Be

Absurd,  If They Could Not Themselves Be Trusted To Act In Good

Faith In Enforcing Those Laws. And Hence They Cannot Be Presumed

To Have Consented To Be Taxed For The Maintenance Of Any Laws,

Except Such As They Are Themselves Ready To Aid In Enforcing. It

Is Therefore Unjust To Tax Them,  Unless They Are Eligible To

Seats In A Jury,  With Power To Judge Of The Justice Of The Laws.

Taxing Them For The Support Of The Laws,  On The Assumption That

They Are In Favor Of The Laws,  And At The Same Time Refusing Them

The Right,  As Jurors,  To Judge Of The Justice Of The Laws,  On The

Assumption That They Are Opposed To The Laws,  Are Flat

Contradictions.

 

But,  It Will Be Asked,  What Motive Have The Majority,  When They

Have All Power In Their Own Hands,  To Submit Their Will To The

Veto Of The Minority?

 

One Answer Is,  That They Have The Motive Of Justice. It Would Be

Unjust To Compel The Minority To Contribute,  By Taxation,  To The

Support Of Any Laws Which They Did Not Approve.

 

Another Answer Is,  That If The Stronger Party Wish To Use Their

Power Only For Purposes Of Justice,  They Have No Occasion To Fear

The Veto Of The Weaker Party; For The Latter Have As Strong

Motives For The Maintenance Of Just Government,  As Have The

Chapter 12 (Limitations Imposed Upon The Majority By The Trial By Jury) Pg 186

Former.

 

Another Answer Is,  That If The Stronger Party Use Their Power

Unjustly,  They Will Hold It By An Uncertain Tenure,  Especially In

A Community Where Knowledge Is Diffused; For Knowledge Will

Enable The Weaker Party To Make Itself In Time The Stronger

Party. It Also Enables The Weaker Party,  Even While It Remains

The Weaker Party,  Perpetually To Annoy,  Alarm,  And Injure Their

Oppressors. Unjust Power,   Or Rather Power That Is Grossly

Unjust,  And That Is Known To Be So By The Minority,    Can Be

Sustained Only At The Expense Of Standing Armies,  And All The

Other Machinery Of Force; For The Oppressed Party Are Always

Ready To Risk Their Lives For Purposes Of Vengeance,  And The

Acquisition Of Their Rights,  Whenever There Is Any Tolerable

Chance Of Success. Peace,  Safety,  And Quiet For All,  Can Be

Enjoyed Only Under Laws That Obtain The Consent Of All. Hence

Tyrants Frequently Yield To The Demands Of Justice From Those

Weaker Than Themselves,  As A Means Of Buying Peace And Safety.

 

Still Another Answer Is,  That Those Who Are In The Majority On

One Law,  Will Be In The Minority On Another. All,  Therefore,  Need

The Benefit Of The Veto,  At Some Time Or Other,  To Protect

Themselves From Injustice.

 

That The Limits,  Within Which Legislation Would,  By This Process,

Be Confined,  Would Be Exceedingly Narrow,  In Comparison With

Those It At Present Occupies,  There Can Be No Doubt. All

Monopolies,  All Special Privileges,  All Sumptuary Laws,  All

Restraints Upon Any Traffic,  Bargain,  Or Contract,  That Was

Naturally Lawful,  [1] All Restraints Upon Men's Natural Rights,

The Whole Catalogue Of Mala Prohibita,  And All Taxation To Which

The Taxed Parties Had Not Individually,  Severally,  And Freely

Consented,  Would Be At An End; Because All Such Legislation

Implies A Violation Of The Rights Of A Greater Or Less Minority.

This Minority Would Disregard,  Trample Upon,  Or Resist,  The

Execution Of Such Legislation,  And Then Throw Themselves Upon A

Jury Of The Whole People For Justification And Protection. In

This Way All Legislation Would Be Nullified,  Except The

Legislation Of That General Nature Which Impartially Protected

The Rights,  And Subserved The Interests,  Of All. The Only

Legislation That Could Be Sustained,  Would Probably Be Such As

Tended Directly To The Maintenance Of Justice And Liberty; Such,

For Example,  As Should Contribute To The Enforcement Of

Contracts,  The Protection Of Property,  And The Prevention And

Punishment Of Acts Intrinsically Criminal. In Short,  Government

In Practice Would Be Brought To The Necessity Of A Strict

Adherence To Natural Law,  And Natural Justice,  Instead Of Being,

As It Now Is,  A Great Battle,  In Which Avarice And Ambition Are

Constantly Fighting For And Obtaining Advantages Over The Natural

Rights Of Mankind.

 

[1] Such As Restraints Upon Banking,  Upon The Rates Of Interest,

Upon Traffic With Foreigners,  &E;.,  &C;.

 

Appendix Pg 187

Taxation

 

It Was A Principle Of The Common Law,  As It Is Of The Law Of

Nature,  And Of Common Sense,  That No Man Can Be Taxed Without

His Personal Consent. The Common Law Knew Nothing Of That System,

Which Now Prevails In England,  Of Assuming A Man's Own Consent

To Be Taxed,  Because Some Pretended Representative,  Whom He Never

Authorized To Act For Him,  Has Taken It Upon Himself To Consent

That He May Be Taxed. That Is One Of The Many Frauds On The

Common Law,  And The English Constitution,  Which Have Been

Introduced Since Magna Carta. Having Finally Established Itself

In England,  It Has Been Stupidly And Servilely Copied And

Submitted To In The United States.

 

 

 

 

 

If The Trial By Jury Were Reestablished,  The Common Law Principle

Of Taxation Would Be Reestablished With It; For It Is Not To Be

Supposed That Juries Would Enforce A Tax Upon An Individual Which

He Had Never Agreed To Pay. Taxation Without Consent Is As

Plainly Robbery,  When Enforcers Against One Man,  As When

Enforced Against Millions; And It Is Not To Be Imagined That Juries

Could Be Blind To So Self-Evident A Principle. Taking A Man's Money

Without His Consent,  Is Also As Much Robbery,  When It Is Done By

Millions Of Men,  Acting In Concert,  And Calling Themselves A

Government,  As When It Is Done By A Single Individual,  Acting On

His Own Responsibility,  And Calling Himself A Highwayman. Neither

The Numbers Engaged In The Act,  Nor The Different Characters They

Assume As A Cover For The Act,  Alter The Nature Of The Act

Itself.

 

If The Government Can Take A Man's Money Without His Consent,

There Is No Limit To The Additional Tyranny It May Practise Upon

Him; For,  With His Money,  It Can Hire Soldiers To Stand Over Him,

Keep Him In Subjection,  Plunder Him At Discretion,  And Kill Him

If He Resists. And Governments Always Will Do This,  As They

Everywhere And Always Have Done It,  Except Where The Common

Law Principle Has Been Established. It Is Therefore A First

Principle,  A Very Sine Qua Non Of Political Freedom,  That A Man

Can Be Taxed Only By His Personal Consent. And The Establishment

Of This Principle,  With Trial By Jury,  Insures Freedom Of Course;

Because:1. No Man Would Pay His Money Unless He Had First

Contracted For Such A Government As He Was Willing To Support;

And,2. Unless The Government Then Kept Itself Within The Terms Of

Its Contract,  Juries Would Not Enforce The Payment Of The Tax.

Besides,  The Agreement To Be Taxed Would Probably Be Entered Into

But For A Year At A Time. If,  In That Year,  The Government Proved

Itself Either Inefficient Or Tyrannical,  To Any Serious Degree,

The Contract Would Not Be Renewed. The Dissatisfied Parties,  If

Sufficiently Numerous For A New Organization,  Would Form

Appendix Pg 188

Themselves Into A Separate Association For Mutual Protection. If

Not Sufficiently Numerous For That Purpose,  Those Who Were

Conscientious Would Forego All Governmental Protection,  Rather

Than Contribute To The Support Of A Government Which They Deemed

Unjust.

 

All Legitimate Government Is A Mutual Insurance Company,

Voluntarily Agreed Upon By The Parties To It,  For The Protection

Of Their Rights Against Wrong-Doers. In Its Voluntary Character

It Is Precisely Similar To An Association For Mutual Protection

Against Fire Or Shipwreck. Before A Man Will Join An Association

For These Latter Purposes,  And Pay The Premium For Being Insured,

He Will,  If He Be A Man Of Sense,  Look At The Articles Of The

Association; See What The Company Promises To Do; What It Is

Likely To Do; And What Are The Rates Of Insurance. If He Be

Satisfied On All These Points,  He Will Become A Member,  Pay His

Premium For A Year,  And Then Hold The Company To Its Contract. If

The Conduct Of The Company Prove Unsatisfactory,  He Will Let His

Policy Expire At The End Of The Year For Which He Has Paid; Will

Decline To Pay Any Further Premiums,  And Either Seek Insurance

Elsewhere,  Or Take His Own Risk Without Any Insurance. And As Men

Act In The Insurance Of Their Ships And Dwellings,  They Would Act

In The Insurance Of Their Properties,  Liberties And Lives,  In The

Political Association,  Or Government.

 

The Political Insurance Company,  Or Government,  Have No More

Right,  In Nature Or Reason,  To Assume A Man's Consent To Be

Protected By Them,  And To Be Taxed For That Protection,  When He

Has Given No Actual Consent,  Than A Fire Or Marine Insurance

Company Have To Assume A Man's Consent To Be Protected By Them,

And To Pay The Premium,  When His Actual Consent Has Never Been

Given. To Take A Man's Property Without His Consent Is Robbery;

And To Assume His Consent,  Where No Actual Consent Is Given,

Makes The Taking None The Less Robbery. If It Did,  The Highwayman

Has The Same Right To Assume A Man's Consent To Part With His

Purse,  That Any Other Man,  Or Body Of Men,  Can Have. And His

Assumption Would Afford As Much Moral Justification For His

Robbery As Does A Like Assumption,  On The Part Of The Government,

For Taking A Man's Property Without His Consent. The Government's

Pretence Of Protecting Him,  As An Equivalent For The Taxation,

Affords No Justification. It Is For Himself To Decide Whether He

Desires Such Protection As The Government Offers Him. If He Do

Not Desire It,  Or Do Not Bargain For It,  The Government Has No

More Right Than Any Other Insurance Company To Impose It Upon

Him,  Or Make Him Pay For It. Trial By The Country,  And No

Taxation Without Consent,  Were The Two Pillars Of English

Liberty,  (When England Had Any Liberty,) And The First Principles

Of The Common Law. They Mutually Sustain Each Other; And

Neither Can Stand Without The Other. Without Both,  No People Have Any

Guaranty For Their Freedom; With Both,  No People Can Be Otherwise

Than Free. [1]

 

[1] Trial By The Country,  And No Taxation Without Consent,

Mutually Sustain Each Other,  And Can Be Sustained Only By Each

Appendix Pg 189

Other,  For These Reasons: 1. Juries Would Refuse To Enforce A Tax

Against A Man Who Had Never Agreed To Pay It. They Would Also

Protect Men In Forcibly Resisting The Collection Of Taxes To

Which They Had Never Consented. Otherwise The Jurors Would

Authorize The Government To Tax Themselves Without Their Consent, 

A Thing Which No Jury Would Be Likely To Do. In These Two Ways,

Then,  Trial By The Country Would Sustain The Principle Of No

Taxation Without Consent. 2. On The Other Hand,  The Principle Of

No Taxation Without Consent Would Sustain The Trial By The

Country,  Because Men In General Would Not Consent To Be Taxed For

The Support Of A Government Under Which Trial By The Country Was

Not Secured. Thus These Two Principles Mutually Sustain Each

Other.

 

But,  If Either Of These Principles Were Broken Down,  The Other

Would Fall With It,  And For These Reasons:If Trial By The Country

Were Broken Down,  The Principle Of No Taxation Without Consent

Would Fall With It,  Because The Government Would Then Be Able

Totax The People Without Their Consent,  Inasmuch As The Legal

Tribunals Would Be Mere Tools Of The Government,  And Would

Enforce Such Taxation,  And Punish Men For Resisting Such

Taxation,  As The Government Ordered.

 

On The Other Hand,  If The Principle Of No Taxation Without

Consent Were Broken Down,  Trial By The Country Would Fall With

It,  Because The Government,  If It Could Tax People Without Their

Consent,  Would,  Of Course,  Take Enough Of Their Money To Enable

It To Employ All The Force Necessary For Sustaining Its Own

Tribunals,  (In The Place Of Juries,) And Carrying Their Decrees

Into Execution.

 

By What Force,  Fraud,  And Conspiracy,  On The Part Of Kings,

Nobles,  And "A Few Wealthy Freeholders," These Pillars Have Been

Prostrated In England,  It Is Desired To Show More Fully In The

Next Volume,  If It Should Be Necessary.

 

 

 

 

Impressum

Tag der Veröffentlichung: 19.05.2014

Alle Rechte vorbehalten

Nächste Seite
Seite 1 /